• Bipolar Disorder
  • Therapy Center
  • When To See a Therapist
  • Types of Therapy
  • Best Online Therapy
  • Best Couples Therapy
  • Best Family Therapy
  • Managing Stress
  • Sleep and Dreaming
  • Understanding Emotions
  • Self-Improvement
  • Healthy Relationships
  • Student Resources
  • Personality Types
  • Guided Meditations
  • Verywell Mind Insights
  • 2024 Verywell Mind 25
  • Mental Health in the Classroom
  • Editorial Process
  • Meet Our Review Board
  • Crisis Support

Introspection and How It Is Used In Psychology Research

Kendra Cherry, MS, is a psychosocial rehabilitation specialist, psychology educator, and author of the "Everything Psychology Book."

introspection a research tool used by early

Amanda Tust is a fact-checker, researcher, and writer with a Master of Science in Journalism from Northwestern University's Medill School of Journalism.

introspection a research tool used by early

Thomas Barwick / Getty Images

  • Improvement Tips

Introspection is a psychological process that involves looking inward to examine one's own thoughts, emotions, judgments, and perceptions.

In psychology, introspection refers to the informal process of exploring one's own mental and emotional states. Although, historically, the term also applies to a more formalized process that was once used as an experimental technique . Learn more about uses for introspection, a few examples, and how to be more introspective.

Uses for Introspection

Introspection is important for several reasons. Among them are that it helps us engage in reflection, it assists with research, and it can be a valuable tool in mental health treatments involving psychotherapy.

One way to use introspection is for reflection, which involves consciously examining our internal psychological processes. When we reflect on our thoughts, emotions , and memories and examine what they mean, we are engaged in introspection.

Doing a reflective dive into our own psychology can help improve our levels of self-awareness. Being self-aware and gaining self-insight through the act of reflection is connected with higher levels of resilience and lower levels of stress . In this way, introspective reflection aids in personal growth.

Research Technique

The term introspection is also used to describe a research technique that was first developed by psychologist Wilhelm Wundt . Also known as experimental self-observation , Wundt's technique involved training people to carefully and objectively as possible analyze the content of their own thoughts.

Some historians suggest that introspection is not the most accurate term to refer to the methods that Wundt utilized. They contend that introspection implies a level of armchair soul-searching, but the methods that Wundt used were a much more highly controlled and rigid experimental technique.

In everyday use, introspection is a way of looking inward and examining one's internal thoughts and feelings. As a research tool, however, the process was much more controlled and structured.

Psychotherapy

Introspection can also be useful in psychotherapy sessions. When both practitioners and patients have the ability to be introspective, this aids in the development of the therapeutic relationship and can even affect treatment outcomes.

Engaging in introspection-based activities has been found beneficial for certain mental health conditions. For example, when people with depression engaged in emotional introspection, they were able to downregulate activity in their amygdala—an area of the brain associated with emotion regulation .

The term introspection can be used to describe both an informal reflection process and a more formalized experimental approach that was used early on in psychology's history. It's also used in psychotherapy sessions.

History of Introspection in Psychology

The process that Wundt used is what set his methods apart from casual introspection. In Wundt's lab, highly trained observers were presented with carefully controlled sensory events. Wundt believed that the observers needed to be in a state of high attention to the stimulus and in control of the situation. The observations were also repeated numerous times.

What was the purpose of these observations? Wundt believed that there were two key components that make up the contents of the human mind: sensations and feelings.

In order to understand the mind, Wundt believed that researchers needed to do more than simply identify its structure or elements. Instead, it was essential to look at the processes and activities that occur as people experience the world around them.

Wundt focused on making the introspection process as structured and precise as possible. Observers were highly trained and the process itself was rigid and highly controlled.

In many instances, respondents were asked to simply respond with a "yes" or "no." In some cases, observers pressed a telegraph key to give their response. The goal of this process was to make introspection as scientific as possible.

Edward Titchener , a student of Wundt's, also utilized this technique, although he has been accused of misrepresenting many of Wundt's original ideas. While Wundt was interested in looking at the conscious experience as a whole, Titchener instead focused on breaking down mental experiences into individual components and asked individuals to describe their mental experiences of events.

Benefits of Introspection

While introspection has fallen out of favor as a research technique, there are many potential benefits to this sort of self-reflection and self-analysis. Among them are:

  • Introspection can be a great source of personal knowledge , enabling you to better recognize and understand what you're thinking and feeling. This leads to a higher level of self-awareness, which can help promote mental health and increase our happiness .
  • The introspective process provides knowledge that is not possible in any other way ; there is no other process or approach that can provide this information. The only way to understand why you think or feel a certain way is through self-analysis or reflection.
  • Introspection can help people make connections between different experiences and their responses . For example, when engaging in self-reflection after a disagreement with your spouse, you may recognize that you responded defensively because you felt belittled or disrespected.
  • Introspection can improve our capacity for empathy . The more we understand ourselves, the easier it becomes to understand others. We're able to put ourselves "in their shoes" and empathize with how they may feel.
  • Introspection makes us stronger leaders . While some believe that being a good leader requires self-confidence, others contend that self-awareness is more important. People who understand themselves internally are able to lead others effectively, also often making better decisions .

Drawbacks of Introspection

Introspection is not a perfect process. So, it can come with a few drawbacks.

People often give greater weight to introspection about themselves while judging others on their outward behavior. This can result in bias without recognizing that a bias exists.

Even when their introspections don't provide useful or accurate information, people often remain confident that their interpretations are correct. This is a phenomenon known as the introspection illusion.

Cognitive biases are a good example of how people are often unaware of their own thoughts and biases. Despite this, people tend to be very confident in their introspections.

Bias can also exist during research studies using introspection. Because observers have to first be trained by researchers, there is always the possibility that this training introduces a bias to the results.

This bias can influence what they observe. Put another way, observers engaged in introspection might be thinking or feeling things because of how they have been influenced and trained by the experimenters.

Rumination involves obsessing over things or having them run through your mind over and over again. When trying to figure out the inner workings of the mind, one can end up ruminating on their "discoveries." This can have negative impacts mentally.

For example, in a study of adolescents with depression , researchers found that these teens tended to have maladaptive introspection with high levels of rumination, thus contributing to the worsening of their symptoms.

Subjectivity

While Wundt's experimental techniques did a great deal to advance psychology as a more scientific discipline, the introspective method had a number of notable limitations. One is that the process is subjective, making it impossible to examine or repeat the results.

When using introspection in research, different observers often provided significantly different responses to the exact same stimuli. Even the most highly trained observers were not consistent in their responses.

Limited Use

Another problem with introspection as a research technique is its limited use. Complex subjects such as learning, personality, mental disorders, and development are difficult or even impossible to study with this technique. This technique is also difficult to use with children and impossible to use with animals.

Because observers have to first be trained by researchers, there is always the possibility that this training introduces a bias to the results. Those engaged in introspection might be thinking or feeling things because of how they have been influenced and trained by the experimenters.

Examples of Introspection

Sometimes, seeing examples can help increase your understanding of a particular concept or idea. Some examples of introspection in everyday life include:

  • Engaging in mindfulness activities designed to increase self-awareness
  • Journaling your thoughts and feelings
  • Practicing meditation to better understand your inner self
  • Reflecting on a situation and how you feel about it
  • Talking with a mental health professional while exploring your mental and emotional states

How to Be Introspective

If you want to be more introspective, there are a few things you can do to assist with this.

  • Ask yourself "what" questions . When trying to figure out our thoughts and emotions, we often ask ourselves "why" we feel the way we do. However, research indicates that "what" questions are more effective for improving introspection. For instance, instead of asking why you feel sad, ask what makes you feel sad. This can help provide more insight into yourself internally.
  • Be more mindful . Introspection is a thoughtful exploration of what you're thinking and feeling at the moment. This requires being present, or more mindful. Greater mindfulness can be achieved in many different ways, some of which include journaling and meditation.
  • Expand your curiosity . Curiosity about your inner self can help you better understand your emotions, reflect on your past, and explore your identity and purpose. Get in touch with your curious side. With curiosity comes exploration, providing a clearer understanding of your psychological workings.
  • Spend some time alone, doing nothing . If the world is always busy around you, it can be difficult to quiet your mind enough to explore its inner workings. Make time regularly to spend some time alone, removing all distractions in your surroundings. This can help create an environment in which you're able to do a deeper dive into your psychological processes.

The use of introspection as a tool for looking inward is an important part of self-awareness and is even used in psychotherapy as a way to help clients gain insight into their own feelings and behavior.

While Wundt's efforts contributed a great deal to the development and advancement of experimental psychology, researchers now recognize the numerous limitations and pitfalls of using introspection as an experimental technique.

Cowden RG, Meyer-Weitz A. Self-reflection and self-insight predict resilience and stress in competitive tennis . Soc Behav Personal . 2016;44(7):1133-1149. doi:10.2224/sbp.2016.44.7.1133

Brock AC. The History of Introspection Revisited . In: Clegg JW, editor. Self-Observation in the Social Sciences . London: Taylor & Francis; 2018:25-44. doi:10.4324/9781351296809-3

Anders A. Introspection and psychotherapy . SFU Res Bull . 2019. doi:10.15135/2019.7.2.55-70

Herwig U, Opialla S, Cattapan K, Wetter TC, Jäncke L, Brühl A. Emotion introspection and regulation in depression . Psychiat Res: Neuroimag . 2018;277:7-13. doi:10.1016/j.psychresns.2018.04.008

Hergenhahn B. An Introduction to the History of Psychology .

Pal M. Promoting mental health through self awareness among the disabled and non-disabled students at higher education level in North 24 paraganas . Int Res J Modern Eng Tech Sci . 2021;3(1):51-53.

Jubraj B, Barnett NL, Grimes L, Varia S, Chater A, Auyeung V. Why we should understand the patient experience: clinical empathy and medicines otimisation . Int J Pharm Pract . 2016;24(5):367-370. doi:10.1111/ijpp.12268

Zhao X. On leadership and self-awareness . Wharton Magazine .

Lilienfeld SO, Basterfield C. Reflective practice in clinical psychology: Reflections from basic psychological science . Clin Psychol Sci Pract . 2020;27(4):e12352. doi:10.1111/cpsp.12352

Kaiser RH, Kang MS, Lew Y, et al. Abnormal frontinsular-default network dynamics in adolescent depression and rumination: a preliminary resting-state co-activation pattern analysis . Neuropsychopharmacol . 2019;44:1604-1612. doi:10.1038/s41386-019-0399-3

Eurich T. What self-awareness really is (and how to cultivate it) . Harvard Business Review .

Litman JA, Robinson OC, Demetre JD. Intrapersonal curiosity: Inquisitiveness about the inner self . Self Ident . 2017;16(2):231-250. doi:10.1080/15298868.2016.1255250

Brock, AC. The history of introspection revisited . In JW Clegg (Ed.), Self-Observation in the Social Sciences .

Pronin, E & Kugler, MB. Valuing thoughts, ignoring behavior: The introspection illusion as a source of the bias blind spot. J Exper Soc Psychol . 2007; 43(4): 565-578. doi:10.1016/j.jesp.2006.05.011.

By Kendra Cherry, MSEd Kendra Cherry, MS, is a psychosocial rehabilitation specialist, psychology educator, and author of the "Everything Psychology Book."

Introspection as the Basic Method in Psychological Science

  • First Online: 19 July 2017

Cite this chapter

introspection a research tool used by early

  • Jaan Valsiner 2  

Part of the book series: SpringerBriefs in Psychology ((BRIEFSTHEORET))

1418 Accesses

The primary method of psychology needs to be introspection. Yet any introspective evidence, to be of value to science, needs to be explicated into the public domain—“shared” between people and generalized from scientific knowledge creation. In this chapter I outline the original Wurzburg method of Karl Buhler and its transformation by Brady Wagoner. Analysis of the rating scales is included.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Compare two rating tasks: (1) Object = MOTHER , end points in scale “ GOOD ”___“ BAD ”, and (2) Object = MOTHER , end points in scale “ POTATO ”_____.“ CELLPHONE ” No. (1) is usual in psychology, and no. (2) is blatantly weird. Yet even the weird version is—at the level of a person’s affective abstraction—answerable (see processes of symbol formation in Werner and Kaplan 1963 ).

Abbey, E., & Diriwächter, R. (Eds.). (2008). Innovating genesis: Microgenesis and the constructive mind in action . Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishers.

Google Scholar  

Brentano, F. (1874). Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkte . Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.

Brock, A. (1991). Imageless thought or stimulus error? The social construction of private experiences. In W. R. Woodward & R. S. Cohen (Eds.), World views and scientific discipline formation (pp. 97–106). Dordrecht: Kluwerr.

Chapter   Google Scholar  

Bühler, K. (1951). On thought connections. In D. Rapaport (Ed.), Organization and pathology of thought (pp. 39–57). New York: Columbia University Press [partial translation of Bühler’s original published in 1908].

Burkart, T. (2010). Qualitatives Experiment. In G. Mey & K. Mruck (Eds.), Handbuch qualitative Forschung in der Psychologie (pp. 254–262). VS Verlag: Wiesbaden.

Burkart, T., & Weggen, J. (2015). Dialogic introspection: A method for exploring emotions in everyday life and experimental contexts. In H. Flam & J. Kleres (Eds.), Methods of exploring emotions (pp. 101–111). London: Routledge.

Burkart, T., Kleining, G., & Witt, H. (2010). Dialogische Introspektion . Wiesbaden: VS Verlag.

Book   Google Scholar  

Diriwächter, R. (2009). Idiographic microgenesis: Re-visiting the experimental tradition of Aktualgenese. In J. Valsiner, P. Molenaar, M. Lyra, & N. Chaudhary (Eds.), Dynamic process methodology in the social and developmental sciences (pp. 319–352). New York: Springer.

Ericsson, K. A., & Simon, H. (1993). Protocol analysis: Verbal reports as data (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Humphrey, G. (1951). Thinking . London: Methuen.

Kleining, G. (2010). Erleben eines Bahnhofs. In T. Burkart, G. Kleining, & H. Witt (Eds.), Dialogische Introspektion (pp. 64–75). Wiesbaden: VS Verlag.

Sander, F. (1928). Experimentelle Ergebnisse der Gestaltpsychologie. In E. Becher (Ed.), Bericht über den X. Kongress für experimentelle Psychologie in Bonn (pp. 23–88). Jena: Gustav Fischer.

Simon, H. (2007). Karl Duncker and cognitive science. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Thinking in psychological science (pp. 3–16). New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.

Toomela, A., & Valsiner, J. (Eds.). (2010). Methodological thinking in psychology: 60 years gone astray? Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishers.

Valsiner, J. (2012). A guided science . New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction.

Wagoner, B. (2007). Overcoming psychology’s methodology: Finding synthesis beyond the American and German-Austrian division. IPBS: Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science, 41 (1), 66–74.

Wagoner, B. (2009). The experimental methodology of constructive microgenesis. In J. Valsiner, P. Molenaar, M. Lyra, & N. Chaudhary (Eds.), Dynamic process methodology in the social and developmental sciences (pp. 99–121). New York: Springer.

Wagoner, B. (2012). Culture in constructive remembering. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Oxford handbook of culture and psychology (pp. 1034–1054). New York: Oxford University Press.

Wagoner, B. (2017). The constructive mind . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Wagoner, B., & Valsiner, J. (2005). Rating tasks in psychology: From static ontology to dialogical synthesis of meaning. In A. Gülerce, A. Hofmeister, I. Staeuble, G. Saunders, & J. Kaye (Eds.), Contemporary theorizing in psychology: Global perspectives (pp. 197–213). Toronto: Captus Press.

Werner, H. (1956). Microgenesis and aphasia. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 52 , 347–353.

Article   Google Scholar  

Werner, H., & Kaplan, B. (1963). Symbol formation . New York: Wiley.

Witt, H. (2010). Introspektion. In G. Mey & K. Mruck (Eds.), Handbuch Qualitative Forschung in der Psychologie (pp. 491–505). Wiesbaden: VS Verlag.

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Department of Communication and Psychology, Aalborg University, Aalborg, Denmark

Jaan Valsiner

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Valsiner, J. (2017). Introspection as the Basic Method in Psychological Science. In: From Methodology to Methods in Human Psychology . SpringerBriefs in Psychology(). Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-61064-1_6

Download citation

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-61064-1_6

Published : 19 July 2017

Publisher Name : Springer, Cham

Print ISBN : 978-3-319-61063-4

Online ISBN : 978-3-319-61064-1

eBook Packages : Behavioral Science and Psychology Behavioral Science and Psychology (R0)

Share this chapter

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Publish with us

Policies and ethics

  • Find a journal
  • Track your research

Psychological Foundations

Early psychology—structuralism and functionalism, learning objectives.

  • Define structuralism and functionalism and the contributions of Wundt and James to the development of psychology

Psychology is a relatively young science with its experimental roots in the 19th century, compared, for example, to human physiology, which dates much earlier. As mentioned, anyone interested in exploring issues related to the mind generally did so in a philosophical context prior to the 19th century. Two men, working in the 19th century, are generally credited as being the founders of psychology as a science and academic discipline that was distinct from philosophy. Their names were Wilhelm Wundt and William James.

Wundt and Structuralism

Structuralism is one of the earliest schools of psychology, focused on understanding the conscious experience through introspection. It was introduced by Wilhelm Wundt and built upon by his student, Edward Titchener. Let’s review a brief history of how structuralism was developed by these two scholars.

Wilhelm Wundt (1832–1920) was a German scientist who was the first person to be referred to as a psychologist. His famous book entitled Principles of Physiological Psychology was published in 1873. Wundt viewed psychology as a scientific study of conscious experience, and he believed that the goal of psychology was to identify components of consciousness and how those components combined to result in our conscious experience. Wundt used introspection (he called it “internal perception”), a process by which someone examines their own conscious experience as objectively as possible, making the human mind like any other aspect of nature that a scientist observed. He believed in the notion of voluntarism—that people have free will and should know the intentions of a psychological experiment if they were participating (Danziger, 1980). Wundt considered his version experimental introspection; he used instruments such as those that measured reaction time. He also wrote  Volkerpsychologie  in 1904 in which he suggested that psychology should include the study of culture, as it involves the study of people.

Wundt’s version of introspection used only very specific experimental conditions in which an external stimulus was designed to produce a scientifically observable (repeatable) experience of the mind (Danziger, 1980). The first stringent requirement was the use of “trained” or practiced observers, who could immediately observe and report a reaction. The second requirement was the use of repeatable stimuli that always produced the same experience in the subject and allowed the subject to expect and thus be fully attentive to the inner reaction. These experimental requirements were put in place to eliminate “interpretation” in the reporting of internal experiences and to counter the argument that there is no way to know that an individual is observing their mind or consciousness accurately, since it cannot be seen by any other person.

Edward Titchener, one of his students, built upon Wundt’s ideas to develop the idea concept of  structuralism . Its focus was on the contents of mental processes rather than their function (Pickren & Rutherford, 2010). Wundt established his psychology laboratory at the University at Leipzig in 1879. In this laboratory, Wundt and his students conducted experiments on, for example, reaction times. A subject, sometimes in a room isolated from the scientist, would receive a stimulus such as a light, image, or sound. The subject’s reaction to the stimulus would be to push a button, and an apparatus would record the time to reaction. Wundt could measure reaction time to one-thousandth of a second (Nicolas & Ferrand, 1999). Experimental requirements of using trained observers and repeatable stimuli were put in place to eliminate “interpretation” of the reporting of internal experiences. However, despite the efforts to train individuals in the process of introspection, this process remained highly subjective, and there was very little agreement between individuals.

Photograph A shows Wilhelm Wundt. Photograph B shows Wundt and five other people gathered around a desk with equipment on top of it.

Figure 1 . (a) Wilhelm Wundt is credited as one of the founders of psychology. He created the first laboratory for psychological research. (b) This photo shows him seated and surrounded by fellow researchers and equipment in his laboratory in Germany.

Watch this video to learn more about the early history of psychology.

A drawing depicts William James.

Figure 2 . William James, shown here in a self-portrait, was the first American psychologist.

James and Functionalism

William James (1842–1910) was the first American psychologist who espoused a different perspective on how psychology should operate. James was introduced to Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection and accepted it as an explanation of an organism’s characteristics. Key to that theory is the idea that natural selection leads to organisms that are adapted to their environment, including their behavior. Adaptation means that a trait of an organism has a function for the survival and reproduction of the individual, because it has been naturally selected. As James saw it, psychology’s purpose was to study the function of behavior in the world, and as such, his perspective was known as functionalism , which is regarded as another early school of psychology.

Functionalism focused on how mental activities helped an organism fit into its environment. Functionalism has a second, more subtle meaning in that functionalists were more interested in the operation of the whole mind rather than of its individual parts, which were the focus of structuralism. Like Wundt, James believed that introspection could serve as one means by which someone might study mental activities, but James also relied on more objective measures, including the use of various recording devices, and examinations of concrete products of mental activities and of anatomy and physiology (Gordon, 1995).

  • Modification, adaptation, and original content. Provided by : Lumen Learning. License : CC BY: Attribution
  • The History of Psychology. Authored by : OpenStax College. Located at : https://openstax.org/books/psychology-2e/pages/1-2-history-of-psychology . License : CC BY: Attribution . License Terms : Download for free at https://openstax.org/books/psychology-2e/pages/1-introduction
  • Wundt and Structuralism. Provided by : OpenStax. Located at : https://openstax.org/books/psychology-2e/pages/1-2-history-of-psychology . License : CC BY: Attribution . License Terms : Access for free at https://openstax.org/books/psychology-2e/pages/1-introduction
  • Psychology 101 - Wundt & James: Structuralism & Functionalism - Vook. Provided by : VookInc's channel. Located at : https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=SW6nm69Z_IE . License : Other . License Terms : Standard YouTube License

Footer Logo Lumen Waymaker

Home

Search form

You are here.

introspection a research tool used by early

  • Structuralism: Introspection and the Awareness of Subjective Experience

introspection a research tool used by early

Wundt’s research in his laboratory in Liepzig focused on the nature of consciousness itself. Wundt and his students believed that it was possible to analyze the basic elements of the mind and to classify our conscious experiences scientifically. Wundt began the field known as structuralism, a school of psychology whose goal was to identify the basic elements or “structures” of psychological experience . Its goal was to create a “periodic table” of the “elements of sensations,” similar to the periodic table of elements that had recently been created in chemistry.

Structuralists used the method of introspection to attempt to create a map of the elements of consciousness. Introspection involves asking research participants to describe exactly what they experience as they work on mental tasks , such as viewing colors, reading a page in a book, or performing a math problem. A participant who is reading a book might report, for instance, that he saw some black and colored straight and curved marks on a white background. In other studies the structuralists used newly invented reaction time instruments to systematically assess not only what the participants were thinking but how long it took them to do so. Wundt discovered that it took people longer to report what sound they had just heard than to simply respond that they had heard the sound. These studies marked the first time researchers realized that there is a difference between the sensation of a stimulus and theperception of that stimulus, and the idea of using reaction times to study mental events has now become a mainstay of cognitive psychology.

Perhaps the best known of the structuralists was Edward Bradford Titchener (1867–1927). Titchener was a student of Wundt who came to the United States in the late 1800s and founded a laboratory at Cornell University. In his research using introspection, Titchener and his students claimed to have identified more than 40,000 sensations, including those relating to vision, hearing, and taste.

An important aspect of the structuralist approach was that it was rigorous and scientific. The research marked the beginning of psychology as a science, because it demonstrated that mental events could be quantified. But the structuralists also discovered the limitations of introspection. Even highly trained research participants were often unable to report on their subjective experiences. When the participants were asked to do simple math problems, they could easily do them, but they could not easily answer how they did them. Thus the structuralists were the first to realize the importance of unconscious processes—that many important aspects of human psychology occur outside our conscious awareness, and that psychologists cannot expect research participants to be able to accurately report on all of their experiences.

  • 22184 reads
  • Approach and Pedagogy
  • The Problem of Intuition Research Focus: Unconscious Preferences for the Letters of Our Own Name
  • Why Psychologists Rely on Empirical Methods
  • Levels of Explanation in Psychology
  • The Challenges of Studying Psychology KET TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Early Psychologists
  • Functionalism and Evolutionary Psychology
  • Psychodynamic Psychology
  • Behaviorism and the Question of Free Will Research Focus: Do We Have Free Will?
  • The Cognitive Approach and Cognitive Neuroscience The War of the Ghosts
  • Social-Cultural Psychology
  • The Many Disciplines of Psychology Psychology in Everyday Life: How to Effectively Learn and Remember KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Chapter Summary
  • The Scientific Method
  • Laws and Theories as Organizing Principles
  • The Research Hypothesis
  • Conducting Ethical Research Characteristics of an Ethical Research Project Using Human Participants
  • Ensuring That Research Is Ethical
  • Research With Animals APA Guidelines on Humane Care and Use of Animals in Research KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Descriptive Research: Assessing the Current State of Affairs
  • Correlational Research: Seeking Relationships Among Variables
  • Experimental Research: Understanding the Causes of Behavior Research Focus: Video Games and Aggression KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • You Can Be an Informed Consumer of Psychological Research Learning Objectives Threats to the Validity of Research Psychology in Everyday Life: Critically Evaluating the Validity of Websites KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Neurons Communicate Using Electricity and Chemicals Video Clip: The Electrochemical Action of the Neuron
  • Neurotransmitters: The Body’s Chemical Messengers KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • The Old Brain: Wired for Survival
  • The Cerebral Cortex Creates Consciousness and Thinking
  • Functions of the Cortex
  • The Brain Is Flexible: Neuroplasticity Research Focus: Identifying the Unique Functions of the Left and Right Hemispheres Using Split-Brain Patients Psychology in Everyday Life: Why Are Some People Left-Handed? KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Lesions Provide a Picture of What Is Missing
  • Recording Electrical Activity in the Brain
  • Peeking Inside the Brain: Neuroimaging Research Focus: Cyberostracism KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Electrical Control of Behavior: The Nervous System
  • The Body’s Chemicals Help Control Behavior: The Endocrine System KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Sensory Thresholds: What Can We Experience? Link
  • Measuring Sensation Research Focus: Influence without Awareness KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • The Sensing Eye and the Perceiving Visual Cortex
  • Perceiving Color
  • Perceiving Form
  • Perceiving Depth
  • Perceiving Motion Beta Effect and Phi Phenomenon KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Hearing Loss KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Experiencing Pain KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • How the Perceptual System Interprets the Environment Video Clip: The McGurk Effect Video Clip: Selective Attention
  • The Important Role of Expectations in Perception Psychology in Everyday Life: How Understanding Sensation and Perception Can Save Lives KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Sleep Stages: Moving Through the Night
  • Sleep Disorders: Problems in Sleeping
  • The Heavy Costs of Not Sleeping
  • Dreams and Dreaming KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Speeding Up the Brain With Stimulants: Caffeine, Nicotine, Cocaine, and Amphetamines
  • Slowing Down the Brain With Depressants: Alcohol, Barbiturates and Benzodiazepines, and Toxic Inhalants
  • Opioids: Opium, Morphine, Heroin, and Codeine
  • Hallucinogens: Cannabis, Mescaline, and LSD
  • Why We Use Psychoactive Drugs Research Focus: Risk Tolerance Predicts Cigarette Use KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Changing Behavior Through Suggestion: The Power of Hypnosis
  • Reducing Sensation to Alter Consciousness: Sensory Deprivation
  • Meditation Video Clip: Try Meditation Psychology in Everyday Life: The Need to Escape Everyday Consciousness KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • How the Environment Can Affect the Vulnerable Fetus KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • The Newborn Arrives With Many Behaviors Intact Research Focus: Using the Habituation Technique to Study What Infants Know
  • Cognitive Development During Childhood
  • Video Clip: Object Permanence
  • Social Development During Childhood
  • Knowing the Self: The Development of the Self-Concept
  • Video Clip: The Harlows’ Monkeys
  • Video Clip: The Strange Situation Research Focus: Using a Longitudinal Research Design to Assess the Stability of Attachment KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Physical Changes in Adolescence
  • Cognitive Development in Adolescence
  • Social Development in Adolescence
  • Developing Moral Reasoning: Kohlberg’s Theory
  • Video Clip: People Being Interviewed About Kohlberg’s Stages KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Physical and Cognitive Changes in Early and Middle Adulthood
  • Social Changes in Early and Middle Adulthood KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Cognitive Changes During Aging
  • Dementia and Alzheimer’s Disease
  • Social Changes During Aging: Retiring Effectively
  • Death, Dying, and Bereavement KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Pavlov Demonstrates Conditioning in Dogs
  • The Persistence and Extinction of Conditioning
  • The Role of Nature in Classical Conditioning KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • How Reinforcement and Punishment Influence Behavior: The Research of Thorndike and Skinner
  • Video Clip: Thorndike’s Puzzle Box
  • Creating Complex Behaviors Through Operant Conditioning KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Observational Learning: Learning by Watching
  • Video Clip: Bandura Discussing Clips From His Modeling Studies Research Focus: The Effects of Violent Video Games on Aggression KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Using Classical Conditioning in Advertising
  • Video Clip: Television Ads Psychology in Everyday Life: Operant Conditioning in the Classroom
  • Reinforcement in Social Dilemmas KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Video Clip: Kim Peek
  • Explicit Memory
  • Implicit Memory Research Focus: Priming Outside Awareness Influences Behavior
  • Stages of Memory: Sensory, Short-Term, and Long-Term Memory
  • Sensory Memory
  • Short-Term Memory KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Encoding and Storage: How Our Perceptions Become Memories Research Focus: Elaboration and Memory
  • Using the Contributions of Hermann Ebbinghaus to Improve Your Memory
  • The Structure of LTM: Categories, Prototypes, and Schemas
  • The Biology of Memory KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Source Monitoring: Did It Really Happen?
  • Schematic Processing: Distortions Based on Expectations
  • Misinformation Effects: How Information That Comes Later Can Distort Memory
  • Overconfidence
  • Heuristic Processing: Availability and Representativeness
  • Salience and Cognitive Accessibility
  • Counterfactual Thinking Psychology in Everyday Life: Cognitive Biases in the Real World KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • How We Talk (or Do Not Talk) about Intelligence How We Talk (or Do Not Talk) about Intelligence
  • General (g) Versus Specific (s) Intelligences
  • Measuring Intelligence: Standardization and the Intelligence Quotient
  • The Biology of Intelligence
  • Is Intelligence Nature or Nurture? Psychology in Everyday Life: Emotional Intelligence KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Extremes of Intelligence: Retardation and Giftedness
  • Extremely Low Intelligence
  • Extremely High Intelligence
  • Sex Differences in Intelligence
  • Racial Differences in Intelligence Research Focus: Stereotype Threat KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • The Components of Language Examples in Which Syntax Is Correct but the Interpretation Can Be Ambiguous
  • The Biology and Development of Language Research Focus: When Can We Best Learn Language? Testing the Critical Period Hypothesis
  • Learning Language
  • How Children Learn Language: Theories of Language Acquisition
  • Bilingualism and Cognitive Development
  • Can Animals Learn Language?
  • Video Clip: Language Recognition in Bonobos
  • Languageand Perception KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Captain Sullenberger Conquers His Emotions Captain Sullenberger Conquers His Emotions
  • Video Clip: The Basic Emotions
  • The Cannon-Bard and James-Lange Theories of Emotion Research Focus: Misattributing Arousal
  • Communicating Emotion KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • The Negative Effects of Stress
  • Stressors in Our Everyday Lives
  • Responses to Stress
  • Managing Stress
  • Emotion Regulation Research Focus: Emotion Regulation Takes Effort KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Finding Happiness Through Our Connections With Others
  • What Makes Us Happy? KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Eating: Healthy Choices Make Healthy Lives
  • Sex: The Most Important Human Behavior
  • The Experience of Sex
  • The Many Varieties of Sexual Behavior Psychology in Everyday Life: Regulating Emotions to Improve Our Health KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISE AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Identical Twins Reunited after 35 Years Identical Twins Reunited after 35 Years
  • Personality as Traits Example of a Trait Measure
  • Situational Influences on Personality
  • The MMPI and Projective Tests Psychology in Everyday Life: Leaders and Leadership KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Psychodynamic Theories of Personality: The Role of the Unconscious
  • Id, Ego, and Superego Research Focus: How the Fear of Death Causes Aggressive Behavior
  • Strengths and Limitations of Freudian and Neo-Freudian Approaches
  • Focusing on the Self: Humanism and Self-Actualization Research Focus: Self-Discrepancies, Anxiety, and Depression KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Studying Personality Using Behavioral Genetics
  • Studying Personality Using Molecular Genetics
  • Reviewing the Literature: Is Our Genetics Our Destiny? KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • When Minor Body Imperfections Lead to Suicide When Minor Body Imperfections Lead to Suicide
  • Defining Disorder Psychology in Everyday Life: Combating the Stigma of Abnormal Behavior
  • Diagnosing Disorder: The DSM
  • Diagnosis or Overdiagnosis? ADHD, Autistic Disorder, and Asperger’s Disorder
  • Attention-Deficit/Hyperactivity Disorder (ADHD)
  • Autistic Disorder and Asperger’s Disorder KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Generalized Anxiety Disorder
  • Panic Disorder
  • Obsessive-Compulsive Disorders
  • Posttraumatic Stress Disorder (PTSD)
  • Dissociative Disorders: Losing the Self to Avoid Anxiety
  • Dissociative Amnesia and Fugue
  • Dissociative Identity Disorder
  • Explaining Anxiety and Dissociation Disorders KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Dysthymia and Major Depressive Disorder
  • Bipolar Disorder
  • Explaining Mood Disorders Research Focus: Using Molecular Genetics to Unravel the Causes of Depression KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Symptoms of Schizophrenia
  • Explaining Schizophrenia KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISE AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Borderline Personality Disorder Research Focus: Affective and Cognitive Deficits in BPD
  • Antisocial Personality Disorder (APD) KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Somatoform and Factitious Disorders
  • Sexual Disorders
  • Disorders of Sexual Function
  • Gender Identity Disorder
  • Paraphilias KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Therapy on Four Legs Therapy on Four Legs
  • Psychodynamic Therapy Important Characteristics and Experiences in Psychoanalysis
  • Humanistic Therapies
  • Behavioral Aspects of CBT
  • Cognitive Aspects of CBT
  • Combination (Eclectic) Approaches to Therapy KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Drug Therapies
  • Using Stimulants to Treat ADHD
  • Antidepressant Medications
  • Antianxiety Medications
  • Antipsychotic Medications
  • Direct Brain Intervention Therapies KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Group, Couples, and Family Therapy
  • Self-Help Groups
  • Community Mental Health: Service and Prevention Some Risk Factors for Psychological Disorders Research Focus: The Implicit Association Test as a Behavioral Marker for Suicide KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISE AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Effectiveness of Psychological Therapy ResearchFocus:Meta-AnalyzingClinicalOutcomes
  • Effectiveness of Biomedical Therapies
  • Effectiveness of Social-CommunityApproaches KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Binge Drinking and the Death of a Homecoming Queen Binge Drinking and the Death of a Homecoming Queen
  • Perceiving Others
  • Forming Judgments on the Basis of Appearance: Stereotyping, Prejudice, and Discrimination Implicit Association Test Research Focus: Forming Judgments of People in Seconds
  • Close Relationships
  • Causal Attribution: Forming Judgments by Observing Behavior
  • Attitudes and Behavior KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Helping Others: Altruism Helps Create Harmonious Relationships
  • Why Are We Altruistic?
  • How the Presence of Others Can Reduce Helping
  • Video Clip: The Case of Kitty Genovese
  • Human Aggression: An Adaptive y et Potentially Damaging Behavior
  • The Ability to Aggress Is Part of Human Nature
  • Negative Experiences Increase Aggression
  • Viewing Violent Media Increases Aggression
  • Video Clip Research Focus: The Culture of Honor
  • Conformity and Obedience: How Social Influence Creates Social Norms
  • Do We Always Conform? KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISES AND CRITICAL THINKING
  • Working in Front of Others: Social Facilitation and Social Inhibition
  • Working Together in Groups Psychology in Everyday Life: Do Juries Make Good Decisions?
  • Using Groups Effectively KEY TAKEAWAYS EXERCISE AND CRITICAL THINKING
  •  Back Matter

This action cannot be undo.

Choose a delete action Empty this page Remove this page and its subpages

Content is out of sync. You must reload the page to continue.

New page type Book Topic Interactive Learning Content

  • Config Page
  • Add Page Before
  • Add Page After
  • Delete Page

HKMU

Psychologily

Introspection and How It Is Used In Psychology Research

Unlocking the Power of Introspection and How It Is Used In Psychology Research

Have you ever wondered what is introspection and how it is used in psychology research? If you’re interested in psychology research, you may have encountered the term “introspection.” Introspection is examining your thoughts, emotions, judgments, and perceptions inwardly. It’s a valuable tool in psychology research, as it allows researchers to gain insight into the mind’s inner workings.

Introspection has a long history in psychology, dating back to the early days of the field. While it’s not always considered a scientific method, it can be valuable for generating hypotheses and exploring new ideas. In recent years, there has been renewed interest in introspection as a research method, and many psychologists are now exploring its potential benefits and drawbacks.

In this article, we’ll examine introspection and how it is used in psychology research. We’ll explore its history, benefits, weaknesses, and some examples of how it has been used in study.

Historical Overview of Introspection

Introspection is a psychological process involving looking inward to examine one’s thoughts, emotions, judgments, and perceptions. The concept of introspection has a long history, dating back to ancient Greek philosophers such as Socrates and Plato. However, introspection as a scientific method of studying the mind emerged in the late 19th century.

A German psychologist, Wilhelm Wundt , is often credited with foundering modern psychology and inventing introspection as a research method. Wundt believed that psychology should be a science that studies the conscious experience of individuals. He used introspection to study the structure of the mind and the elements of consciousness.

Wundt’s approach to introspection involved careful observation and analysis of one’s own experiences. Participants in his experiments were asked to describe their own conscious experiences in detail, such as the sensations they felt when looking at a particular color or listening to a sound. Wundt believed that by studying the structure of consciousness, psychologists could better understand the workings of the mind.

Wundt’s approach to introspection was later criticized for its subjectivity and lack of reliability. However, his work paved the way for developing other methods of studying the mind, such as behaviorism and cognitive psychology. Today, introspection is still used as a research method in psychology. Still, it is usually combined with other ways, such as neuroimaging and behavioral observation, to understand the mind better.

Introspection in Modern Psychology

Introspection is a fundamental process in modern psychology that involves examining one’s own thoughts, emotions, judgments, and perceptions. The method of introspection is used in various areas of psychology, including cognitive and behavioral psychology. Here are some of the ways introspection is used in modern psychology.

Role in Cognitive Psychology

Cognitive psychology is a branch of psychology that focuses on the study of mental processes, including perception, attention, memory, and problem-solving. Introspection plays a crucial role in cognitive psychology, as it allows researchers to gain insight into the subjective experiences of individuals.

For example, in a study on attention, researchers may use introspection to ask participants to describe their experience of focusing on a particular task. This information can then be used to develop theories about how attention works and can be improved.

Influence on Behavioral Psychology

Behavioral psychology is a branch of psychology that focuses on studying behavior, including observable actions and responses to stimuli. While introspection is not as central to behavioral psychology as cognitive psychology, it still plays a role in understanding behavior.

For example, in a study on addiction, researchers may use introspection to ask participants to describe their experience of craving a particular substance. This information can then be used to develop interventions targeting the underlying psychological processes contributing to addiction.

Methods of Introspection

If you want to learn more about your internal psychological processes, introspection can be helpful. Here are some methods of introspection that you can use to gain more insight into your thoughts, emotions, and memories.

Self-Report

Self-report is a standard method of introspection that involves asking yourself questions about your thoughts, feelings, and behaviors. You can use self-reporting to gain more insight into your personality traits, values, and beliefs. For example, you might ask yourself questions like:

  • What are my biggest strengths and weaknesses?
  • What are my core values and beliefs?
  • What motivates me to do the things I do?

By answering these questions honestly, you can better understand your own psychology.

Diaries and Journals

Keeping a diary or journal is another effective method of introspection. By writing down your thoughts and feelings on a regular basis, you can gain more insight into your own psychology. You can use your diary or journal to reflect on your day-to-day experiences, explore your emotions, and identify patterns in your behavior. For example, you might write about:

  • What happened today that made me feel happy or sad?
  • What are some of the challenges I’m facing right now?
  • What are some of the things I’m grateful for in my life?

By regularly reflecting on your experiences in this way, you can gain a deeper understanding of your psychology.

Think-Aloud Protocols

Think-aloud protocols are a method of introspection that involves verbalizing your thoughts as you complete a task. This can be a helpful way to gain insight into your own cognitive processes. For example, use a think-aloud protocol to explore how you approach a problem-solving task. As you work through the study, you verbalize your thoughts, explaining why you’re making certain decisions and how you’re solving the problem.

Introspection and How It Is Used In Psychology Research

Advantages and Disadvantages of Introspection

Introspection is a useful tool in psychology research for gaining insight into one’s mental processes. However, like any method, it has both strengths and limitations.

Strengths of Introspection

One of the primary strengths of introspection is that it allows researchers to access private mental experiences that cannot be directly observed through other scientific methods. By examining their own thoughts, emotions, and perceptions, individuals can provide valuable data that can be used to develop theories and hypotheses about mental processes.

Additionally, introspection is a relatively easy and straightforward method that does not require extensive training or specialized equipment. This makes it accessible to a wide range of individuals, including those without a background in psychology.

Limitations of Introspection

Despite its strengths, introspection also has several limitations that must be considered. One primary end is that introspective reports may be biased or inaccurate due to various factors, including social desirability bias and difficulty accurately recalling past experiences.

Another limitation is that introspection is a subjective process influenced by various factors, including mood, motivation, and cognitive biases. Different individuals may provide additional reports of the same mental experience, making it difficult to draw definitive conclusions.

Introspection in Clinical Practice

Introspection is a valuable tool in clinical practice as it allows individuals to explore their thoughts, emotions, and behaviors in a safe and controlled environment. This process can help individuals gain insight into their mental health and make positive life changes. In this section, we will explore the therapeutic applications of introspection and provide case studies to illustrate its effectiveness.

Therapeutic Applications

Introspection is often used in psychotherapy to help individuals gain insight into their mental health. By exploring their thoughts, emotions, and behaviors, individuals can identify patterns contributing to their mental health issues. This process can help individuals develop coping strategies and make positive life changes.

One therapeutic application of introspection is cognitive-behavioral therapy (CBT). CBT is a type of therapy that focuses on changing negative thought patterns and behaviors. Introspection can be used in CBT to help individuals identify their negative thought patterns and replace them with more positive ones.

Another therapeutic application of introspection is psychodynamic therapy. Psychodynamic therapy is a type of therapy that focuses on exploring the unconscious mind and how it influences behavior. Introspection can be used in psychodynamic therapy to help individuals gain insight into their unconscious thoughts and behaviors.

Case Studies

Case studies can provide valuable insight into the effectiveness of introspection in clinical practice. Here are two examples:

  • Case Study 1:  Jane has been struggling with depression for several years. She has tried various treatments, but nothing seems to be working. Her therapist suggests that she try introspection to gain insight into her depression. Through introspection, Jane realizes that her depression is linked to negative self-talk. She works with her therapist to develop strategies to replace her negative self-talk with more positive self-talk. Over time, Jane’s depression improves.
  • Case Study 2:  John has been struggling with anxiety for several years. He has tried various treatments, but nothing seems to be working. His therapist suggests that he try introspection to gain insight into his anxiety. Through introspection, John realizes that his concern is linked to his fear of failure. He works with his therapist to develop strategies to overcome his fear of failure. Over time, John’s anxiety improves.

In both case studies, introspection was valuable in helping individuals gain insight into their mental health issues and make positive changes in their lives.

Introspection in Social and Cultural Context

Cultural considerations.

Regarding introspection, cultural differences can play a significant role in shaping how individuals perceive and reflect on their mental states. For instance, some cultures may emphasize group harmony and social conformity, which can make it more challenging for individuals to engage in introspection without feeling self-conscious or uncomfortable. In contrast, cultures prioritizing individualism may encourage individuals to explore their inner selves more freely.

Additionally, cultural differences can influence which aspects of the self an individual focuses on during introspection. For example, in some cultures, individuals may be more likely to reflect on their relationships with others or their roles within their communities, while in others, individuals may be more inclined to focus on their achievements or goals.

Social Implications

Introspection can also have important social implications, particularly in social psychology. For example, research has shown that social factors, such as the presence of others or the perceived expectations of others, can influence individuals’ introspective processes. Additionally, introspection can influence social behavior by shaping how individuals respond to social feedback or make decisions in social contexts.

One classic example of the social implications of introspection is the phenomenon of “self-serving bias,” where individuals are more likely to attribute their successes to internal factors (such as their abilities) and their failures to external factors (such as bad luck). This bias can have important implications for how individuals perceive themselves and their place within social groups.

Future of Introspection in Psychology Research

As the field of psychology continues to evolve, the role of introspection in research is likely to change as well. While introspection has been a valuable tool for exploring one’s mental and emotional states, it has limitations that may make it less useful in certain contexts.

One potential future use of introspection in psychology research is as a complement to other methods, such as physiological measures or behavioral observations. By combining multiple data sources, researchers can better understand the complex processes underlying psychological phenomena.

Another potential future direction for introspection in psychology research is the development of more structured and standardized methods for collecting and analyzing introspective data. This could involve using specific prompts or questions to guide participants’ introspection or the development of standardized rating scales to quantify the results.

It is also possible that advances in technology will allow for new ways of collecting and analyzing introspective data. For example, wearable devices that can track physiological responses may provide a more objective measure of participants’ internal experiences. Similarly, machine learning algorithms can identify patterns in introspective data that are not immediately apparent to human observers.

Frequently Asked Questions

What is the definition of introspection in psychology research.

Introspection is a psychological process involving looking inward to examine one’s thoughts, emotions, judgments, and perceptions. In psychology, introspection refers to the informal process of exploring one’s own mental and emotional states. It is a method of self-observation and self-reflection that can provide insights into one’s own experiences and mental processes.

How is introspection used in real-life examples?

Introspection is used in real-life examples, including therapy sessions, meditation practices, and self-help techniques. In therapy, clients may be asked to reflect on their thoughts and emotions to gain insight into their behavior and feelings. In meditation, practitioners may use introspection to observe their thoughts and emotions without judgment. Self-help techniques like journaling or self-reflection exercises can also involve introspection.

Who is the founder of introspection in psychology?

Wilhelm Wundt is often credited as the founder of introspection in psychology. He is known for his work in establishing psychology as a scientific discipline and for his use of introspection as a research method in his laboratory experiments.

What is the difference between introspection and self-reflection?

Introspection and self-reflection are often used interchangeably, but there is a subtle difference between the two. Introspection refers to the process of looking inward to examine one’s own thoughts and emotions. Self-reflection, however, involves thinking about one’s own experiences and behavior more generally, without necessarily looking at specific thoughts or feelings.

What is the role of introspection in psychological research?

Introspection can play a valuable role in psychological research by providing insights into subjective experiences and mental processes. It can be used to explore topics such as emotion, perception, and memory, and can provide a rich source of data for researchers. However, introspection has limitations, as it is subjective and can be influenced by factors such as bias and memory.

Can you provide an example of how introspection is used in psychological research?

One example of how introspection is used in psychological research is in emotion studies. Participants may be asked to reflect on their emotional experiences and report their thoughts and feelings during specific situations. This data can then be used to gain insights into the nature of emotions and how individuals experience them.

Leave a Comment Cancel reply

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

SEP logo

  • Table of Contents
  • New in this Archive
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Introspection

Introspection, as the term is used in contemporary philosophy of mind, is a means of learning about one's own currently ongoing, or perhaps very recently past, mental states or processes. You can, of course, learn about your own mind in the same way you learn about others' minds—by reading psychology texts, by observing facial expressions (in a mirror), by examining readouts of brain activity, by noting patterns of past behavior—but it's generally thought that you can also learn about your mind introspectively , in a way that no one else can. But what exactly is introspection? No simple characterization is widely accepted.

Introspection is a key concept in epistemology, since introspective knowledge is often thought to be particularly secure, maybe even immune to skeptical doubt. Introspective knowledge is also often held to be more immediate or direct than sensory knowledge. Both of these putative features of introspection have been cited in support of the idea that introspective knowledge can serve as a ground or foundation for other sorts of knowledge.

Introspection is also central to philosophy of mind, both as a process worth study in its own right and as a court of appeal for other claims about the mind. Philosophers of mind offer a variety of theories of the nature of introspection; and philosophical claims about consciousness, emotion, free will, personal identity, thought, belief, imagery, perception, and other mental phenomena are often thought to have introspective consequences or to be susceptible to introspective verification. For similar reasons, empirical psychologists too have discussed the accuracy of introspective judgments and the role of introspection in the science of the mind.

1.1 Necessary Features of an Introspective Process

1.2 the targets of introspection, 1.3 the products of introspection, 2.1.1 behavioral observation accounts, 2.1.2 theory theory accounts, 2.1.3 restrictions on parity, 2.2.1 simple monitoring accounts, 2.2.2 multi-process monitoring accounts, 2.3.1 self-fulfillment and containment, 2.3.2 self-shaping, 2.3.3 expressivism, 2.3.4 transparency, 2.4 introspective pluralism, 3.1 the rise of introspective psychology as a science, 3.2 early skepticism about introspective observation, 3.3 the decline of scientific introspection, 3.4 the re-emergence of scientific introspection, 4.1.1 varieties of perfection: infallibility, indubitability, incorrigibility, and self-intimation, 4.1.2 weaker guarantees, 4.1.3 privilege without guarantee, 4.2.1 of the causes of attitudes and behavior, 4.2.2 of attitudes, 4.2.3 of conscious experience, other internet resources, related entries, 1. general features of introspection.

Introspection is generally regarded as a process by means of which we learn about our own currently ongoing, or very recently past, mental states or processes. Not all such processes are introspective, however: Few would say that you have introspected if you learn that you're angry by seeing your facial expression in the mirror. However, it's unclear and contentious exactly what more is required for a process to qualify as introspective. A relatively restrictive account of introspection might require introspection to involve attention to and direct detection of one's ongoing mental states; but many philosophers think attention to or direct detection of mental states is impossible or at least not present in many paradigmatic instances of introspection.

For a process to qualify as “introspective” as the term is ordinarily used in contemporary philosophy of mind, it must minimally meet the following three conditions:

The mentality condition : Introspection is a process that generates, or is aimed at generating, knowledge, judgments, or beliefs about mental events, states, or processes, and not about affairs outside one's mind, at least not directly. In this respect, it is different from sensory processes that normally deliver information about outward events or about the non-mental aspects of the individual's body. The border between introspective and non-introspective knowledge can begin to seem blurry with respect to bodily self-knowledge such as proprioceptive knowledge about the position of one's limbs or nociceptive knowledge about one's pains. But it seems that in principle the introspective part of such processes, pertaining to judgments about one's mind—e.g., that one has the feeling as though one's arms were crossed or of toe-ishly located pain—can be distinguished from the non-introspective judgment that one's arms are in fact crossed or one's toe is being pinched.

The first-person condition : Introspection is a process that generates, or is aimed at generating, knowledge, judgments, or beliefs about one's own mind only and no one else's, at least not directly. Any process that in a similar manner generates knowledge of one's own and others' minds is by that token not an introspective process. (Some philosophers have contemplated peculiar or science fiction cases in which we might introspect the contents of others' minds directly—for example in telepathy or when two individuals' brains are directly wired together—but the proper interpretation of such cases is disputable see, e.g., Gertler 2000.)

The temporal proximity condition : Introspection is a process that generates knowledge, beliefs, or judgments about one's currently ongoing mental life only; or, alternatively (or perhaps in addition) immediately past (or even future) mental life, within a certain narrow temporal window (sometimes called the specious present; see the entry on the experience and perception of time ). You may know that you were thinking about Montaigne yesterday during your morning walk, but you cannot know that fact by current introspection alone—though perhaps you can know introspectively that you currently have a vivid memory of having thought about Montaigne. Likewise, you cannot know by introspection alone that you will feel depressed if your favored candidate loses the election in November—though perhaps you can know introspectively what your current attitude is toward the election or what emotion starts to rise in you when you consider the possible outcomes. Whether the target of introspection is best thought of as one's current mental life or one's immediately past mental life may depend on one's model of introspection: On self-detection models of introspection, according to which introspection is a causal process involving the detection of a mental state (see Section 2.2 below), it's natural to suppose that a brief lapse of time will transpire between the occurrence of the mental state that is the introspective target and the final introspective judgment about that state, which invites (but does not strictly imply) the idea that introspective judgments generally pertain to immediately past states. On self-shaping and self-fulfillment models of introspection, according to which introspective judgments create or embed the very state introspected (see Sections 2.3.1 and 2.3.2 below), it seems more natural to think that the target of introspection is one's current mental life or perhaps even the immediate future.

Few contemporary philosophers of mind would call a process “introspective” if it does not meet some version of the three conditions above, though in ordinary language the temporal proximity condition may sometimes be violated. (For example, in ordinary speech we might describe as “introspective” a process of thinking about why you abandoned a relationship last month or whether you're really as kind to your children as you think you are.) However, many philosophers of mind will resist calling a process that meets these three conditions “introspective” unless it also meets some or all of the following three conditions:

The directness condition : Introspection yields judgments or knowledge about one's own current mental processes relatively directly or immediately . It's difficult to articulate exactly what directness or immediacy involves in the present context, but some examples should make the import of this condition relatively clear. Gathering sensory information about the world and then drawing theoretical conclusions based on that information should not, according to this condition, count as introspective, even if the process meets the three conditions above. Seeing that a car is twenty feet in front of you and then inferring from that fact about the external world that you are having a visual experience of a certain sort does not, by this condition, count as introspective. However, as we will see in Section 2.3.4 below, those who embrace transparency theories of introspection may reject at least strong formulations of this condition.

The detection condition : Introspection involves some sort of attunement to or detection of a pre-existing mental state or event, where the introspective judgment or knowledge is (when all goes well) causally but not ontologically dependent on the target mental state. For example, a process that involved creating the state of mind that one attributes to oneself would not be introspective, according to this condition. Suppose I say to myself in silent inner speech, “I am saying to myself in silent inner speech, ‘haecceities of applesauce’”, without any idea ahead of time how I plan to complete the embedded quotation. Now, what I say may be true, and I may know it to be true, and I may know its truth (in some sense) directly, by a means by which I could not know the truth of anyone else's mind. That is, it may meet all the four conditions above and yet we may resist calling such a self-attribution introspective. Self-shaping (Section 2.3.2 below), expressivist (Section 2.3.3 below), and transparency (Section 2.3.4 below) accounts of self-knowledge emphasize the extent to which our self-knowledge often does not involve the detection of pre-existing mental states; and because something like the detection condition is implicitly or explicitly accepted by many philosophers, some philosophers (including some but not all of those who endorse self-shaping, expressivist, and/or transparency views) would regard it as inappropriate to regard such accounts of self-knowledge as accounts of introspection proper.

The effort condition : Introspection is not constant, effortless, and automatic . We are not every minute of the day introspecting. Introspection involves some sort of special reflection on one's own mental life that differs from the ordinary un-self-reflective flow of thought and action. The mind may monitor itself regularly and constantly without requiring any special act of reflection by the thinker—for example, at a non-conscious level certain parts of the brain or certain functional systems may monitor the goings-on of other parts of the brain and other functional systems, and this monitoring may meet all five conditions above—but this sort of thing is not what philosophers generally have in mind when they talk of introspection. However, this condition, like the directness and detection conditions, is not universally accepted. For example, philosophers who think that conscious experience requires some sort of introspective monitoring of the mind and who think of conscious experience as a more or less constant feature of our lives may reject the effort condition (Armstrong 1968, 1999; Lycan 1996).

Though not all philosophical accounts that are put forward by their authors as accounts of “introspection” meet all of conditions 4–6, most meet at least two of those. Because of differences in the importance accorded to conditions 4–6, it is not unusual for authors with otherwise similar accounts of self-knowledge to differ in their willingness to describe their accounts as accounts of “introspection”.

Accounts of introspection differ in what they treat as the proper targets of the introspective process. No major contemporary philosopher believes that all of mentality is available to be discovered by introspection. For example, the cognitive processes involved in early visual processing and in the detection of phonemes are generally held to be introspectively impenetrable and nonetheless (in some important sense) mental (Marr 1983; Fodor 1983). Many philosophers also accept the existence of unconscious beliefs or desires, in roughly the Freudian sense, that are not introspectively available (e.g., Gardner 1993; Velleman 2000; Moran 2001; Wollheim 2003; though see Lear 1998). Although in ordinary English usage we sometimes say we are “introspecting” when we reflect on our character traits, contemporary philosophers of mind generally do not believe that we can directly introspect character traits in the same sense in which we can introspect some of our other mental states (especially in light of research suggesting that we sometimes have poor knowledge of our traits, reviewed in Taylor and Brown 1988; Paulhus and John 1998; Vazire 2010).

The two most commonly cited classes of introspectible mental states are attitudes , such as beliefs, desires, evaluations, and intentions, and conscious experiences , such as emotions, images, and sensory experiences. (These two groups may not be wholly, or even partially, disjoint: Depending on other aspects of her view, a philosopher may regard some or all conscious experiences as involving attitudes, and/or she may regard attitudes as things that are or can be consciously experienced.) It of course does not follow from the fact (if it is a fact) that some attitudes are introspectible that all attitudes are, or from the fact that some conscious experiences are introspectible that all conscious experiences are. Some accounts of introspection focus on attitudes (e.g., Nichols and Stich 2003), while others focus on conscious experiences (e.g., Hill 1991; Goldman 2006; Schwitzgebel 2012); and it is sometimes unclear to what extent philosophers intend their remarks about the introspection of one type of target to apply to the other type. There is no guarantee that the same mechanism or process is involved in introspecting all the different potential targets.

Generically, this article will describe the targets of introspection as mental states , though in some cases it may be more apt to think of the targets as processes rather than states. Also, in speaking of the targets of introspection as targets , no presupposition is intended of a self-detection view of introspection as opposed to a self-shaping or containment or expressivist view (see Section 2 below). The targets are simply the states self-ascribed as a consequence of the introspective process if the process works correctly, or if the introspective process fails, the states that would have been self-ascribed.

Though philosophers have not explored the issue very thoroughly, accounts also differ regarding the products of introspection. Most philosophers hold that introspection yields something like beliefs or judgments about one's own mind, but others prefer to characterize the products of introspection as “thoughts”, “representations”, “awareness”, or the like. For ease of exposition, this article will describe the products of the introspective process as judgments, without meaning to beg the question against competing views.

2. Introspective Versus Non-Introspective Accounts of Self-Knowledge

This section will outline several approaches to self-knowledge. Not all deserve to be called introspective, but an understanding of introspection requires an appreciation of this diversity of approaches—some for the sake of the contrast they provide to introspection proper and some because it's disputable whether they should be classified as introspective. These approaches are not exclusive. Surely there is more than one process by means of which we can obtain self-knowledge. Unavoidably, some of the same territory covered here is also covered, rather differently, in the entry on self-knowledge .

2.1 Self/Other Parity Accounts

Symmetrical or self/other parity accounts of self-knowledge treat the processes by which we acquire knowledge of our own minds as essentially the same as the processes by which we acquire knowledge of other people's minds. A simplistic version of this view is that we know both our own minds and the minds of others only by observing outward behavior. On such a view, introspection strictly speaking is impossible, since the first-person condition on introspection (condition 2 in Section 1.1) cannot be met: There is no distinctive process that generates knowledge of one's own mind only. Twentieth-century behaviorist principles tended to encourage this view, but no prominent treatment of self-knowledge accepts this view in its most extreme and simple form. Advocates of parity accounts sometimes characterize our knowledge of our own minds as arising from “theories” that we apply equally to ourselves and others (as in Nisbett and Ross 1980; Gopnik 1993a, 1993b). Consequently, this approach to self-knowledge is sometimes called the theory theory .

Among leading researchers, Bem (1972) perhaps comes closest to a simple self/other parity view, arguing on the basis of psychological research that our knowledge of the “internal states” of both self and other derives largely from the same types of behavioral evidence and employs the same principles of inference. We notice how we behave, and then we infer the attitudes evidenced by those behaviors—and we do so even when we actually lack the ascribed attitude. For example, Bem cites classic research in social psychology suggesting that when induced to perform an action for a small reward, people will attribute to themselves a more positive attitude toward that action than when they are induced by a large reward (Festinger and Carlsmith 1959; see also Section 4.2.2 below). When we notice ourselves doing something with minimal compensation, we infer a positive attitude toward that activity, just as we would if we saw someone else perform the same activity with minimal compensation. Likewise, we might know we like Thai food because we've noticed that we sometimes drive all the way across town to get it; we might know that we're happy because we see or feel ourselves smiling. Bem argues that social psychology has consistently failed to show that we have any appreciable access to private information that might tell against such externally-driven self-attributions. On Bem's view, if we are better at discerning our own motives and attitudes, it's primarily because we have observed more of our own behavior than of anyone else's.

Nisbett, Wilson, and their co-authors (Nisbett and Bellows 1977; Nisbett and Wilson 1977; Nisbett and Ross 1980; Wilson 2002) similarly argue for self/other parity in our knowledge of the bases or causes of our own and others' attitudes and behavior, describing cases in which people seem to show poor knowledge of these bases or causes. For example, people queried in a suburban shopping center about why they chose a particular pair of stockings appeared to be ignorant of the influence of position on that choice, including explicitly denying that influence when it was suggested to them. People asked to rate various traits of supposed job applicants were unaware that their judgments of the applicant's flexibility were greatly influenced by having been told that the applicant had spilled coffee during the job interview (see also Section 4.2.2 below). In such cases, Nisbett and his co-investigators found that subjects' descriptions of the causal influences on their own behavior closely mirrored the influences hypothesized by outside observers. From this finding, they infer that the same mechanism drives the first-person and third-person attributions, a mechanism that that does not involve any special private access to the real causes of one's attitudes and behavior and instead relies heavily on intuitive psychological theories.

Gopnik (1993a, 1993b; Gopnik and Meltzoff 1994) deploys developmental psychological evidence to support a parity theory of self-knowledge. She points to evidence that for a wide variety of mental states, including believing, desiring, and pretending, children develop the capacity to ascribe those states to themselves at the same age they develop the capacity to ascribe those states to others. For example, children do not seem to be able to ascribe to themselves past false beliefs (after having been tricked by the experimenter) any earlier than they can ascribe false beliefs to other people. This appears to be so even when that false belief is in the very recent past, having only just been revealed to be false. According to Gopnik, this pervasive parallelism shows that we are not given direct introspective access to our beliefs, desires, pretenses, and the like. Rather, we must develop a “theory of mind” in light of which we interpret evidence underwriting our self-attributions. The appearance of the immediate givenness of one's mental states is, Gopnik suggests, merely an “illusion of expertise”: Experts engage in all sorts of tacit theorizing that they don't recognize as such—the expert chess player for whom the strength of a move seems simply visually given, the doctor who immediately intuits cancer in a patient. Since we are all experts at mental state attribution, we don't recognize the layers of theory underwriting the process.

The empirical evidence behind self/other parity views remains contentious (White 1988; Nichols and Stich 2003). Furthermore, though Bem, Nisbett, Wilson, and Gopnik all stress the parallelism between mental state attribution to oneself and others and the inferential and theoretical nature of such attributions, they all also leave some room for a kind of self-awareness different in kind from the awareness one has of others' mental lives. Thus, none endorses a purely symmetrical or self/other parity view. Bem acknowledges that the parallelism only holds “to the extent that internal cues are weak, ambiguous, or uninterpretable” (1972, 5). With this caveat in mind, he states that our self-knowledge is “partially” based on external cues. Nisbett and Wilson stress that we lack access only to the “processes” or causes underlying our behavior and attitudes. Our attitudes themselves and our current sensations, they say, can be known with “near certainty” (1977, 255; though contrast Nisbett and Ross 1980, 200–202, which seems sympathetic to Bem's skepticism about special access even to our attitudes). Gopnik allows that we “may be well equipped to detect certain kinds of internal cognitive activity in a vague and unspecified way”, and that we have “genuinely direct and special access to certain kinds of first-person evidence [which] might account for the fact that we can draw some conclusions about our own psychological states when we are perfectly still and silent”, though we can “override that evidence with great ease” (1993a, 11–12). Ryle (1949) similarly stresses the importance of outward behavior in the self-attribution of mental states while acknowledging the presence of “twinges”, “thrills”, “tickles”, and even “silent soliloquies”, which we know of in our own case and that do not appear to be detectable by observing outward behavior. However, none of these authors develops an account of this apparently more direct self-knowledge. Their theories are consequently incomplete. Regardless of the importance of behavioral evidence and general theories in driving our self-attributions, in light of the considerations that drive Bem, Nisbett, Wilson, Gopnik, and Ryle to these caveats, it is probably impossible to sustain a view on which there is complete parity between first- and third-person mental state attributions. There must be some sort of introspective, or at least uniquely first-person, process.

Self/other parity views can also be restricted to particular subclasses of mental states: Any mental state that can only be known by cognitive processes identical to the processes by which we know about the same sorts of states in other people is a state to which we have no distinctively introspective access. States for which parity is often asserted include personality traits, unconscious motives, early perceptual processes, and the bases of our decisions (see Section 4.2.1 below for more on this). We learn about these states in ourselves, perhaps, in much the same way we learn about such states in other people. Carruthers (2011; see also Section 4.2.2 below) presents a case for parity of access to propositional attitudes like belief and desire (in contrast to inner speech, visual imagery, and the like, which he holds to be introspectible).

2.2 Self-Detection Accounts

Etymologically, the term “introspection”—from the Latin “looking into”—suggests a perceptual or quasi-perceptual process. Locke writes that we have a faculty of “Perception of the Operation of our own Mind” which, “though it be not Sense, as having nothing to do with external Objects; yet it is very like it, and might properly enough be call'd internal Sense” (1690/1975, 105, italics suppressed). Kant (1781/1997) says we have an “inner sense” by which we learn about mental aspects of ourselves that is in important ways parallel to the “outer sense” by which we learn about outer objects.

But what does it mean to say that introspection is like perception? In what respects? As Shoemaker (1994a, 1994b, 1994c) points out, in a number of respects introspection is plausibly unlike perception. For example, introspection does not involve a dedicated organ like the eye or ear (though as Armstrong 1968 notes, neither does bodily proprioception). Both friends and foes of self-detection accounts have tended to agree that introspection does not involve a distinctive phenomenology of “introspective appearances” (Shoemaker 1994a, 1994b, 1994c; Lycan 1996; Rosenthal 2001; Siewert 2012): The visual experience of redness has a distinctive sensory quality or phenomenology that would be difficult or impossible to convey to a blind person; analogously for the olfactory experience of smelling a banana, the auditory experience of hearing a pipe organ, the experience of touching something painfully hot. To be analogous to sensory experience in this respect, introspection would have to generate an analogously distinctive phenomenology—some quasi-sensory phenomenology in addition to, say, the visual phenomenology of seeing red that is the phenomenology of the introspective appearance of the visual phenomenology of seeing red. This would seem to require two layers of appearance in introspectively attended sensory perception: a visual appearance of the outward object and an introspective appearance of that visual appearance. (This isn't to say, however, that introspection, or at least conscious introspection, doesn't involve some sort of “cognitive phenomenology”—if there is such a thing—of the sort that accompanies conscious thoughts in general: See Bayne and Montague, eds., 2011.)

Contemporary proponents of quasi-perceptual models of introspection concede the existence of such disanalogies (e.g., Lycan 1996). We might consider an account of introspection to be quasi-perceptual, or less contentiously to be a “self-detection” account, if it meets the first five conditions described in Section 1.1—that is, the mentality condition, the first-person condition, the temporal proximity condition, the directness condition, and the detection condition. One aspect of the detection condition deserves special emphasis here: that detection requires the ontological independence of the target mental state and the introspective judgment—the two states will be causally connected (assuming that all has gone well) but not constitutively connected. (Shoemaker (1994a, 1994b, 1994c) calls models of self-knowledge that meet this aspect of the detection condition “broad perceptual” models.) Maybe on a liberal understanding of “detection” that does not require ontological independence, containment or other accounts of introspection (see Section 2.3.1 below) might qualify as involving “detection”. However, that is not how “detection” is being used in the present taxonomy.

Self-detection accounts of self-knowledge seem to put introspection epistemically on a par with sense perception. To many philosophers, this has seemed a deficiency in these accounts. A long and widespread philosophical tradition holds that self-knowledge is epistemically special, that we have specially “privileged access” to—perhaps even infallible or indubitable knowledge of—at least some portion of our mentality, in a way that is importantly different in kind from our knowledge of the world outside us (see Section 4 below). Both self/other parity accounts (Section 2.1 above) and self-detection accounts (this section) of self-knowledge either deny any special epistemic privilege or characterize that privilege as similar to the privilege of being the only person to have an extended view of an object or a certain sort of sensory access to that object. Other accounts of self-knowledge to be discussed later in Section 2.3 are more readily compatible with, and often to some extent driven by, more robust notions of the epistemic differences between self-knowledge and knowledge of environmental objects.

Armstrong (1968, 1981, 1999) is perhaps the leading defender of a quasi-perceptual, self-detection account of introspection. He describes introspection as a “self-scanning process in the brain” (1968, 324), and he stresses what he sees as the important ontological distinction between the state of awareness produced by the self-scanning procedure and the target mental state of which one is aware by means of that scanning—the distinction, for example, between one's pain and one's introspective awareness of that pain.

Armstrong also appears to hold that the quasi-perceptual introspective process proceeds at a fairly low level cognitively—quick and simple, typically without much interference by or influence from other cognitive or sensory processes. He describes introspection as “completely non-inferential”, similar to the simple detection of pressure on one's back (1968, 97), and he says it can be (and presumably typically is) continuous and “reflex”, involving no more than keeping “a watching brief on our own current mental contents, but without making much of a deal of it” (1999, 115). Since Armstrong allows that inferences are often non-conscious, based on sensory or other cues that the inferring person cannot herself discern, his claim that the introspective process is non-inferential is a substantial commitment to the simplicity of the process. He contrasts this reflexive self-monitoring with more sophisticated acts of deliberate introspection which he thinks are also possible (1999, 114). Note that in calling reflexive self-monitoring “introspection”, Armstrong violates the effort condition from Section 1.1, which requires that introspection not be constant and automatic. Lycan (1996) endorses a similar view, though unlike Armstrong, Lycan characterizes introspection as involving attentional mechanisms, thus presumably treating introspection as more demanding of cognitive resources (though still perhaps nearly constant).

Nichols and Stich (2003) employ a model of the mind on which having a propositional attitude such as a belief or desire is a matter of having a representation stored in a functionally-defined (and metaphorical) “belief box” or “desire box” (see also the entries on belief and functionalism ). On their account, self-awareness of these attitudes typically involves the operation of a simple “Monitoring Mechanism” that merely takes the representations from these boxes, appends an “I believe that …”, “I desire that …”, or whatever (as appropriate) to that representation, and adds it back into the belief box. For example, if I desire that my father flies to Hong Kong on Sunday, the Monitoring Mechanism can copy the representation in my desire box with the content “my father flies to Hong Kong on Sunday” and produce a new representation in my belief box—that is, create a new belief—with the content “I desire that my father flies to Hong Kong on Sunday”. Nichols and Stich also propose an analogous but somewhat more complicated mechanism (they leave the details unspecified) that takes percepts as its input and produces beliefs about those percepts as its output.

Nichols and Stich emphasize that this Monitoring Mechanism does not operate in isolation, but often co-operates or competes with a second means of acquiring self-knowledge, which involves deploying theories along the lines suggested by Gopnik (see Section 2.1.2 above). They offer a “double dissociation” argument for this view. That is, they present, on the one hand, cases which they interpret as cases showing a breakdown in the Monitoring Mechanism, while the capacity for theoretical inference about the mind remains intact and, on the other hand, cases in which the capacity for theoretical inference about the mind is impaired but the Monitoring Mechanism continues to function normally, suggesting that theoretical inference and self-monitoring are distinct and separable processes. Nichols and Stich argue that autistic people have very poor theoretical knowledge of the mind, as suggested by their very poor performance in “theory of mind” tasks (tasks like assessing when someone will have a false belief), and yet they succeed in monitoring their mental states as shown by their ability to describe their mental states in autobiographies and other forms of self-report. Conversely, Nichols and Stich argue that schizophrenic people remain excellent theorizers about mental states but monitor their own mental states very poorly—for example, when they fail to recognize certain actions as their own and struggle to report, or deny the existence of, ongoing thoughts.

Goldman (2006) criticizes the account of Nichols and Stich (see Section 2.2.1 above) for not describing how the Monitoring Mechanism detects the attitude type of the representation (belief, desire, etc.). If talk of “belief boxes” and the like is shorthand for talk of functional role (as Nichols and Stich say), then the Monitoring Mechanism must somehow detect the functional role of the detected representation. But functional role is a matter of what is apt to cause a particular mental state and what that mental state is apt to cause (see the entry on functionalism ), and Goldman argues that a simple mechanism could not discern such dispositional and relational facts (though Nichols and Stich might be able to avoid this concern by describing introspection as involving not just one but rather a cluster of similar mechanisms: 2003, 162). Goldman also argues that the Nichols and Stich account leaves unclear how we can discern the strength or intensity of our beliefs, desires, and other propositional attitudes.

Goldman's positive account starts with the idea that introspection is a quasi-perceptual process that involves attention: “Attention seems to act like an orienting organ in introspection, analogous to the shift of eye gaze or the sniffing of the nose” (2006, 244). Individual attended mental states are then classified into broad categories (similarly, in visual perception we can classify seen objects into broad categories). However, on Goldman's view this process can only generate introspective knowledge of the general types of mental states (such as belief, happiness, bodily sensation) and some properties of those mental states (such as degree of confidence for belief, and “a multitude of finely delineated categories” for bodily sensation). Specific contents, especially of attitudes like belief, are too manifold, Goldman suggests, for pre-existing classificational categories to exist for each one. Rather, we represent the specific content of such mental states by “redeploying” the representational content of the mental state, that is, simply copying the content of the introspected mental state into the content of the introspective belief or judgment (somewhat like in the Nichols and Stich account). Finally, Goldman argues that some mental states require “translation” into the mental code appropriate to belief if they are to be introspected. Visual representations, he suggests, have a different format or mental code than beliefs, and therefore cognitive work will be necessary to translate the fine-grained detail of visual experience into mental contents that can be believed introspectively.

Hill (1991, 2009) also offers a multi-process self-detection account of introspection. Like Goldman, Hill sees attention (in some broad, non-sensory sense) as central to introspection, though he also allows for introspective awareness without attention (1991, 117–118). Hill emphasizes dissimilarities between introspection and perception, while retaining a broadly self-detection account. Hill (2009) argues that introspection is a process that produces judgments about , rather than perceptual awareness of, the target states, and suggests that the processes that generate these judgments vary considerably, depending on the target state, and are often complex. For example, judgments about enduring beliefs and desires must, he says, involve complex procedures for searching “vast and heterogeneous” long-term memory stores. Central to Hill's (1991) account is an emphasis on the capacity of introspective attention to transform—especially to amplify and enrich, even to create—the target experience. In this respect Hill argues that the introspective act differs from the paradigmatic observational act which does not transform the object perceived (though of course both scientific and ordinary—especially gustatory—observation can affect what is perceived); and thus Hill's account contains a “self-fulfillment” or “self-shaping” aspect in the sense of Section 2.3.1 and Section 2.3.2 below, and only qualifiedly and conditionally meets the detection condition on accounts of introspection as described in Section 1.1 above—the condition that introspection involves attunement to or detection of a pre-existing mental state or event.

Like Hill, Prinz (2004) argues that introspection must involve multiple mechanisms, depending both on the target states (e.g., attitudes vs. perceptual experiences) and the particular mode of access to those states. Access might involve controlled attention or it might be more of a passive noticing; it might involve the verbal “captioning” or labeling of experiences or it might involve the kind of non-verbal access that even monkeys have to their mental states. Prinz (2007) sharply distinguishes between the conceptual classification of our conscious experiences into various types that can be recognized and re-identified over time—classifications which he thinks must necessarily be somewhat crude—and non-conceptual knowledge of ongoing conscious experiences attained by “pointing” at them with attention. The latter type of knowledge, Prinz argues, is much more detailed and finely structured than the former but cannot be expressed or retained over time. Prinz also follows Hill in emphasizing that introspection often intensifies or otherwise modifies the target experience. In such cases, Prinz argues, introspective “access” is only access in an attenuated sense.

2.3 Introspection Without Self-Detection?

There are several ways to generate judgments, or at least statements, about one's own current mental life—self-ascriptions, let's call them—that are reliably true though they do not involve the detection of a pre-existing state. Consider the following four types of case:

Automatically self-fulfilling self-ascriptions : I think to myself, “I am thinking”. Or: I judge that I am making a judgment about my own mental life. Or: I say to myself in inner speech “I am saying to myself in inner speech: ‘blu-bob’”. Such self-ascriptions are automatically self-fulfilling. Their existence conditions are a subset of their truth conditions.

Self-ascriptions that prompt self-shaping : I declare that I have a mental image of a pink elephant. At the same time I make this declaration, I deliberately cause myself to form the mental image of a pink elephant. Or: A man uninitiated in romantic love declares to a prospective lover that he is the kind of person who sends flowers to his lovers. At the same time he says this, he successfully resolves to be the kind of person who sends flowers to his lovers. The self-ascription either precipitates a change or buttresses what already exists in such a way as to make the self-ascription accurate. In these cases, unlike the cases described in (A), some change or self-maintenance is necessary to render the self-ascription true, beyond the self-ascriptional event itself.

Accurate self-ascription through self-expression : I learn to say “I'm in pain!” instead of “ow!” as an automatic, unreflective response to painful stimuli. Or: I use the self-attributive sentence “I believe Russell changed his mind about pacifism” simply as a cautious way of expressing the belief that Russell changed his mind about pacifism, this expression being the product of reflecting upon Russell rather than a product of reflection upon my own mind. Self-expressions of this sort are assumed here to flow naturally from the states expressed in roughly the same way that facial expressions and non-self-attributive verbal expressions flow naturally from those same states—that is, without being preceded by any attempt to detect the state self-ascribed.

Self-ascriptions derived from judgments about the outside world : From the non-self-attributive fact that Stanford is south of Berkeley I derive the self-attributive conclusion that I believe that Stanford is south of Berkeley. Or: From the non-self-attributive fact that it would be good to go to home now, I derive the self-attributive judgment that I want to go home now. These derivations may be inferences, but if so, such inferences require no specific premises about ongoing mental states. Perhaps one embraces a general inference principle like “from P , it is permissible to derive I believe that P ”, or “normally, if something is good, I want it”.

The following accounts of self-knowledge all take advantage of one or more of these facts about self-ascription. Because these ways of obtaining self-knowledge all violate the detection condition on introspection (condition 5 in Section 1.1 above), and because philosophers are divided about whether methods of obtaining self-knowledge that violate that condition count as introspective methods strictly speaking, philosophers are divided about whether accounts of self-knowledge of the sort described in this section should be regarded as accounts of introspection.

An emphasis on infallible knowledge through self-fulfilling self-ascriptions goes back at least to Augustine (c. 420 C.E./1998) and is most famously deployed by Descartes in his Discourse on Method (1637/1985) and Meditations (1641/1984), where he takes the self-fulfilling thought that he is thinking as indubitably true, immune to even the most radical skepticism, and a secure ground on which to build further knowledge.

Contemporary self-fulfillment accounts tend to exploit the idea of containment . In a 1988 essay, Burge writes:

When one knows one is thinking that p , one is not taking one's thought (or thinking) that p merely as an object. One is thinking that p in the very event of thinking knowledgeably that one is thinking it. It is thought and thought about in the same mental act. (654)

This is the case, Burge argues, because “by its reflexive, self-referential character, the content of the second-order [self-attributive] judgment is locked (self-referentially) onto the first-order content which it both contains and takes as its subject matter” (1988, 659–660; cf. Heil 1988; Gertler 2000, 2001; Heil and Gertler describe such thoughts as introspective while Burge appears not to think of self-knowledge so structured as introspective: 1998, 244; see also 1988, 652). In judging that I am thinking of a banana, I thereby necessarily think of a banana: The self-attributive judgment contains, as a part, the very thought self-ascribed, and thus cannot be false. In a 1996 essay, Burge extends his remarks to include not just self-attributive “thoughts” as targets but also (certain types of) “judgments” (e.g., “I judge, herewith, that there are physical entities” and other judgments with “herewith”-like reflexivity, 92)

Shoemaker (1994a, 1994b, 1994c) deploys the containment idea very differently, and over a much wider array of introspective targets, including conscious states like pains and propositional attitudes like belief. Shoemaker speculates that the relevant containment relation holds not between the contents or concepts employed in the target state and in the self-ascriptive state but rather between their neural realizations in the brain. To develop this point, Shoemaker distinguishes between a mental state's “core realization” and its “total realization”. One might think of mental processes as transpiring in fairly narrow regions of the brain (their core realization), and yet, Shoemaker suggests, it's not as though we could simply carve off those regions from all others and still have the mental state in question. To be the mental state it is, the process must be embedded in a larger causal network involving more of the brain (the total realization). Relationships of containment or overlap between core realization and total realization between the target state and the self-ascriptive judgment might then underwrite introspective accuracy. For example, the total brain-state realization of the state of pain may simply be a subset of the total brain-state realization of the state of believing that one is in pain. Introspective accuracy might then be explained by the fact that the introspective judgment is not an independently existing state.

More recently, philosophers have applied Burge-like content-containment models (as opposed to Shoemaker-like realization-containment models) to self-knowledge of conscious states, or “phenomenology”, in particular—for example, Gertler (2001), Papineau (2002), Chalmers (2003), and Horgan and Kriegel (2007). Husserl (1913/1982) offers an early phenomenal containment approach, arguing that we can at any time put our “cogitatio”—our conscious experiences—consciously before us through a kind of mental glancing, with the self-perception that arises containing as a part the conscious experience toward which it is directed, and incapable of existing without it. Papineau offers a “quotational” account on which in introspection we self-attribute “the experience: ___”, where the blank is completed by the experience itself. Chalmers writes that “direct phenomenal beliefs” about our experiences are “partly constituted by an underlying phenomenal quality”, in that the two will be tightly coupled across “a wide range of nearby conceptually possible cases” (2003, 235).

One possible difficulty with such accounts is that while it seems plausible to suppose that an introspective thought or judgment might contain another thought or judgment as a part, it's less clear how a self-attributive judgment or belief might contain a piece of conscious experience as a part. Beliefs, and other belief-like mental states like judgments, one might think, contain concepts , not conscious experiences, as their constituents (Fodor 1998); or, alternatively, one might think that beliefs are functional or dispositional patterns of response to input (Dennett 1987; Schwitzgebel 2002), again rendering it unclear how a piece of phenomenology could be part of belief. Perhaps with this concern in mind, advocates of containment accounts often appeal to “phenomenal concepts” that are, like the introspective judgments to which they contribute, partly constituted by the the conscious experiences that are the contents of those concepts. Such concepts are often thought to be obtained by demonstrative attention to our conscious experiences as they are ongoing.

It would seem, at least, that beliefs, concepts, or judgments containing pieces of phenomenology would have to expire once the phenomenology has passed and thus that the introspective judgments could not used in later inferences without recreating the state in question. Chalmers (2003) concedes the temporal locality of such phenomenology-containing introspective judgments and consequently their limited use in speech and in making generalizations. Papineau (2002), in contrast, embraces a theory in which the imaginative recreation of phenomenology in thinking about past experience is commonplace.

Although we can seemingly at least sometimes arrive at true self ascriptions through the self-shaping and the self-expression procedures (B and C) described at the beginning of Section 2.3, and although such procedures may meet the first three conditions on an account of introspection as described in Section 1.1—that is, they may (depending on how they are described and developed) be procedures that can yield only knowledge or judgments (or at least self-ascriptions) about one's own currently ongoing or very recently past mental states—few philosophers would describe such procedures as “introspective”. Nonetheless, they warrant brief treatment here, partly for the same reason self/other parity accounts warranted treatment in Section 2.1 above—that is, as skeptical accounts suggesting that the scope of introspection may be considerably narrower than is generally thought—and partly as background for the “transparency” accounts to be discussed in Section 2.3.4 below, with which they are often married.

It is difficult to find accounts of self-knowledge that stress the self-shaping technique in its purest, forward-looking, causal form—perhaps because it's clear that self-knowledge must involve considerably more than this (Gertler 2011). However, McGeer (1996, 2008; McGeer and Pettit 2002) puts considerable emphasis on self-shaping, writing that “we learn to use our intentional self-ascriptions to instill or reinforce tendencies and inclinations that fit with these ascriptions, even though such tendencies and inclinations may at best have been only nascent at the time we first made the judgments” (1996, 510). If I describe myself as brave in battle, or as a committed vegetarian—especially if I do so publicly—I create commitments and expectations for myself that help to make those self-ascriptions true. McGeer compares self-knowledge to the knowledge a driver has, as opposed to a passenger, of where the car is going: The driver, unlike the passenger, can make it the case that the car goes where she says it is going (505).

There are also strains in Dennett (though Dennett may not have an entirely consistent view on these matters; see Schwitzgebel 2007) that suggest either a self-fulfillment or a self-shaping view. In some places, Dennett compares “introspective” self-reports about consciousness to works of fiction, immune to refutation in the same way that fictional claims are—one could no more go wrong about one's consciousness, Dennett says, than Doyle could go wrong about the color of Holmes's easy chair (e.g., 1991, 81, 94). Such remarks are consistent with either an anti-realist view of fiction (there are no facts about the easy chair or about consciousness; see 366–367) or a self-fulfillment or self-shaping realist view (Doyle creates facts about Holmes as he thinks or writes about him; we create facts about what it's like to be us in thinking or making claims about our consciousness, as perhaps on 81 and 94). More moderately, in discussing attitudes, Dennett emphasizes how the act of formulating an attitude in language—for example, when ordering a menu item—can involve self-attributing a degree of specification in one's attitudes that was not present before, thereby committing one to, and partially or wholly creating, the specific attitude self-ascribed (1987, 20).

Wittgenstein writes:

[H]ow does a human being learn the meaning of the names of sensations?—of the word “pain” for example. Here is one possibility: words are connected with the primitive, the natural, expressions of the sensation and used in their place. A child has hurt himself and he cries; and then adults talk to him and teach him exclamations and, later, sentences. They teach the child new pain-behaviour.
“So you are saying that the word ‘pain’ really means crying?”—On the contrary: the verbal expression of pain replaces crying and does not describe it. (1953/1968, sec. 244)
“It can't be said of me at all (except perhaps as a joke) that I know I am in pain. What is it supposed to mean—except perhaps that I am in pain?” (1953/1968, sec. 246).

On Wittgenstein's view, it is both true that I am in pain and that I say of myself that I am in pain, but the utterance in no way emerges from a process of detecting one's pain.

A simple expressivist view—sometimes attributed to Wittgenstein on the basis of these and related passages—denies that the expressive utterances (e.g., “that hurts!”) genuinely ascribe mental states to the individuals uttering them. Such a view faces serious difficulties accommodating the evident semantics of self-ascriptive utterances, including their use in inference and the apparent symmetries between present-tense and past-tense uses and between first-person and third-person uses (Wright 1998; Bar-On 2004). Consequently, Bar-On advocates, instead, what she calls a neo-expressivist view according to which expressive utterances can share logical and semantic structure with non-expressive utterances, despite the epistemic differences between them.

Expressivists have not always been clear about exactly the range of target mental states expressible in this way, but it seems plausible that at least in principle some true (or apt) self-ascriptions could arise in this manner, with no intervening introspective self-detection. The question would then be whether this is how we generally arrive at true self-ascriptions, for some particular class of mental states, or whether some more archetypically introspective process is also available. (For a more detailed treatment of expressivism, consult the section about the expressivist model of self-knowledge in the entry self-knowledge .)

Evans writes:

[I]n making a self-ascription of belief, one's eyes are, so to speak, or occasionally literally, directed outward—upon the world. If someone asks me, “Do you think there is going to be a third world war?”, I must attend, in answering him, to precisely the same outward phenomena as I would attend to if I were answering the question “Will there be a third world war?” I get myself into the position to answer the question whether I believe that p by putting into operation whatever procedure I have for answering the question whether p . (1982, 225)

Transparency approaches to self-knowledge, like Evans', emphasize cases in which it seems that one arrives at an accurate self-ascription not by means of attending to, or thinking about, one's own mental states, but rather by means of attending to or thinking about the external states of the world that the target mental states are about. Note that this claim has both a negative and a positive aspect: We do not learn about our minds by as it were gazing inward; and we do learn about our minds by reflecting on the aspects of the world that our mental states are about. The positive and negative theses are separable: A pluralist might accept the positive thesis without the negative one; an advocate of a self/other parity theory or an expressivist account of self-knowledge (with respect to a certain class of target states) might accept the negative thesis without the positive. (N.B.: In the philosophical literature on self-knowledge “transparency” is also sometimes used to mean something like self-intimation in the sense of Section 4.1.1 below, for example in Wright 1998; Bilgrami 2006. This is a completely different usage, not to be confused with the present usage.) Because transparency accounts stress the outward focus of our thought in arriving at self-ascriptions, calling such accounts accounts of “introspection” strains against the etymology of the term. Nonetheless, some prominent advocates of transparency accounts, such as Dretske (1995) and Tye (2000), offer them explicitly as accounts of introspection.

The range of target states to which transparency applies is a matter of some dispute. Among philosophers who accept something like transparency, belief is generally regarded as transparent (Gordon 1995, 2007; Gallois 1996; Moran 2001; Fernández 2003; Byrne 2005). Perceptual states or perceptual experiences are also often regarded as transparent in the relevant sense. Harman's example is the most cited:

When Eloise sees a tree before her, the colors she experiences are all experienced as features of the tree and its surroundings. None of them are experienced as intrinsic features of her experience. Nor does she experience any features of anything as intrinsic features of her experiences. And that is true of you too. There is nothing special about Eloise's visual experience. When you see a tree, you do not experience any features as intrinsic features of your experience. Look at a tree and try to turn your attention to intrinsic features of your visual experience. I predict you will find that the only features there to turn your attention to will be features of the presented tree. (Harman 1990, 667)

Harman's emphasis here is on the negative thesis, which goes back at least to Moore (1903; though Moore does not unambiguously endorse it). The view that it is impossible to attend directly to perceptual experience has recently been especially stressed by Tye (1995, 2000, 2002; see also Evans 1982; Van Gulick 1993; Shoemaker 1994a; Dretske 1995; Martin 2002; Stoljar 2004), and directly conflicts with accounts according to which we learn about our sensory experience primarily by directing introspective attention to it (e.g., Goldman 2006; Petitmengin 2006; Hill 2009; Siewert 2012; and back at least to Wundt 1888 and Titchener 1908/1973).

Gordon (2007) argues (contra Nichols and Stich 2003 and Goldman 2006) that Evans-like ascent routines (ascending from “ p ” to “I believe that p ”) can drive the accurate self-ascription of all the attitudes, not just belief. He makes his case by wedding the transparency thesis to something like an expressive account of self-ascription: To answer a question about what I want—for example, which flavor ice cream do I want?—I think not about my desires but rather about the different flavors available, and then I express the resulting attitude self-ascriptively. Similarly for hopes, fears, wishes, intentions, regrets, etc. Gordon points out that from a very early age, before they likely have any self-ascriptive intent, children learn to express their attitudes self-ascriptively, for example with simple phrases like “[I] want banana!” (see also Bar-On 2004).

The transparency thesis is in fact consistent, not just with expressivism, but with any of the four non-detection-based self-ascription procedures described at the beginning of this section (and indeed Aydede and Güzeldere 2005 attempt to reconcile aspects of the transparency view with a broadly detection-like approach to introspection). This manifold compatibility highlights the fact that by itself the transparency thesis does not go far toward a positive view of the mechanisms of self-knowledge.

Moran (2001) brings together transparency and self-shaping in his commissive account of self-knowledge. Moran argues that normally when we are prompted to think about what we believe, desire, or intend (and he limits his account primarily to these three mental states), we reflect on the (outward) phenomena in question and make up our minds about what to believe, desire, or do. Rather than attempting to detect a pre-existing state, we open or re-open the matter and come to a resolution. Since we normally do believe, desire, and intend what we resolve to believe, desire, and do, we can therefore accurately self-ascribe those attitudes. Falvey (2000) embraces a similar view, and furthermore joins it with expressivism, a move Moran resists. (See also Falvey 2000; Boyle 2009; and see the discussion of the commitment model of self-knowledge in the entry self-knowledge for a more detailed discussion of commissive accounts.)

Byrne (2005) and Dretske (1995) bring together transparency and something like a derivational model of self-knowledge—a model on which I derive the conclusion that I believe that P directly from P itself, or the conclusion that I am representing x as F from the fact that x is F —a fact which must of course, to serve as a premise in the derivation, be represented (or believed) by me. Byrne argues that just as one might abide by the following epistemic rule:

DOORBELL: If the doorbell rings, believe that there is someone at the door

so also might someone abide by the rule:

BEL: If P , believe that you believe that P .

To determine whether you believe that P , first determine whether P is the case, then follow the rule BEL. Byrne (2011a, 2011b, 2011c, 2012) offers similar accounts of self-knowledge of intention, thinking, seeing, and desire.

Dretske analogizes introspection to ordinary cases of “displaced perception”—cases in which one perceives that something is the case by way of directly perceiving some other thing (e.g., hearing that the mail carrier has arrived by hearing the dog's barking; seeing that you weigh 110 pounds by seeing the dial on the bathroom scale): One perceives that one represents x as F by way of perceiving the F -ness of x . Dretske notes, however, two points of disanalogy between the cases. In the case of hearing that the mail carrier has arrived by hearing the dog's bark, the conclusion (that the mail carrier has arrived) is only established if the premise about the dog's barking is true, and furthermore it depends on a defeasible connecting belief, that the dog's barking is a reliable indicator of the mail's arrival. In the introspective case, however, the inference, if it is an inference, does not require the truth of the premise about x 's being F . Even if x is not F , the conclusion that I'm representing x as F is supported. Nor does there seem to be any sort of defeasible connecting belief.

Tye also emphasizes transparency in his account of introspection, though he limits his remarks to the introspection of conscious experience or “phenomenal character”. In his 2000 book, Tye develops a view like Dretske's, analogizing introspection to displaced perception, though Tye unlike Dretske explicitly denies that inference is involved, instead proposing a mechanism similar to the sort of mechanism envisioned by simple monitoring accounts like those of Nichols and Stich (2003; see Section 2.2.1 above), a reliable process that, in the case of perceptual self-awareness, takes awareness of external things as its input and yields as its output awareness of phenomenal character. (The key difference between Tye's 2000 account on the one hand and the Nichols and Stich account on the other that warrants the classification of Tye's view here rather than in the section on self-detection models is this: Tye rejects the idea that the process is one of internal detection, while Nichols and Stich stress that idea. To adjudicate the dispute between those two positions, and to determine whether it might, in fact, be merely nominal, it would be helpful to have a clearer sense than has so far been given of what it means to say that one subpersonal system detects, or “monitors” or “scans”, the states or contents of another.) However, in his 2009 book, Tye rejects the displaced perception model in favor of a version of the transparency view that identifies phenomenal character with external qualities in the world, so that perceiving features of the world just is perceiving phenomenal character—a view that he recognizes is then charged with the difficult task of explaining how phenomenal character is a property (or “quality”) of external objects rather than, as is generally assumed, a property only of experiences of those objects.

Several authors have challenged the idea that sensory experience necessarily eludes attention—that is, they have denied the central claim of transparency theories about sensory experience. Block (1996), Kind (2003), and Smith (2008) have argued that phosphenes—those little lights you see when you press on your eyes—and visual blurriness are aspects of sensory experiences that can be directly attended. Siewert (2004) has argued that what's intuitively appealing in the transparency view is primarily the observation that in reflecting on sensory experience one does not withdraw attention from the objects sensed; but, he argues, this is compatible with also devoting a certain sort of attention to the sensory experience itself. In early discussions of attention, perceptual attention was sometimes distinguished from “intellectual attention” (James 1890/1981; Baldwin 1901–1905; see also Peacocke 1998; Mole 2011), that is, from the kind of attention we can devote to purely imagined word puzzles or to philosophical issues. If non-sensory forms of attention are possible, then the transparency thesis for sensory experience will require restatement: Is it only sensory attention to sensory experience that is impossible? Or is it any kind of attention whatsoever? Simply to say we don't attend sensorily to our mental states is to make only a modest claim, akin to the claim that we see objects rather than seeing our visual experiences of objects; but to say that we cannot attend to our mental states even intellectually appears extreme. In light of this, it remains unclear how to cast the transparency intuition to better bring out the core idea that is meant to be conveyed by the slogan that introspecting sensory experience is not a matter of attending to one's own mind.

Philosophers discussing self-knowledge often write as if approaches highlighting one of these methods of generating self-ascriptions conflict with approaches that highlight other of these methods, and also as if approaches of this general sort conflict with self-detection approaches (Section 2.2 above). While conflicts will certainly exist between different accounts intended to serve as exhaustive approaches to self-knowledge, it is implausible that any one or even any few of these approaches to self-knowledge is exhaustive. Plausibly, all of the non-self-detection approaches described above can lead, at least occasionally, to accurate self-ascriptions. Enthusiasts for another of the models, or for a self-detection model, needn't deny this. It also seems hard to deny that we at least sometimes reach conclusions about our mental lives based on the kind of theoretical inference or self-interpretation emphasized by advocates of self/other parity accounts (Section 2.1 above). Finally, even philosophers concerned about strong or oversimple self-scanning views might wish to grant that the mind can do some sort of tracking of its own present or recently past states—for example, when we trace back a stream of recently past thoughts that presumably can't (because past) be self-ascribed by self-fulfillment, self-shaping, self-expression, or transparency methods.

Schwitzgebel (2012) elevates this pluralism into a kind of negative account of introspection. Introspective judgments, he says, arise from a shifting confluence of many processes, recruited opportunistically, none of which can be called introspection proper. Just as there is no single, unified faculty of poster-taking-in that one employs when trying to take in a poster at a psychological conference or science fair, there is, on Schwitzgebel's view, no single, unified faculty of introspection or one underlying core process. Instead, the introspector, like the poster-viewer, brings to bear a diverse range of cognitive resources as suits the occasion. However, he says, the process wouldn't be worth calling "introspective" unless the introspector aimed to reach a judgment about her current or very recently past conscious experience, in a way that uses at least some resources specific to the first-person case, and in a way that involves some relatively direct sensitivity to the target state.

3. The Role of Introspection in Scientific Psychology

Philosophers have long made introspective claims about the human mind—or, to speak more cautiously, they've made claims seemingly at least in part introspectively grounded. Aristotle (3rd c. BCE/1961) asserts that thought does not occur without imagery. Mengzi (3rd c. BCE/2008) argues that our hearts are pleased by moral goodness and revolted by evil, even if the pleasure and revulsion are not evident in our outward behavior. Berkeley finds in himself no “abstract ideas” like that of a triangle that is, in Locke's terms “neither oblique, nor rectangle, neither equilateral, equicrural, nor scalenon, but all and none of these at once” (Berkeley 1710/1965, 12; Locke 1689/1975, 596). James Mill (1829/1878) attempts a catalog of the varieties of sense experience.

Although a number of early modern philosophers had aimed to initiate the scientific study of the mind, it wasn't until the middle of the 19th century—with the appearance of quantitative introspective methods , especially regarding sensory consciousness—that the study of the mind took shape as a progressive, mathematical, laboratory-based science. Early quantitative psychologists such as Helmholtz (1856/1962), Fechner (1860/1964), and Wundt (1896/1902) sought quantitative answers to questions like: By how much must two physical stimuli differ for the experiences of them to differ noticeably? How weak a stimulus can still be consciously perceived? What is the mathematical relationship between stimulus intensity and the intensity of the resulting sensation? (The Weber-Fechner law holds that the relationship is logarithmic.) Along what dimensions, exactly, can sense experience vary? (The “color solid” [see the link to the Munsell solid in Other Internet Resources, below], for example, characterizes color experience by appeal to just three dimensions of variation: hue, saturation, and lightness or brightness.) Although from very early on, psychologists also employed non-introspective methods (e.g., performance on memory tests, reaction times), most early characterizations of the field stood introspection at the center. James, for example, wrote that “introspective observation is what we have to rely on first and foremost and always” (1890/1981, 185).

In contrast with the dominant philosophical tradition that has, since Descartes, stressed the special privilege or at least high accuracy of introspective judgments about consciousness (see Section 4.1 below) many early introspective psychologists held that the introspection of currently ongoing or recently past conscious experience is difficult and prone to error if the introspective observer is insufficiently trained. Wundt, for example, reportedly did not credit the introspective reports of people with fewer than 50,000 trials of practice in observing their conscious experience (Boring 1953). Titchener, a leading American introspective psychologist, wrote a 1600-page introspective training manual for students, arguing that introspective observation is at least as difficult as observation in the physical sciences (Titchener 1901–1905; see also Wundt 1874/1908; Müller 1904; for contemporary discussions of introspective training see Varela 1996; Nahmias 2002; Schwitzgebel 2011b). This difference in optimism about untrained introspection may partly reflect differences in the types of judgments foregrounded in the two disciplines. Philosophers stressing privilege tend to focus on coarse and (seemingly) simple judgments such as “I'm having a visual experience of redness” or “I believe it's raining”. The projects of interest to introspective psychologists often required much finer judgments—such as determining with mathematical precision whether one visual sensation has twice the “intensity” of another or determining along what dimensions emotional experience can vary.

Early introspective psychologists' theoretical discussions of the nature of introspection were often framed in reaction to skepticism about the scientific viability of introspection, especially the concern that the introspective act interferes with or destroys the mental state or process that is its target. [ 1 ] ) The most influential formulation of this concern was Comte's:

But as for observing in the same way intellectual phenomena at the time of their actual presence, that is a manifest impossibility. The thinker cannot divide himself into two, of whom one reasons whilst the other observes him reason. The organ observed and the organ observing being, in this case, identical, how could observation take place? This pretended psychological method is then radically null and void (1830, using the translation of James 1890/1981, 188).

Introspective psychologists tended to react to this concern in one of three ways. The most concessive approach—recommended, for example, by James (1890/1981; see also Mill 1865/1961; Lyons 1986)—was to grant Comte's point for concurrent introspection, that is, introspection simultaneous with the target state or process, and to emphasize in contrast immediate retrospection , that is, reflecting on or attending to the target process (usually a conscious experience) very shortly after it occurs. Since the scientific observation occurs only after the target process is complete, it does not interfere with that process; but of course the delay between the process and the observation must be as brief as possible to ensure that the process is accurately remembered.

Brentano (1874/1973) responded to Comte's concern by distinguishing between “inner observation” [ innere Beobachtung ] and “inner perception” [ innere Wahrnehmung ]. Observation, as Brentano characterizes it, involves dedicating full attention to a phenomenon, with the aim of apprehending it accurately. This dedication of attention necessarily interferes with the process to be observed if the process is a mental one; therefore, he says, inner observation is problematic as a scientific psychological method. Inner perception , in contrast, according to Brentano, does not involve attention to our mental lives and thus does not objectionably disturb them. While our “attention is turned toward a different object … we are able to perceive, incidentally, the mental processes which are directed toward that object” (1874/1973, 30). Brentano concedes that inner perception necessarily lacks the advantages of attentive observation, so he recommends conjoining it with retrospective methods.

Wundt (1888) agrees with Comte and Brentano that observation necessarily involves attention and so often interferes with the process to be observed, if that process is an inner, psychological one. To a much greater extent than Brentano, however, Wundt emphasizes the importance to scientific psychology of direct attention to experience, including planful and controlled variation. The psychological method of “inner perception” is, for Wundt, the method of holding and attentively manipulating a memory image or reproduction of a past psychological process. Although Wundt sees some value in this retrospective method, he thinks it has two crucial shortcomings: First, one can only work with what one remembers of the process in question—the manipulation of a memory-image cannot discover new elements. And second, foreign elements may be unintentionally introduced through association—one might confuse one's memory of a process with one's memory of another associated process or object.

Therefore, Wundt suggests, the science of psychology must depend upon the attentive observation of mental processes as they occur. He argues that those who think attention necessarily distorts the target mental process are too pessimistic. A subclass of mental processes remains relatively unperturbed by attentive observation—the “simpler” mental processes, especially of perception (1896/1902, 27–28). The experience of seeing red, Wundt claims, is more or less the same whether or not one is attending to the psychological fact that one is experiencing redness. Wundt also suggests that the basic processes of memory, feeling, and volition can be observed systematically and without excessive disruption. These alone , he thinks, can be studied by introspective psychology (see also Wundt 1874/1904; 1896/1902; 1907). Other aspects of our psychology must be approached through non-introspective methods such as the observation of language, mythology, culture, and human and animal development.

Although introspective psychologists were able to build scientific consensus on some issues concerning sense experience—issues such as the limits of sensory perception in various modalities and some of the contours of variation in sensory experience—by the early 20th century it was becoming clear that on many issues consensus was elusive. The most famous dispute concerned the existence of “imageless thought” (see the discussion of the imageless thought controversy in the entry mental imagery ; see also Humphrey 1951; Kusch 1999); but other topics proved similarly resistant such as the structure of emotion or “feeling” (James 1890/1981; Külpe 1893/1895; Wundt 1896/1902; Titchener 1908/1973) and the experiential changes brought about by shifts in attention (Wundt 1896/1902; Pillsbury 1908; Titchener 1908/1973; Chapman 1933).

By the 1910s, behaviorism (which focused simply on the relationship between outward stimuli and behavioral response) had declared war on introspective psychology, portraying it as bogged down in irresolvable disputes between differing introspective “experts”, and also rebuking the introspectivists' passive taxonomizing of experience, recommending that psychology focus instead on socially useful paradigms for modifying behavior (e.g., Watson 1913). In the 1920s and 1930s, introspective studies were increasingly marginalized. Although strict behaviorism declined in the 1960s and 1970s, its main replacement, cognitivist functionalism (which treats functionally defined internal cognitive processes as central to psychological inquiry), generally continued to share behaviorism's disdain of introspective methods.

Psychophysics (the study of the relationship between physical sensory input and consequent psychological state or response), where the introspective psychologists had found their greatest success, underwent a subtle shift in this period from a focus on subjective methods—methods that involve asking subjects to report on their experiences or percepts—to a focus on objective methods such as asking subjects to report on states of the outside world, including insisting that subjects guess even when they feel they don't know or have no relevant conscious experience (especially with the rise of “signal detection theory” in psychophysics: Green and Swets 1966; Cheesman and Merikle 1986; Macmillan and Creelman 1991; Merikle, Smilek, and Eastwood 2001). Perhaps in accord with transparency views of introspection (Section 2.3.4 above), the two types of instruction to subjects seem very similar (compare the subjective “tell me if you visually experience a flash of light” with the objective “tell me if the light flashes”). On the other hand, perhaps in tension with transparency views, subjective and objective instructions seem sometimes to differ importantly, especially in cases of known illusion, Gestalt effects such as perceived grouping, stimuli near the limits of perceivability, and the experience of ambiguous figures (Boring 1921; Merikle, Smilek, and Eastwood 2001; Siewert 2004).

In no period, however, were introspective methods entirely abandoned by psychologists, and in the last few decades, they have begun to make something of a comeback, especially with the rise of the interdisciplinary field of “consciousness studies” (see, e.g., Jack and Roepstorff, eds., 2003, 2004). Ericsson and Simon (1984/1993; to be discussed further in Section 4.2.3 below) have advocated the use of “think-aloud protocols” and immediately retrospective reports in the study of problem solving. Other researchers have emphasized introspective methods in the study of imagery (Marks 1985; Kosslyn, Reisbert, and Behrmann 2006) and emotion (Lambie and Marcel 2002; Barrett et al. 2007).

Beeper methodologies have been developed to facilitate immediate retrospection, especially by Hurlburt (1990, 2011; Hurlburt and Heavey 2006; Hurlburt and Schwitzgebel 2007) and Csikszentmihalyi (Larson and Csikszentmihalyi 1983; Hektner, Schmidt, and Csikszentmihalyi 2007). Traditional immediately retrospective methods required the introspective observer in the laboratory somehow to intentionally refrain from introspecting the target experience as it occurs, arguably a difficult task. Hurlburt and Csikszentmihalyi, in contrast, give participants beepers to wear during ordinary, everyday activity. The beepers are timed to sound only at long intervals, surprising participants and triggering an immediately retrospective assessment of their “inner experience”, emotion, or thoughts in the moment before the beep.

Introspective or subjective reports of conscious experience have also played an important role in the search for the “neural correlates of consciousness” (as reviewed in Rees and Frith 2007; Tononi and Koch 2008; Prinz 2012; see also Varela 1996). One paradigm is for researchers to present ambiguous sensory stimuli, holding them constant over an extended period, noting what neural changes correlate with changes in subjective reports of experience. For example, in “binocular rivalry” methods, two different images (e.g., a face and a house) are presented, one to each eye. Participants typically say that only one image is visible at a time, with the visible image switching every few seconds. Researchers have sometimes reported finding evidence that activity in “early” visual areas (such as V1) is not temporally coupled with reported changes in visual experience, while changes in conscious percept are better temporally coupled with activity in frontal and parietal areas further downstream and to large-scale changes in neural synchronization or oscillation; but the evidence is disputed (Lumer, Friston, and Rees 1998; Tong et al. 1998; Tononi et al. 1998; Polonsky et al. 2000; Kreiman, Fried, and Koch 2002; Moutoussis and Zeki 2002; Tong, Meng, and Blake 2006; Kamphuisen, Bauer, and van Ee 2008; Sandberg et al. 2013; Ishiku and Zeki 2014). Another version of the ambiguous sensory stimuli paradigm involves presenting the subject with an ambiguous figure such as the Rubin faces-vase figure:

Using this paradigm, researchers have found neuronal changes both in early visual areas and in later areas, as well as changes in widespread neuronal synchrony, that correspond temporally with subjective reports of flipping between one way and another of seeing the ambiguous figure (Kleinschmidt et al. 1998; Rodriguez et al. 1999; Ilg et al. 2008; Parkkonen et al. 2008; de Graaf et al. 2011). In masking paradigms, stimuli are briefly presented then followed by a “mask”. On some trials, subjects report seeing the stimuli, while on others they don't. In trials in which the subject reports that stimulus was visually experienced, researchers have tended to find higher levels of activity through at least some of the downstream visual pathways as well as spontaneous electrical oscillations near 40 Hz (Dehaene et al. 2001; Summerfield, Jack, and Burgess 2002; Del Cul, Baillet, and Dehaene 2007; Quiroga et al. 2008). However, it remains contentious how properly to interpret such attempts to find neural correlates of consciousness (Noë and Thompson 2004; Overgaard, Sandberg, and Jensen 2008; Tononi and Koch 2008; Dehaene and Changeux 2011; Aru, Bachmann, Singer, and Melloni 2012; de Graaf, Hsieh, and Sack 2012).

If we report our attitudes by introspecting upon them, then much of survey research is also introspective, though psychologists have not generally explicitly described it as such. As with subjective vs. objective methods in psychophysics, there appears to be only a slight difference between subjectively phrased questions (“Do you approve of the President's handling of the war?”, “Do you think gay marriage should be legalized?”) and objectively phrased questions (“Has the President handled the war well?”, “Should gay marriage be legalized?”). This would seem to support the observation at the core of transparency theory (discussed in Section 2.3.4 above) that questions about the mind and questions about the outside world often call for the same type of reflection.

4. The Accuracy of Introspection

4.1 varieties of privilege.

It's plausible to suppose that people have some sort of privileged access to at least some of their own mental states or processes: You know about your own mind, or at least some aspects of it, in a different way and better than you know about other people's minds, and maybe also in a different way and better than you know about the outside world. Consider pain. It seems you know your own pains differently and better than you know mine, differently and (perhaps) better than you know about the coffee cup in your hand. If so, perhaps that special “first-person” privileged knowledge arises through something like introspection, in one or more of the senses described in Section 2 above.

Just as there is a diversity of methods for acquiring knowledge of or reaching judgments about one's own mental states and processes, to which the label “introspection” applies with more or less or disputable accuracy, so also is there a diversity of forms of “privileged access”, with different kinds of privilege and to which the idea of access applies with more or less or disputable accuracy. And as one might expect, the different introspective methods do not all align equally well with the different varieties of privilege.

A substantial philosophical tradition, going back at least to Descartes (1637/1985; 1641/1984; also Augustine c. 420 C.E./1998), ascribes a kind of epistemic perfection to at least some of our judgments (or thoughts or beliefs or knowledge) about our own minds—infallibility, indubitability, incorrigibility, or self-intimation. Consider the judgment (thought, belief, etc.) that P , where P is a proposition self-ascribing a mental state or process (for example P might be I am in pain , or I believe that it is snowing , or I am thinking of a dachshund ). The judgment that P is infallible just in case, if I make that judgment, it is not possible that P is false. It is indubitable just in case, if I make the judgment, it is not possible for me to doubt the truth of P . It is incorrigible just in case, if I make the judgment, it is not possible for anyone else to show that P is false. And it is self-intimating if it is not possible for P to be true without my reaching the judgment (thought, belief, etc.) that it is true. Note that the direction of implication for the last of these is the reverse of the first three. Infallibility, indubitability, and incorrigibility all have the form: “If I judge (think, believe, etc.) that P , then …”, while self-intimation has the form “If P , then I judge (think, believe, etc.) that P ”. All four theses also admit of weakening by adding conditions to the antecedent “if” clause (e.g., “If I judge that P as a result of normal introspective processes, then …”). (See Alston 1971 for a helpful dissection of these distinctions; all admit of variations and nuance. Also note that some philosophers [e.g. Ayer 1936/1946; Armstrong 1963; Chalmers 2003; Tye 2009] use “incorrigibility” to mean infallibility as defined here, while others [e.g., Ayer 1963; Alston 1971; Rorty 1970; Dennett 2000] use it with the more etymologically specific meaning of [something like] “incapable of correction”.)

Descartes (1641/1984) famously endorsed the indubitability of “I think”, which he extends also to such mental states as doubting, understanding, affirming, and seeming to have sensory perceptions. He also appears to claim that the thought or affirmation that I am in such states is infallibly true. He was followed in this—especially in his infallibilism—by Locke (1690/1975), Hume (1739/1978), twentieth-century thinkers such as Husserl (1913/1982), Ayer (1936/1946, 1963), Lewis (1946), and the early Shoemaker (1963), and many others. Historical arguments for indubitability and infallibility have tended to center on intuitive appeals to the apparent impossibility of doubting or going wrong about such matters as whether one is having a thought with a certain content or is experiencing pain or having a visual experience as of seeing red.

Recent infallibilists have added to this intuitive appeal structural arguments based on self-fulfillment accounts of introspection or self-knowledge (see Section 2.3.1 above)—generally while also narrowing the scope of infallibility, for example to thoughts about thoughts (Burge 1988, 1996), or to “pure” phenomenal judgments about consciousness (Chalmers 2003; see also Wright 1998; Gertler 2001; Horgan, Tienson, and Graham 2006; Horgan and Kriegel 2007; Tye 2009; with important predecessors in Brentano 1874/1973; Husserl 1913/1982). The intuitive idea behind all these structural arguments is that somehow the self-ascriptive thought or judgment contains the mental state or process self-ascribed: the thought that I am thinking of a pink elephant contains the thought of a pink elephant; the judgment that I am having a visual experience of redness contains the red experience itself.

In contrast, self/other parity (Section 2.1) and self-detection (Section 2.2) accounts of introspection or self-knowledge appear to stand in tension with infallibilism. If introspection or self-knowledge involves a causal process from a mental state to an ontologically distinct self-ascription of that state, it appears that, however reliable such a process may generally be, there is inevitably room in principle for interference and error. Minimally, it seems, stroke, quantum accident, or clever neurosurgery could break otherwise generally reliable relationships between target mental states and the self-ascriptions of those states. Similar considerations apply to self-shaping (Section 2.3.2) and expressivist (Section 2.3.3) accounts, to the extent that these are interpreted causally rather than constitutively.

Introspective incorrigibility, as opposed to either infallibility or indubitability, was held by Rorty (1970) to be “the mark of the mental”—and thus as applying to a wide range of mental states—and has also been embraced more recently by Dennett (2000, 2002). The idea behind incorrigibility, recall, is that no one else could show your self-ascriptions to be false; or we might say, more qualifiedly and a bit differently, that if you arrive at the right kind of self-ascriptive judgment (perhaps an introspectively based judgment about a currently ongoing conscious process that survives critical reflection), then no one else, perhaps not even you in the future, aware of this, can rationally hold that judgment to be mistaken. If I judge that right now I am in severe pain, and I do so as a result of considering introspectively whether I am indeed in such pain (as opposed to, say, merely inferring that I am in pain based on outward behavior), and if I pause to think carefully about whether I really am in pain and conclude that I indeed am, then no one else who is aware of this can rationally believe that I'm not in pain, regardless of what my outward behavior might be (say, calm and relaxed) or what shows up in the course of brain imaging (say, no activation in brain centers normally associated with pain).

Incorrigibility does not imply infallibility: I may not actually be in pain, even if no one could show that I'm not. Consequently, incorrigibility is compatible with a broader array of sources of self-knowledge than is infallibility. Neither Rorty nor Dennett, for example, appear to defend incorrigibility by appeal to self-fulfillment accounts of introspection (though in both cases, interpreting their positive accounts is difficult). Causal accounts of self-knowledge may be compatible with incorrigibility if the causal connections underwriting the incorrigible judgments are vastly more trustworthy than judgments obtained without the benefit of this sort of privileged access. Of course, unless one embraces a strict self-fulfillment account, with its attendant infallibilism, one will want to rule out abnormal cases such as quantum accident; hence the need for qualifications.

Self-intimating mental states are those such that, if a person (or at least a person with the right background capacities) has them, she necessarily believes or judges or knows that she does. Conscious states are often held to be in some sense self-intimating, in that the mere having of them involves, requires, or implies some sort of representation or awareness of those states. Brentano argues that consciousness, for example, of an outward stimulus like a sound, “clearly occurs together with consciousness of this consciousness”, that is, the consciousness is “of the whole mental act in which the sound is presented and in which the consciousness itself exists concomitantly” (1874/1995, 129; see also phenomenological approaches to self-consciousness ). Recent “higher order” and “same order” theories of consciousness (Armstrong 1968; Rosenthal 1990, 2005; Gennaro 1996; Lycan 1996; Carruthers 2005; Kriegel 2009; see also higher-order theories of consciousness ) explain consciousness in terms of some thought, perception, or representation of the mental state that is conscious—the presence of that thought, perception, or representation being what makes the target state conscious. (On same order theories, the target mental state, or an aspect of it, represents itself, with no need for a distinct higher order state.) Thus, Horgan and others have described consciousness as “self-presenting” (Horgan, Tienson, and Graham 2005; Horgan and Kriegel 2007; the usage appears to follow Chisholm 1981, but Chisholm actually has an indubitability rather than a self-intimation thesis in mind). Shoemaker (1995) argues that beliefs—as long as they are “available” (i.e., readily deployed in inference, assent, practical reasoning, etc.), which needn't require that they are occurrently conscious—are self-intimating for individuals with sufficient cognitive capacity. Shoemaker's idea is that if the belief that P is available in the relevant sense, then one is disposed to do things like say “I believe P ”, and such dispositions are themselves constitutive of believing that one believes that P .

Self-intimation claims (unlike infallibility, indubitability, and incorrigibility claims) are not usually cast as claims about “introspection”. This may be because knowledge acquired through self-intimation would appear to be constant and automatic, thus violating the effort condition on introspection (condition 6 in Section 1.1 above).

A number of philosophers have argued for forms of first-person privilege involving some sort of epistemic guarantee—not just conditional accuracy as a matter of empirical fact, but something more robust than that—without embracing infallibility, indubitability, incorrigibility, or self-intimation in the senses described in Section 4.1.1 above.

Shoemaker (1968), for example, argues that self-knowledge of certain psychological facts such as “I am waving my arm” or “I see a canary”, when arrived at “in the ordinary way (without the aid of mirrors, etc.)”, is immune to error through misidentification relative to the first-person pronoun (see also Campbell 1999; Pryor 1999; Bar-On 2004; Hamilton 2008). That is, although one may be wrong about waving one's arm (perhaps the nerves to your arm were recently severed unbeknownst to you) or about seeing a canary (perhaps it's a goldfinch), one cannot be wrong due to mistakenly identifying the person waving the arm or seeing the canary as you , when in fact it is someone else. This immunity arises, Shoemaker argues, because there is no need for identification in the first place, and thus no opportunity for mis -identification. In this respect, Shoemaker argues, knowledge that a particular arm that is moving is your arm (not immune to misidentification since maybe it's someone else's arm, misidentified in the mirror) is different from the knowledge that you are moving your arm—knowledge, that is, of what Searle (1983) calls an “intention in action”.

Shoemaker has also argued for the conceptual impossibility of introspective self-blindness with respect to one's beliefs, desires, and intentions, and for somewhat different reasons one's pains (1988, 1994b). A self-blind creature, by Shoemaker's definition, would be a rational creature with a conception of the relevant mental states, and who can entertain the thought that she has this or that belief, desire, intention, or pain, but who nonetheless utterly lacks introspective access to the type of mental state in question. A self-blind creature could still gain “third person” knowledge of the mental states in question, through observing her own behavior, reading textbooks, and the like. (Thus, strict self/other parity accounts of self-knowledge of the sort described in Section 2.1 are accounts according to which one is self-blind in Shoemaker's sense.) Shoemaker's case against self-blindness with respect to belief turns on the dilemma of whether the self-blind creature can avoid “Moore-paradoxical” sentences (see Moore 1942, 1944/1993; Shoemaker 1995) like “it's raining but I don't believe that it's raining” in which the subject asserts both P and that she doesn't believe that P . If the subject is truly self-blind, Shoemaker suggests, there should be cases in which her best evidence is both that P and that she doesn't believe that P (the latter, perhaps, based on misleading facts about her behavior). But if the subject asserts “ P but I don't believe that P ” in such cases, she does not (contra the initial supposition) really have a rational command of the nature of belief and assertion; and thus it's not a genuine case of self-blindness as originally intended. Alternatively, perhaps the creature can reliably avoid such Moore-paradoxical sentences, self-attributing belief in an apparently normal way. But then, Shoemaker suggests, it seems that she is indistinguishable from normal people in thought and behavior and hence not self-blind. For desire, intention, and pain, too, Shoemaker aims to reveal incoherences between having a rational command of the concepts in question and behaving as though one were systematically ignorant of or mistaken about those states. Shoemaker uses his case against self-blindness as part of his argument against self-detection accounts of introspection (described in Section 2.2 above): If introspection were a matter of detecting the presence of states that exist independently of the introspective judgment or belief, then it ought to be possible for the faculty enabling the detection to break down entirely, as in the case of blindness, deafness, etc., in outward perception (see also Nichols and Stich 2003, who argue that schizophrenia provides such a case).

Burge has influentially asserted that brute errors about “present, ordinary, accessible propositional attitudes [such as belief and desire]” are impossible or at least subject to “severe limits”—where a “brute error” is an error that “indicates no rational failure and no malfunction in the mistaken individual” such as commonly occur in ordinary perception due to “misleading natural conditions or look-alike substitutes” (1988, 657–658; 1996, 103–104). However, Burge offers little argument for this claim, apart from the argument mentioned in Sections 2.3.1 and 4.1.1 above that for certain sorts of self-ascriptions error in general (and not just “brute error”) is impossible, due to the “self-verifying” nature of such self-ascriptions.

Dretske (1995, 2004) argues that we have infallible knowledge of the content of our attitudes without necessarily knowing (or even having a very good idea about) the attitude we take toward those contents. For example, if I believe that it will rain tomorrow , I have infallibly accurate information, which I may then access introspectively, regarding the presence of a mental state with a certain content—the content “it will rain tomorrow”—but I may often have little or no information about the fact that my attitude toward that content is the particular attitude it is—belief, in this case (as opposed to supposition or hope). This view follows from Dretske's accepting something like a containment account of the introspection of the content of the attitude (the introspective judgment employing the same content as the target attitude; see Section 2.3.1 above, especially the discussion of Burge), while he sees knowledge of the attitude one has toward that content as requiring complex information about the causal role and history of that mental state.

Transcendental arguments for the accuracy of certain sorts of self-knowledge offer a different sort of epistemic guarantee—“transcendental arguments” being arguments that assume the existence of some sort of experience or capacity, then develop insights about the background conditions necessary for that experience or capacity, and finally conclude that those background conditions must in fact be met. Burge (1996; see also Shoemaker 1988) argues that to be capable of “critical reasoning” one must be able to recognize one's own attitudes, knowledgeably evaluating, identifying, and reviewing one's beliefs, desires, commitments, suppositions, etc., where these mental states are known to be the states they are. Since we are (by assumption, for the sake of transcendental argument) capable of critical reasoning, we must have some knowledge of our attitudes. Bilgrami (2006) argues that we can only be held responsible for actions if we know the beliefs and desires that “rationalize” our actions; since we can (by assumption) sometimes be held responsible, we must sometimes know our beliefs and desires. Wright (1989) argues that the “language game” of ascribing “intentional states” such as belief and desire to oneself and others requires as a background condition that self-ascriptions have special authority within that game. Given that we successfully play this language game, we must indeed have the special authority that we assume and others grant us in the context of the game.

Developing an analogy from Wright (1998), if it's your turn with the kaleidoscope, you have a type of privileged perspective on the shapes and colors it presents. If someone else in the room wants to know what color dominates, for example, the most straightforward course would be to ask you. But this type of privileged access comes with no guarantee. At least in principle, you might be quite wrong about the tumbling shapes. You might be dazzled by afterimages, or momentarily confused, or hallucinating, or (unbeknownst to you) colorblind. (Yes, people often don't know they are colorblind, a point stressed by Kornblith 1998.) It is also at least in principle possible that others may know better than you, perhaps even systematically so, what is transpiring in the kaleidoscope. You might think the figure shows octagonal symmetry, but the rest of us, familiar with the kaleidoscope's design, might know that the symmetry is hexagonal. A brilliant engineer may invent a kaleidoscope state detector that can dependably reveal from outside the shape, color, and position of the tumbling chunks.

Wright raises this analogy to suggest that people's privilege with respect to certain aspects of their mental lives must be different from that of the person with the kaleidoscope; but other philosophers, especially those who embrace self-detection accounts of introspection, should find the analogy at least somewhat apt: Introspective privilege is akin to the privilege of having a unique and advantageous sensory perspective on something. Metaphorically speaking, we are the only ones who can gaze directly at our attitudes or our stream of experience, while others must rely on us or on outward signs. Less metaphorically, in generating introspective judgments (or beliefs or knowledge) about one's own mentality one employs a detection process available to no one else. It is then an empirical question how accurate the deliverances of this process are; but on the assumption that the deliverances are in a broad range of conditions at least somewhat accurate and more accurate than the typical judgments other people make about those same aspects of your mind, you have a “privileged” perspective. Typically, advocates of self-detection models of introspection regard the mechanism or cognitive process generating introspective judgments or beliefs as highly reliable in roughly this way, but not infallible, and not immune to correction by other people (Armstrong 1968; Churchland 1988; Hill 1981, 2009; Lycan 1996; Nichols and Stich 2003; Goldman 2000, 2006).

4.2 Empirical Evidence on the Accuracy of Introspection

The arguments of the previous section are a priori in at least the broad sense of that term (the psychologists' sense): They depend on general conceptual considerations and armchair folk psychology rather than on empirical research. To these might be added the argument, due to Boghossian (1989) that “externalism” about the content of our attitudes (the view that our attitudes depend constitutively not just on what is going on internally but also on facts about our environment; Putnam 1975; Burge 1979) seems to problematize introspective self-knowledge of those attitudes. This issue will not be treated here, since it is amply covered in the entries on externalism about mental content and externalism and self-knowledge .

Now we turn to empirical research on our self-knowledge of those aspects of our minds often thought to be accessible to introspection. Since character traits are not generally regarded as introspectible aspects of our mentality, we'll skip the large literature on the accuracy or inaccuracy of our judgments about them (e.g., Taylor and Brown 1988; Paulhus and John 1998; Funder 1999; Vazire 2010; see also Haybron's 2008 skeptical perspective on our knowledge of how happy we are); nor will we discuss self-knowledge of subpersonal, nonconscious mental processes, such as the processes underlying visual recognition of color and shape.

As a general matter, while a priori accounts of the epistemology of introspection have tended to stress its privilege and accuracy, empirical accounts have tended to stress its failures.

Perhaps the most famous argument in the psychological literature on introspection and self-knowledge is Nisbett and Wilson's argument that we have remarkably poor knowledge of the causes of, and processes underlying, our behavior and attitudes (Nisbett and Wilson 1977; Nisbett and Ross 1980; Wilson 2002). Section 2.1 above briefly mentioned their emblematic finding that people in a shopping mall were often ignorant of a major factor—position—influencing their judgments about the quality of pairs of stockings. In Nisbett and Bellows (1977), also briefly mentioned above, participants were asked to assess the influence of various factors on their judgments about features of a supposed job applicant. As in Nisbett and Wilson's stocking study, participants denied the influence of some factors that were in fact influential; for example, they denied that the information that they would meet the applicant influenced their judgments about the applicant's flexibility. (It actually had a major influence, as assessed by comparing the judgments of participants who were told and not told that they would meet the applicant.) Participants also attributed influence to factors that were not in fact influential; for example, they falsely reported that the information that the applicant accidentally knocked over a cup of coffee during the interview influenced “how sympathetic the person seems” to them. Nisbett and Bellows found that ordinary observers' hypothetical ratings of the influence of the various factors on the various judgments closely paralleled the participants' own ratings of the factors influencing them—a finding used by Nisbett to argue that people have no special access to causal influences on their judgments and instead rely on the same sorts of theoretical considerations outside observers rely on (the self/other parity view described in Section 2.1). Despite some objections (such as White 1988), both psychologists and philosophers now tend to accept Nisbett's and Wilson's view that there is at best only a modest first-person advantage in assessing the factors influencing our judgments and behavior.

In series of experiments, Gazzaniga (1995) presented commissurotomy patients (people with severed corpus callosum) with different visual stimuli to each hemisphere of the brain. With cross-hemispheric communication severely impaired due to the commissurotomy, the left hemisphere, controlling speech, had information about one part of the visual stimulus, while the right hemisphere, controlling some aspects of movement (especially the left hand) had information about a different part. Gazzaniga reported finding that when these “split brain” patients were asked to explain why they did something, when that action was clearly caused by input to the right, non-verbal hemisphere, the left hemisphere would sometimes fluently confabulate an explanation. For example, Gazzaniga reports presenting an instruction like “laugh” to the right hemisphere, making the patient laugh. When asked why he laughed, the patient would say something like “You guys come up and test us every month. What a way to make a living!” (1393). When a chicken claw was shown to the left hemisphere and snow scene to the right, and the patient was asked to select an appropriate picture from an array, the right hand would point to a chicken and the left hand to a snow shovel, and when asked why she selected those two things, the patient would say something like “Oh, that's simple. The chicken claw goes with the chicken and you need a shovel to clean out the chicken shed” (ibid.). Similar confabulation about motives is sometimes (but not always) seen in people whose behavior is, unbeknownst to them, driven by post-hypnotic suggestion (Richet 1884; Moll 1889/1911), and in disorders such as hemineglect (anosognosia), blindness denial (Anton's syndrome), and Korsakoff's syndrome (Hirstein 2005).

In a normal population, Johansson and collaborators (Johansson et al. 2005; Johansson et al. 2006) manually displayed to participants pairs of pictures of women's faces. On each trial, the participant was to point to the face he found more attractive. The picture of that face was then centered before the participant while the other face was hidden. On some trials, participants were asked to explain the reasons for their choices while continuing to look at the selected face. On a few key trials, the experimenters used sleight-of-hand to present to the participant the face that was not selected as though it had been the face selected. Strikingly, the switch was noticed only 28% of the time. What's more, when the change was not detected participants actually gave explanations for their choice that appealed to specific features of the unselected face that were not possessed by the selected face 13% of the time. For example, one participant claimed to have chosen the face before him “because I love blondes” when in fact he had chosen a dark-haired face (Johansson et al. 2006, 690). Johansson and colleagues failed to find any systematic differences in the explanations of choice between the manipulated and non-manipulated trials, using a wide variety of measures. They found, for example, no difference in linguistic markers of confidence (including pauses in speech), emotionality, specificity of detail, complexity or length of description, or general position in semantic space. These results, like Nisbett's and Wilson's, suggest that at least some of the time when people think they are explaining the bases of their decisions, they are instead merely theorizing or confabulating.

Wegner has found that people can often be manipulated into believing that they willed or intended behavior that is in fact caused by another person's manipulation and, conversely, that they exerted no control over movements that were in fact their own—as with Ouija boards, with or without a cheating, intentionally directive confederate (Wegner and Wheatley 1999; Wegner 2002). The literature on “cognitive dissonance” is replete with cases in which participants' attitudes appear to change for reasons they do, or would, deny. According to cognitive dissonance theory, when people behave or appear to behave counternormatively (e.g., incompetently, foolishly, immorally), they will tend to adjust their attitudes so as to make the behavior seem less counternormative or “dissonant” (Festinger 1957; Aronson 1968; Cooper and Fazio 1984; Stone and Cooper 2001). For example, people induced to falsely describe as enjoyable a monotonous task they've just completed will tend, later, to report having a more positive attitude toward the task then those not induced to lie (though much less so if they were handsomely paid to lie in which case the behavior is not clearly counternormative; Festinger and Carlsmith 1959; but see Bem 1967, 1972 for an argument that the attitude doesn't change but only the report of it). Presumably, if such attitude changes were known to the subject they would generally fail to have their dissonance-reducing effect. Research psychologists have also confirmed such familiar phenomena as “sour grapes” (Lyubomirsky and Ross 1999; Kay, Jiminez, and Jost 2002) and “self-deception” (Mele 2001) which presumably also involve ignorance of the factors driving the relevant judgments and actions. And of course the Freudian psychoanalytic tradition has also long held that people often have only poor knowledge of their motives and the influences on their attitudes (Wollheim 1981; Cavell 2006).

In light of this empirical research, no major philosopher now holds (perhaps no major philosopher ever held) that we have infallible, indubitable, incorrigible, or self-intimating knowledge of the causes of our judgments, decisions, and behavior. Perhaps weaker forms of privilege also come under threat. But the question arises: Whatever failures there may be in assessing the causes of our attitudes and behavior, are those failures failures of introspection , properly construed? Psychologists tend to cast these results as failures of “introspection”, but if it turns out that a very different and more trustworthy process underwrites our knowledge of some other aspects of our minds—such as what our present attitudes are (however caused) or our currently ongoing or recently past conscious experience—then perhaps we can call only that process introspection, thereby retaining some robust form of introspective privilege while acceding to the psychological consensus regarding (what we would now call non-introspective) first-person knowledge of causes. Indeed, few contemporary philosophical accounts of introspection or privileged self-knowledge highlight, as the primary locus of privilege, the causes of our attitudes and behavior (though Bilgrami 2006 is a notable exception). Thus, the literature reviewed in this section can be interpreted as suggesting that the causes of our behavior are not, after all, the sorts of things to which we have introspective access.

Research psychologists have generally not been as skeptical of our knowledge of our attitudes as they have been of our knowledge of the causes of our attitudes (Section 4.2.1 above). In fact, many of the same experiments that purport to show inaccurate knowledge of the causes of our attitudes nonetheless rely unguardedly on self-report for assessment of the attitudes themselves—a feature of those experiments criticized by Bem (1967). Attitudinal surveys in psychology and social science generally rely on participants' self-report as the principal source of evidence about attitudes (de Vaus 1985/2002; Sirken et al. (eds.) 1999). However, as in the case of motives and causes, there's a long tradition in clinical psychology skeptical of our self-knowledge of our attitudes, giving a large role to “unconscious” motives and attitudes.

A key challenge in assessing the accuracy of people's beliefs or judgments about their attitudes is the difficulty of accurately measuring attitudes independently of self-report. There is at present no tractable measure of attitude that is generally seen by philosophers as overriding individuals' own reports about their attitudes. However, in the psychological literature, “implicit” measures of attitudes—measures of attitudes that do not reply on self-report—have recently been gaining considerable attention (see Wittenbrink and Schwarz, eds., 2007; Petty, Fazio, and Briñol, eds., 2009). Such measures are sometimes thought capable of revealing unconscious attitudes or implicit attitudes either unavailable to introspection or erroneously introspected (Wilson, Lindsey, and Schooler 2000; Kihlstrom 2004; Lane et al. 2007; though see Hahn et al. forthcoming).

Much of the leading research on implicit attitude measures has concerned racism, in accord with the view that racist attitudes, though common, are considered socially undesirable and therefore often not self-ascribed even when present. For example, Campbell, Kruskal, and Wallace (1966) explored the use of seating distance as an index of racial attitudes, noting that racially Black and White students tended to aggregate in classroom seating arrangements. Using facial electromyography (EMG), Vanman et al. (1997) found (racially) White participants to display facial responses indicative of negative affect more frequently when asked to imagine co-operative activity with Black than with White partners—results interpreted as indicative of racist attitudes. Cunningham et al. (2004) showed White and Black faces to White participants while participants were undergoing fMRI brain imaging. They found less amygdala activation when participants looked at faces from their own group than when participants looked at other faces; and since amygdala activation is generally associated with negative emotion, they interpreted this tendency suggesting a negative attitude toward outgroup members (see also Hart et al 1990; and for discussion Ito and Cacioppo 2007).

Much of the recent implicit attitude research has focused on response priming and interference in speeded tasks. In priming research, a stimulus (the “prime”) is briefly displayed, followed by a mask that hides it, and then a second stimulus (the “target”) is displayed. The participant's task is to respond as swiftly as possible to the target, typically with a classification judgment. In evaluative priming, for example, the participant is primed with a positively or negatively valenced word or picture (e.g., snake), then asked to make a swift judgment about whether the subsequently presented target word (e.g., “disgusting”) is good or bad, or has some other feature (e.g., belongs to a particular category). Generally, negative primes will speed response for negative targets while delaying response for positive targets, and positive primes will do the reverse. Researchers have found that photographs of Black faces, whether presented visibly or whether presented so quickly as to be subliminal, tend to facilitate the categorization of negative targets and delay the categorization of positive targets for White participants—a result widely interpreted as revealing racist attitudes (Fazio et al. 1995; Dovidio et al. 1997; Wittenbrink, Judd, and Park 1997). In the Implicit Association Test , respondents are asked to respond disjunctively to combined categories, giving for example one response if they see either a dark-skinned face or a positively valenced word and a different response if they see either a light-skinned face or a negatively valenced word. As in evaluative priming tasks, White respondents tend to respond more slowly when asked to pair dark-skinned faces with positively valenced words than with negatively valenced words, which is interpreted as revealing a negative attitude or association (Greenwald, McGhee, and Schwartz 1998; Lane et al. 2007).

As mentioned above, such implicit measures are often interpreted as revealing attitudes to which people have poor or no introspective access. The evidence that people lack introspective knowledge of such attitudes generally turns on the low correlations between such implicit measures of racism and more explicit measures such as self-report—though due to the recognized social undesirability of racial prejudice, it is difficult to disentangle self-presentational from self-knowledge factors in self-reports (Fazio et al. 1995; Greenwald, McGhee, and Schwartz 1998; Wilson, Lindsey, and Schooler 2000; Greenwald and Nosek 2009). People who appear racist by implicit measures might disavow racism and inhibit racist patterns of response on explicit measures (such as when asked to rate the attractiveness of faces of different races) because they don't want to be seen as racist—a motivation that might drive them whether or not they have accurate self-knowledge of their racist attitudes. Still, it seems prima facie plausible that people have at best limited knowledge of the patterns of association that drive their responses on priming and other implicit measures.

But what do such tests really measure? In philosophy, Zimmerman (2007) and Gendler (2008a, 2008b) have argued that measures like the Implicit Association Test do not measure actual racist beliefs but rather something else, something under less rational control (Gendler calls them “aliefs”). In psychology, Gawronski and Bodenhausen (2006) advance a model according to which there is a substantial difference between implicit attitudes, defined in terms of associative processes, and explicit attitudes which have a propositional structure and are guided by standards of truth and consistency (see also Wilson, Lindsey, and Schooler 2000; Greenwald and Nosek 2009). On such a model, as on Zimmerman's and Gendler's views, a person with implicit racist associations may nonetheless have fully and genuinely egalitarian propositional beliefs. To the extent attitudes are held to be reflected in, or even defined by, our explicit judgments about the matter in question and also, differently but perhaps not wholly separably (see Section 2.3.4 above), our explicit judgments about our attitudes toward the matter in question, our self-knowledge would seem to be correspondingly secure and implicit measures beside the point. To the extent attitudes are held to crucially involve swift and automatic, or unreflective, patterns of reaction and association, our self-knowledge of them would appear to be correspondingly problematic, corrigible by data from implicit measures (Bohner and Dickel 2011; Schwitzgebel 2011a).

In a different vein, Carruthers (2011; see also Rosenthal 2001; Bem 1967, 1972) argues that the evidence of Nisbett, Gazzaniga, Wegner, and others (reviewed in Section 4.2.1 above) shows that people confabulate not just in reporting the causes of their attitudes but also in reporting the attitudes themselves. For example, Carruthers suggests that if someone in Nisbett and Wilson's famous 1977 study confabulates “I thought this pair was softest” as an explanation of her choice of the rightmost pair of stockings, she errs not only about the cause of her choice but also in ascribing to herself the judgment that the pair was softest. On this basis, Carruthers adopts a self/other parity view (see Section 2.1 above) of our self-knowledge of our attitudes, holding that we can only introspect, in the strict sense, conscious experiences like those that arise in perception and imagery.

Currently ongoing conscious experience—or maybe immediately past conscious experience (if we hold that introspective judgment must temporally follow the state or process introspected, or if we take seriously the concerns raised in Section 3.2 about the self-undermining of the introspective process)—is both the most universally acknowledged target of the introspective process and the target most commonly thought to be known with a high degree of privilege. Infallibility, indubitability, incorrigibility, and self-intimation claims (see Section 4.1.1) are most commonly made for self-knowledge of states such as being in pain or having a visual experience as of the color red, where these states are construed as qualitative states, or subjective experiences, or aspects of our phenomenology or consciousness. (All these terms are intended interchangeably to refer to what Block [1995], Chalmers [1996], and other contemporary philosophers call “phenomenal consciousness”.) If attitudes are sometimes conscious, then we might also be capable of introspecting those attitudes as part of our capacity to introspect conscious experience generally (Goldman 2006; Hill 2009).

It's difficult to study the accuracy of self-ascriptions of conscious experience for the same reasons it's difficult to study the accuracy of our self-ascriptions of attitudes (Section 4.2.2): There's no widely accepted measure to trump or confirm self-report. In the medical literature on pain, for example, no behavioral or physiological measure of pain is generally thought capable of overriding self-report of current pain, despite the fact that scaling issues remain a problem both within and especially between subjects (Williams, Davies, and Chadury 2000) as does retrospective assessment (Redelmeier and Kahneman 1996). When physiological markers of pain and self-report dissociate, it's by no means clear that the physiological marker should be taken as the more accurate index (for methodological recommendations see Price and Aydede 2005). Corresponding remarks apply to the case of pleasure (Haybron 2008).

As mentioned in Section 3.3 above, early introspective psychologists both asserted the difficulty of accurately introspecting conscious experience and achieved only mixed success in their attempts to obtain scientifically replicable (and thus presumably accurate) data through the use of trained introspectors. In some domains they achieved considerable success and replicability, such as in the construction of the “color solid” (a representation of the three primary dimensions of variation in color experience: hue, saturation, and lightness or brightness), the mapping of the size of “just noticeable differences” between sensations and the “liminal” threshold below which a stimulus is too faint to be experienced, and the (at least roughly) logarithmic relationship between the intensity of a sensory stimulus and the intensity of the resulting experience (the “Weber-Fechner law”). Contemporary psychophysics—the study of the relation between physical stimuli and the resulting sense experiences or percepts—is rooted in these early introspective studies. However, other sorts of phenomena proved resistant to cross-laboratory introspective consensus—such as the possibility or not of imageless thought (see the entry on “ mental imagery ”), the structure of emotion, and the experiential aspects of of attention. Perhaps these facts about the range of early introspective agreement and apparently intractable disagreement cast light on the range over which careful and well-trained introspection is and is not reliable.

Ericsson and Simon (1984/1993; Ericsson 2003) discuss and review relationships between the subject's performance on various problem-solving tasks, her concurrent verbalizations of conscious thoughts (“think aloud protocols”), and her immediately retrospective verbalizations. The existence of good relationships in the predicted directions in many problem-solving tasks lends empirical support to the view that people's reports about their stream of thoughts often accurately reflect those thoughts. For example, Ericsson and Simon find that think-aloud and retrospective reports of thought processes correlate with predicted patterns of eye movement and response latency. Ericsson and Simon also cite studies like that of Hamilton and Sanford (1978), who asked subjects to make yes or no judgments about whether pairs of letters were in alphabetical order (like MO) or not (like RP) and then to describe retrospectively their method for arriving at the judgments. When subjects retrospectively reported knowing the answer “automatically” without an intervening conscious process, reaction times were swift and did not depend on the distance between the letters. When subjects retrospectively reported “running through” a sequential series of letters (such as “LMNO” when prompted with “MO”) reaction times correlated nicely with reported length of run-through. On the other hand, Flavell, Green, and Flavell (1995) report gross and widespread introspective error about recently past and even current (conscious) thought in young children; and Smallwood and Schooler (2006) review literature that suggests that people are not especially good at detecting when their mind is wandering.

In the 20th century, philosophers arguing against infallibilism often devised hypothetical examples in which they suggested it was plausible to attribute introspective error; but even if such examples succeed, they are generally confined to far-fetched scenarios, pathological cases, or very minor or very brief mistakes (e.g., Armstrong 1963; Churchland 1988; Kornblith 1998, with an eye to the distinction between mistakes about current conscious experience and other sorts of mistakes). In the 21st century, philosophical critics of the accuracy of introspective judgments about consciousness shifted their focus to cases of widespread disagreement or (putative) error, either among ordinary people or among research specialists. Dennett (1991), Blackmore (2002), and Schwitzgebel (2011b), for example, argue that most people are badly mistaken about the nature of the experience of peripheral vision. These authors argue that people experience visual clarity only in a small and rapidly moving region of about 1–2 degrees of visual arc, contrary to the (they say) widespread impression most people have that they experience a substantially broader range of stable clarity in the visual field. Other recent arguments against the accuracy of introspective judgments about conscious experience turn on citing the widespread disagreement about whether there is a “phenomenology of thinking” beyond that of imagery and emotion, about whether sensory experience as a whole is “rich” (including for example constant tactile experience of one's feet in one's shoes) or “thin” (limited mostly just to what is in attention at any one time), and about the nature of visual imagery experience (Hurlburt and Schwitzgebel 2007; Bayne and Spener 2010; Schwitzgebel 2011b; though see Hohwy 2011). Irvine (2013) has argued that the methodological problems in this area are so severe that the term “consciousness” should be eliminated from scientific discourse as impossible to effectively operationalize or measure.

  • Alston, William P., 1971, “Varieties of privileged access”, American Philosophical Quarterly , 8: 223–241.
  • Amedi, Amir, Rafael Malach, and Alvaro Pascual-Leone, 2005, “Negative BOLD differentiates visual imagery and perception”, Neuron , 48: 859–872.
  • Aristotle, 3rd c. BCE/1961, De Anima , W.D. Ross (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Armstrong, David M., 1963, “Is introspective knowledge incorrigible?”, Philosophical Review , 72: 417–432.
  • –––, 1968, A materialist theory of the mind , London: Routledge.
  • –––, 1981, The nature of mind and other essays , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 1999, The mind-body problem , Boulder, CO: Westview.
  • Aronson, Elliot, 1968, “Dissonance theory: Progress and problems”, in Theories of cognitive consistency , Robert P. Abelson, et al. (eds.), Chicago: Rand McNally, 112–139.
  • Aru, Jaan, Talis Bachmann, Wolf Singer, and Lucia Melloni, 2012, “Distilling the neural correlates of consciousness”, Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews , 36: 737–746.
  • Augustinus, Aurelius, c. 420 C.E./1998, The city of God against the pagans , R.W. Dyson (tr.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Aydede, Murat, and Güven Güzeldere, 2005, “Cognitive architecture, concepts, and introspection: An information-theoretic solution to the problem of phenomenal consciousness”, Noûs , 39: 197–255.
  • Ayer, A.J., 1936/1946, Language, truth, and logic , 2nd ed., London: Gollancz.
  • –––, 1963, The concept of a person , New York: St. Martin's.
  • Baldwin, James Mark, 1901–1905, Dictionary of philosophy and psychology , New York: Macmillan.
  • Bar-On, Dorit, 2004, Speaking my mind , Oxford: Oxford.
  • Barrett, Lisa Feldman, Batja Mesquita, Kevin N. Ochsner, and James J. Gross, 2007, “The experience of emotion”, Annual Review of Psychology , 58: 373–403.
  • Bayne, Tim, and Michelle Montague, eds., 2011, Cognitive phenomenology , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Bayne, Tim, and Maja Spener, 2010, “Introspective humility”, Philosophical Issues , 20, 1–22.
  • Bem, Daryl J., 1967, “Self-perception: An alternative interpretation of cognitive dissonance phenomena”, Psychological Review , 74: 183–200.
  • –––, 1972, “Self-perception theory”, Advances in Experimental Social Psychology , 6: 1–62.
  • Berkeley, George, 1710/1965, A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge , in Principles, Dialogues, and Philosophical Correspondence , Colin M. Turbayne (ed.), New York: Macmillan, 3–101.
  • Bilgrami, Akeel, 2006, Self-knowledge and resentment , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Blackmore, Susan, 2002, “There is no stream of consciousness”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 9(5–6), 17–28.
  • Block, Ned, 1995, “On a confusion about a function of consciousness”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 18: 227–247.
  • –––, 1996, “Mental paint and mental latex”, Philosophical Issues , 7: 19–49.
  • Boghossian, Paul, 1989, “Content and self-knowledge”, Philosophical Topics , 17: 5–26.
  • Bohner, Gerd, and Nina Dickel, 2011, “Attitudes and attitude change”, Annual Review of Psychology , 62: 391–417.
  • Boring, Edwin G., 1921, “The stimulus-error”, American Journal of Psychology , 32: 449–471.
  • –––, 1953, “A history of introspection”, Psychological Bulletin , 50: 169–189.
  • Boyle, Matthew, 2009, “Two kinds of self-knowledge”, Philosophy & Phenomenological Research , 78: 133–164.
  • Brentano, Franz, 1874/1995, Psychology from an empirical standpoint , 2nd English edition, Antos C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell and Linda L. McAlister (trans.), New York: Routledge.
  • Burge, Tyler, 1979, “Individualism and the mental”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy , 4: 73–121.
  • –––, 1988, “Individualism and self-knowledge”, Journal of Philosophy , 85: 649–663.
  • –––, 1996, “Our entitlement to self-knowledge”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , 96: 91–116.
  • –––, 1998, “Reason and the first person”, in Knowing our own minds , Crispin Wright, Barry C. Smith, and Cynthia Macdonald (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 243–270.
  • Byrne, Alex, 2005, “Introspection”, Philosophical Topics , 33(1): 79–104.
  • –––, 2011a, Knowing that I am thinking, in Self-knowledge , Anthony Hatzimoysis (ed.), Oxford: Oxford.
  • –––, 2011b, Knowing what I want, in Consciousness and the Self , JeeLoo Liu and John Perry (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge.
  • –––, 2011c, Transparency, belief, intention, Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume , 85, 201-221.
  • –––, 2012, in Introspection and Consciousness , Declan Smithies and Daniel Stoljar (eds.), Oxford: Oxford.
  • Campbell, Donald T., William H. Kruskal, and William P. Wallace, 1966, “Seating aggregation as an index of attitude”, Sociometry , 29: 1–15.
  • Campbell, John, 1999, “Immunity to error through misidentification and the meaning of a referring term”, Philosophical Topics , 25(1–2), 89–104.
  • Carruthers, Peter, 2005, Consciousness: Essays from a higher-order perspective , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2011, The Opacity of Mind , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Cavell, Marcia, 2006, Becoming a subject , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Chalmers, David J., 1996, The conscious mind , New York: Oxford.
  • –––, 2003, “The content and epistemology of phenomenal belief”, in Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives , Quentin Smith and Aleksandar Jokic (eds.), Oxford: Oxford, 220–272.
  • Chapman, Dwight W., 1933, “Attensity, clearness, and attention”, American Journal of Psychology , 45: 156–165.
  • Cheesman, Jim, and Philip M. Merikle, 1986, “Distinguishing conscious from unconscious perceptual processes”, Canadian Journal of Psychology , 40: 343–367.
  • Chisholm, Roderick M., 1981, The first person , Brighton, UK: Harvester.
  • Churchland, Paul M., 1988, Matter and consciousness , rev. ed., Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Comte, Auguste, 1830, Cours de philosophie positive , volume 1, Paris: Bacheleier, Libraire pour les Mathématiques.
  • Cooper, Joel, and Russell H. Fazio, 1984, “A new look at dissonance theory”, Advances in Experimental Social Psychology , 17: 229–266.
  • Cui, Xu, Cameron B. Jeter, Dongni Yang, P. Read Montague, and David M. Eagleman, 2007, “Vividness of mental imagery: Individual variability can be measured objectively”, Vision Research , 47: 474–478.
  • Cunningham, William A., et al., 2004, “Separable neural components in the processing of Black and White faces”, Psychological Science , 15: 806–813.
  • de Graaf, Tom A., Maartje c. de Jong, Rainer Goebel, Raymond van Ee, and Alexander T. Sack, 2011, “On the functional relevance of frontal cortex for passive and volunatarily controlled bistable vision”, Cerebral Cortex , 21: 2322–2331.
  • de Graaf, Tom A., Po-Jang Hsieh, and Alexander T. Sack, 2012, “The 'correlates' in neural correlates of consciousness”, Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews , 36: 191–197.
  • De Vaus, David, 1985/2002, Surveys in social research , London: Routledge.
  • Dehaene, Stanislaus, et al., 2001, “Cerebral mechanisms of word masking and unconscious repetition priming”, Nature Neuroscience , 4: 752–758.
  • Dehaene, Stanislaus, and Jean-Pierre Changeux, 2011, “Experimental and theoretical approaches to conscious processing”, Neuron , 70: 200–227.
  • Del Cul, Antoine, Sylvain Baillet, and Stanislas Dehaene, 2007, “Brain dynamics underlying the nonlinear threshold for access to consciousness”, PLoS Biology , 5(10): e260).
  • Dennett, Daniel C., 1987, The intentional stance , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 1991, Consciousness explained , Boston: Little, Brown, and Co.
  • –––, 2000, “The case for rorts”, in Rorty and his critics , R.B. Brandom (ed.), Malden, MA: Blackwell, 91–101.
  • –––, 2002, “How could I be wrong? How wrong could I be?”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 9(5–6): 13–6.
  • Descartes, René, 1637/1985, Discourse on the method , in The philosophical writings of Descartes , vol. 1, John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch (editors and translators), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 111–151.
  • –––, 1641/1984, Meditations on first philosophy , in The philosophical writings of Descartes , vol. 2, John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch (editors and translators,), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1–62.
  • Dovidio, John F., Kerry Kawakami, Craig Johnson, Brenda Johnson, and Adaiah Howard, 1997, “On the nature of prejudice: Automatic and controlled processes”, Journal of Experimental Social Psychology , 33: 510–540.
  • Dretske, Fred, 1995, Naturalizing the mind , Cambridge, MA: MIT.
  • –––, 2004, “Knowing what you think vs. knowing that you think it”, in The externalist challenge , Richard Schantz (ed.), Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 389–399.
  • Ebbinghaus, Hermann, 1885/1913, Memory: A contribution to experimental psychology , Henry A. Ruger and Clara E. Bussenius (translators), New York: Columbia.
  • Ericsson, K. Anders, 2003, “Valid and non-reactive verbalization of thoughts during performance of tasks: Towards a solution to the central problems of introspection as a source of scientific data”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 10(9–10): 1–18.
  • Ericsson, K. Anders, and Herbert A. Simon, 1984/1993, Protocol analysis , rev. ed., Cambridge, MA: MIT.
  • Evans, Gareth, 1982, The varieties of reference , John McDowell (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon; New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Fazio, Russell H., Joni R. Jackson, Bridget C. Dunton, and Carol J. Williams, 1995, “Variability in automatic activation as an unobtrusive measure of racial attitudes: A bona fide pipeline?”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 69(6): 1013–1027.
  • Fechner, Gustav, 1860/1964, Elements of Psychophysics , Helmut E. Adler, Davis H. Howes, and Edwin G. Boring (ed. and trans.), New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.
  • Fernández, Jorgi, 2003, “Privileged access naturalized”, Philosophical Quarterly , 53: 352–372.
  • Festinger, Leon, 1957, A theory of cognitive dissonance , Stanford, CA: Stanford.
  • Festinger, Leon, and James M. Carlsmith, 1959, “Cognitive consequences of forced compliance”, Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology , 58: 203–210.
  • Flavell, John H., Frances L. Green, and Eleanor R. Flavell, 1995, Young children's knowledge about thinking , Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development , 60(1).
  • Fodor, Jerry A., 1983, Modularity of mind , Cambridge, MA: MIT.
  • –––, 1998, Concepts: Where cognitive science went wrong , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Funder, David C., 1999, Personality judgment , London: Academic.
  • Gallois, Andre, 1996, The world without, the mind within , Cambridge: Cambridge.
  • Galton, Francis, 1869/1891, Hereditary genius , rev. ed., New York: Appleton.
  • Gardner, Sebastian, 1993, Irrationality and the philosophy of psychoanalysis , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Gazzaniga, Michael S., 1995, “Consciousness and the cerebral hemispheres”, in The Cognitive Neurosciences , Michael S. Gazzaniga (ed.), Cambridge, MA: MIT, 1391–1400.
  • Gawronski, Bertram, and Galen V. Bodenhausen, 2006, “Associative and propositional processes in evaluation: An integrative review of implicit and explicit attitude change”, Psychological Bulletin , 132: 692–731.
  • Gendler, Tamar Szabó, 2008a, “Alief and Belief”, Journal of Philosophy , 105: 634–663.
  • –––, 2008b, “Alief in Action, and Reaction”, Mind & Language , 23: 552–585.
  • Gennaro, Rocco J., 1996, Consciousness and Self-Consciousness , Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
  • Gertler, Brie, 2000, “The mechanics of self-knowledge”, Philosophical Topics , 28: 125–146.
  • –––, 2001, “Introspecting phenomenal states”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , 63: 305–328.
  • –––, 2011, “Self-knowledge and the transparency of belief”, in Self-knowledge , Anthony Hatzimoysis (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Goldman, Alvin I., 1989, “Interpretation psychologized”, Mind and Language , 4: 161–185.
  • –––, 2000, “Can science know when you're conscious?”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 7(5): 3–22.
  • –––, 2006, Simulating minds , Oxford: Oxford.
  • Gopnik, Alison, 1993a, “How we know our minds: The illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 16: 1–14.
  • –––, 1993b, “Psychopsychology”, Consciousness and Cognition , 2: 264–280.
  • Gopnik, Alison, and Andrew N. Meltzoff, 1994, “Minds, bodies and persons: Young children's understanding of the self and others as reflected in imitation and ‘theory of mind’ research”, in Self-awareness in animals and humans , Sue Taylor Parker, Robert W. Mitchell, and Maria L. Boccia (eds.), New York: Cambridge, 166–186.
  • Gordon, Robert M., 1995, “Simulation without introspection or inference from me to you”, in Mental simulation , Martin Davies and Tony Stone (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell.
  • –––, 2007, “Ascent routines for propositional attitudes”, Synthese , 159: 151–165.
  • Green, David M., and John A. Swets, 1966, Signal detection theory and psychophysics , Oxford: Wiley.
  • Greenwald, Anthony G., Debbie E. McGhee, and Jordan L.K. Schwartz, 1998, “Measuring individual differences in implicit cognition: The Implicit Association Test”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 74: 1464–1480.
  • Greenwald, Anthony G., and Brian A. Nosek, 2009, “Attitudinal dissociation: What does it mean?”, in Attitudes: Insights from the New Implicit Measures , Richard E. Petty, Russell H. Fazio, and Pablo Briñol (eds.), New York: Taylor and Francis, 65–82.
  • Hahn, Adam, Charles M. Judd, Holen K. Hirsh, and Irene V. Blair, forthcoming, “Awareness of implicit attitudes”, Journal of Experimental Psychology: General .
  • Hamilton, Andy, 2007, “Memory and self-consciousness: Immunity to error through misidentification”, Synthese , 171: 409–417.
  • Hamilton, J.M.E., and A.J. Sanford, 1978, “The symbolic distance effect for alphabetic order judgements: A subjective report and reaction time analysis”, Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology , 30: 33–43.
  • Harman, Gilbert, 1990, “The intrinsic quality of experience”, in James Tomberlin, (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives , 4, Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview, 31–52.
  • Hart, Allen J., Paul J. Whalen, Lisa M. Shin, Sean C. McInerney, Hakan Fischer, and Scott L. Rauch, 2000, “Differential response in the human amygdala to racial outgroup vs ingroup face stimuli”, NeuroReport , 11: 2351–2355.
  • Haybron, Daniel M., 2008, The pursuit of unhappiness , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Hektner, Joel M., Jennifer A. Schmidt, and Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi, 2007, Experience sampling method , Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
  • Heil, John, 1988, “Privileged access”, Mind , 97: 238–251.
  • Helmholtz, Hermann, 1856/1962, Helmholtz's Treatise on Physiological Optics , James P.C. Southall (ed.), New York: Dover. [Translation based on 1924 edition.]
  • Hill, Christopher S., 1991, Sensations: A defense of type materialism , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2009, Consciousness , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hirstein, William, 2005, Brain fiction , Cambridge, MA: MIT.
  • Hohwy, Jakob, 2011, “Phenomenal variability and introspective reliability”, Mind & Language , 26: 261–286.
  • Horgan, Terence, John L. Tienson, and George Graham, 2006, “Internal-world skepticism and mental self-presentation”, in Self-representational approaches to consciousness , Uriah Kriegel and Kenneth Williford (eds.), Cambridge, MA: MIT, 191–207.
  • Horgan, Terence, and Uriah Kriegel, 2007, “Phenomenal epistemology: What is consciousness that we may know it so well?”, Philosophical Issues , 17(1): 123–144.
  • Hume, David, 1739/1978, A treatise of human nature , L.A. Selby-Bigge and P.H. Nidditch (eds.), Oxford: Clarendon.
  • –––, 1748/1975, An enquiry concerning human understanding , in Enquiries concerning human understanding and concerning the principles of morals , L.A. Selby-Bigge and P.H. Nidditch (eds.), Oxford: Clarendon, 1–165.
  • Humphrey, George, 1951, Thinking: An introduction to its experimental psychology , London: Methuen.
  • Hurlburt, Russell T., 1990, Sampling normal and schizophrenic inner experience , New York: Plenum.
  • Hurlburt, Russell T., 2011, Investigating pristine inner experience , Cambridge: Cambridge.
  • Hurlburt, Russell T., and Christopher L. Heavey, 2006, Exploring inner experience , Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
  • Hurlburt, Russell T., and Eric Schwitzgebel, 2007, Describing inner experience? Proponent meets skeptic , Cambridge, MA: MIT.
  • Husserl, Edmund, 1913/1982, Ideas , Book I, T.E. Klein and W.E. Pohl (trs.), Dordrecht: Kluwer.
  • Ilg, Rüdiger, Afra M. Wohlschläger, Stefan Burazanis, Andreas Wöller, Sabine Nunnemann, and Mark Mühlau, 2008, “Neural correlates of spontaneous percept switches in ambiguous stimuli: An event-related functional magnetic resonance imaging study”, European Journal of Neuroscience , 28: 2325–2332.
  • Irvine, Elizabeth, 2013, Consciousness as a scientific concept , Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Ito, Tiffany A., and John T. Cacioppo, 2007, “Attitudes as mental and neural states of readiness”, in Implicit measures of attitudes , Bernd Wittenbrink and Norbert Schwarz (eds.), New York: Guilford, 125–158.
  • Jack, Anthony, and Andreas Roepstorff, 2003, Trusting the subject , vol. 1, special issue of the Journal of Consciousness Studies , no. 10(9–10).
  • –––, 2004, Trusting the subject , vol. 2, special issue of the Journal of Consciousness Studies , 11(7–8).
  • James, William, 1890/1981, The principles of psychology , Cambridge, MA: Harvard.
  • Jaynes, Julian, 1976, The origin of consciousness in the breakdown of the bicameral mind , New York: Houghton Mifflin.
  • Johansson, Petter, Lars Hall, Sverker Sikström, and Andreas Olsson, 2005, “Failure to detect mismatches between intention and outcome in a simple decision task”, Science , 310: 116–119.
  • Johansson, Petter, Lars Hall, Sverker Sikström, Betty Tärning, and Andreas Lind, 2006, “How something can be said about telling more than we can know: On choice blindness and introspection”, Consciousness and Cognition , 15: 673–692.
  • Kamphuisen, Allard, Markus Bauer, and Raymond van Ee, 2008, “No evidence for widespread synchronized networks in binocular rivalry: MEG frequency tagging entrains primary early visual cortex”, Journal of Vision , 8(5): article 4.
  • Kant, Immanuel, 1781/1997, The critique of pure reason , Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (eds. and trs.), Cambridge: Cambridge.
  • Kay, Aaron C., Maria C. Jimenez, and John T. Jost, 2002, “Sour grapes, sweet lemons, and the anticipatory rationalization of the status quo”, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin , 28: 1300–1312.
  • Kihlstrom, John F., “Implicit methods in social psychology”, in The SAGE handbook of methods in social psychology , Carol Sansone, Carolyn C. Morf, and A.T. Panter (eds.), Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 195–212.
  • Kind, Amy, 2003, “What's so transparent about transparency?”, Philosophical Studies , 115: 225–244.
  • Kleinschmidt, A., C. Büchel, S. Zeki, and R.S.J. Frackowiak, 1998, “Human brain activity during spontaneously reversing perception of ambiguous figures”, Proceedings of the Royal Society B , 265: 2427–2433.
  • Knapen, Tomas, Jan Brascamp, Joel Pearson, Raymond van Ee, and Randolph Blake, 2011, “The role of frontal and parietal areas in bistable perception”, Journal of Neuroscience , 31: 10293–10301.
  • Kornblith, Hilary, 1998, “What is it like to be me?”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy , 76: 48–60.
  • Kosslyn, Stephen M., Daniel Reisberg, and Marlene Behrmann, 2006, “Introspection and mechanism in mental imagery”, in The Dalai Lama at MIT , Anne Harrington and Arthur Zajonc (eds.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard, 79–90.
  • Kreiman, Gabriel, Itzhak Fried, and Christof Koch, 2002, “Single-neuron correlates of subjective vision in the human medial temporal lobe”, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences , 99: 8378–8383.
  • Kriegel, Uriah, 2009, Subjective consciousness , Oxford: Oxford.
  • Külpe, Oswald, 1893/1895, Outlines of psychology , London: Swan Sonnenschein.
  • Kusch, Martin, 1999, Psychological knowledge , London, Routledge.
  • Lambie, John A., and Anthony J. Marcel, 2002, “Consciousness and the varieties of emotion experience: A theoretical framework”, Psychological Review , 109: 219–259.
  • Lane, Kristin A., Mahzarin R. Banaji, Brian A. Nosek, and Anthony G. Greenwald, 2007, “Understanding and using the Implicit Association Test: IV”, in Implicit measures of attitudes , Bernd Wittenbrink and Norbert Schwarz (eds.), New York: Guilford, 59–102.
  • Larson, Reed, and Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi, 1983, “The Experience Sampling Method” in Harry T. Reis, (ed.), Naturalistic approaches to studying social interaction , San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 41-56.
  • Lear, Jonathan, 1998, Open-minded , Cambridge, MA: Harvard.
  • Lewis, C.I., 1946, An analysis of knowledge and valuation , La Salle, IL: Open Court.
  • Locke, John, 1690/1975, An essay concerning human understanding , Peter H. Nidditch (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Lumer, Erik D., Karl J. Friston, and Geraint Rees, 1998, “Neural correlates of perceptual rivalry in the human brain”, Science , 280: 1930–1934.
  • Lycan, William G., 1996, Consciousness and experience , Cambridge, MA: MIT.
  • Lyons, William, 1986, The disappearance of introspection , Cambridge, MA: MIT.
  • Lyubomirsky, Sonja, and Lee Ross, 1999, “Changes in attractiveness of elected, rejected, and precluded alternatives: A comparison of happy and unhappy individuals”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 76: 988–1007.
  • Macmillan, Neil A., and C. Douglas Creelman, 1991, Detection theory , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Marks, David F., 1985, “Imagery paradigms and methodology” Journal of Mental Imagery , 9: 93–105.
  • Marr, David, 1983, Vision , New York: Freeman.
  • Martin, Michael G.F., 2002, “The transparency of experience”, Mind and Language , 17: 376–425.
  • Maudsley, Henry, 1867/1977, Physiology and pathology of the mind , Daniel N. Robinson (ed.), Washington, DC: University Publications of America.
  • McGeer, Victoria, 1996, “Is ‘self-knowledge’ an empirical problem? Renegotiating the space of philosophical explanation”, Journal of Philosophy , 93: 483–515.
  • –––, 2008, “The moral development of first-person authority”, European Journal of Philosophy , 16: 81–108.
  • McGeer, Victoria, and Philip Pettit, 2002, “The self-regulating mind”, Language and Communication , 22: 281–299.
  • Mele, Alfred, 2001, Self-deception unmasked , Princeton, NJ: Princeton.
  • Mengzi, 3rd c. BCE/2008, B.W. Van Norden (tr.), Indianapolis: Hackett.
  • Merickle, Philip M., Daniel Smilek, and John D. Eastwood, 2001, “Perception without awareness: Perspectives from cognitive psychology”, Cognition , 79: 115–134.
  • Mill, James, 1829/1878, Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind , John Stuart Mill (ed.), London: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.
  • Mill, John Stuart, 1865/1961, Auguste Comte and positivism , Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan.
  • Mole, Christoper, 2011, Attention is cognitive unison , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Moll, Albert, 1889/1911, Hypnotism , Arthur F. Hopkirk (ed.), New York: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  • Moore, George Edward, 1903, “The refutation of idealism”, Mind , 12: 433–453.
  • –––, 1942, “A reply to my critics”, in The philosophy of G.E. Moore , in P.A. Schilpp (ed.), New York: Tudor, 535–677.
  • –––, 1944/1993, “Moore's paradox”, in G.E. Moore, Selected writings , Thomas Baldwin (ed.), London: Routledge, 207–212.
  • Moran, Richard, 2001, Authority and estrangement , Princeton: Princeton.
  • Müller, G.E., 1904, Die Gesichtspunkte und die Tatsachen der psychophysischen Methodik , Wiesbaden: J.F. Bergmann.
  • Nahmias, Eddy, 2002, “Verbal reports on the contents of consciousness: Reconsidering introspectionist methodology”, Psyche , 8(21).
  • Nichols, Shaun, and Stephen P. Stich, 2003, Mindreading , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Nisbett, Richard E., and Nancy Bellows, 1977, “Verbal reports about causal influences on social judgments: Private access versus public theories”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 35: 613–624.
  • Nisbett, Richard E., and Lee Ross, 1980, Human inference , Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
  • Nisbett, Richard E., and Timothy DeCamp Wilson, 1977, “Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes”, Psychological Review , 84: 231–259.
  • Noë, Alva, 2004, Action in perception , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Noë, Alva, and Evan Thompson, 2004, “Are there neural correlates of consciousness?”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 11: (1): 3–28.
  • Overgaard, Morten, Kristian Sandberg, and Mads Jensen, 2008, “The neural correlate of consciousness?”, Journal of Theoretical Biology , 254: 713–715.
  • Papineau, David, 2002, Thinking about consciousness , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Parkkonen, Lauri, Jesper Andersson, Matti Hämäläinen, and Riitta Hari, 2008, “Early visual brain areas reflect the percept of an ambiguous scene”, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences , 105: 20500–20504.
  • Paulhus, Delroy L., and Oliver P. John, 1998, “Egoistic and moralistic biases in self-perception: The interplay of self-deceptive styles with basic traits and motives”, Journal of Personality , 66: 1025–1060.
  • Peacocke, Christopher, 1998, “Conscious attitudes, attention, and self-knowledge”, in Knowing our own minds , Crispin Wright, Barry C. Smith, and Cynthia Macdonald (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 63–99.
  • Petitmengin, Claire, 2006, “Describing one's subjective experience in the second person: An interview method for the science of consciousness”, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences , 5: 229–269.
  • Petty, Richard E., Russell H. Fazio, and Pablo Briñol (eds.), 2009, Attitudes: Insights from the new implicit measures , New York: Taylor and Francis.
  • Pillsbury, W.B., 1908, Attention , London: Swan Sonnenschein.
  • Price, Donald D., and Murat Aydede, 2005, “The experimental use of introspection in the scientific study of pain and its integration with third-person methodologies: The experiential-phenomenological approach”, in Pain: New essays on its nature and the methodology of its study ,Murat Aydede (ed.), Cambridge, MA: MIT, 243–273.
  • Prinz, Jesse, 2004, “The fractionation of introspection”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 11(7–8): 40–57.
  • –––, 2007, “Mental pointing: Phenomenal knowledge without concepts”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 14(9–10): 184–211.
  • –––, 2012, The conscious brain , Oxford: Oxford.
  • Pryor, James, 1999, “Immunity to error through misidentification”, Philosophical Topics , 26(1–2): 271–304.
  • Putnam, Hilary, 1975, “The meaning of ‘meaning’” in Hilary Putnam, Philosophical papers , vol. 2, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 215–271.
  • Quiroga, R. Quian, R. Mukamel, E.A. Isham, and I. Fried, 2008, “Human single-neuron responses at the threshold of conscious recognition”, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences , 105: 3599–3604.
  • Redelmeier, Donald A., and Daniel Kahneman, 1996, “Patients' memories of painful medical treatments: Real-time and retrospective evaluations of two minimally invasive procedures”, Pain , 66: 3–8.
  • Rees, Geraint, and Chris Frith, 2007, “Methodologies for identifying the neural correlates of consciousness”, in The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness , Max Velmans and Susan Schneider (eds.), Malden, MA: Blackwell, 553–566.
  • Richet, Charles, 1884, L'homme et l'intelligence , Paris: F. Alcan.
  • Rodriguez, Eugenio, Nathalie George, Jean-Philippe Lachauz, Jacques Martinerie, Bernard Renault, and Francisco J. Varela, 1999, Perception's shadow: Long-distance synchronization of human brain activity“, Nature , 397: 430–433.
  • Rorty, Richard, 1970, ”Incorrigibility as the mark of the mental“, Journal of Philosophy , 67: 399–424.
  • Rosenthal, David M., 1990, ”Two concepts of consciousness“, Philosophical Studies , 49: 329–359
  • –––, 2001, ”Introspection and self-interpretation“, Philosophical Topics , 28(2): 201–233.
  • –––, 2005, Consciousness and Mind , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Ryle, Gilbert, 1949, The concept of mind , New York: Barnes and Noble.
  • Sandberg, Kristian, Bahador Bahrami, Ryota Kanai, Gareth Robert Barnes, Morten Overgaard, and Geraint Rees, 2013, ”Early visual responses predict conscious face perception within and between subjects during binocular rivalry“, Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience , 25: 969–985.
  • Schwitzgebel, Eric, 2002, ”A phenomenal, dispositional account of belief“, Noûs , 36: 249–275.
  • –––, 2005, ”Difference tone training“, Psyche , 11(6).
  • –––, 2007, ”No unchallengeable epistemic authority, of any sort, regarding our own conscious experience—contra Dennett?“, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences , 6: 107–113.
  • –––, 2011a, ”Knowing your own beliefs“, Canadian Journal of Philosophy , 35, supplement 41–62 ( Belief and Agency , ed. D. Hunter.)
  • –––, 2011b, Perplexities of consciousness , Cambridge, MA: MIT.
  • –––, 2012, ”Introspection, what?“, in Introspection and consciousness , Declan Smithies and Daniel Stoljar (eds.), Oxford: Oxford.
  • Scollon, Christie Napa, Ed Diener, Shigehiro Oishi, Robert Biswas-Diener , 2005, ”An experience-sampling and cross-cultural investigation of the relation between pleasant and unpleasant affect“, Cognition and Emotion , 19: 27–52.
  • Searle, John R., 1983, Intentionality , Cambridge: Cambridge.
  • –––, 1992, The rediscovery of the mind , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Shoemaker, Sydney, 1963, Self-knowledge and self-identity , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 1968, ”Self-reference and self-awareness“, Journal of Philosophy , 65: 555–567.
  • –––, 1988, ”On knowing one's own mind“, Philosophical Perspectives , 2: 183–209.
  • –––, 1994a, ”Self-knowledge and ‘inner sense’. Lecture I: The object perception model, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , 54: 249–269.
  • –––, 1994b, “Self-knowledge and ‘inner sense’. Lecture II: The broad perceptual model”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , 54: 271–290.
  • –––, 1994c, “Self-knowledge and ‘inner sense’. Lecture III: The phenomenal character of experience”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , 54: 291–314.
  • –––, 1995, “Moore's paradox and self-knowledge”, Philosophical Studies , 77: 211–228.
  • Siewert, Charles, 2004, “Is experience transparent?”, Philosophical Studies , 117: 15–41.
  • –––, 2012, ”On the phenomenology of introspection“, in Introspection and consciousness , Declan Smithies and Daniel Stoljar (eds.), Oxford: Oxford.
  • Sirken, Monroe G., Douglas J. Herrmann, Susan Schechter, Norbert Schwarz, Judith N. Tanur, Roger Tourangeau (eds.), 1999, Cognition and survey research , New York: John Wiley and Sons.
  • Smallwood, Jonathan, and Jonathan W. Schooler, 2006, “The restless mind”, Psychological Bulletin , 132: 946–958.
  • Smith, A.D., 2008, “Translucent experiences”, Philosophical Studies , 140:197–212.
  • Spener, Maja, forthcoming, “Disagreement about cognitive phenomenology”, in Cognitive phenomenology , Tim Bayne and Michelle Montague (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Stoljar, Daniel, 2004, “The argument from diaphanousness”, in New essays in the philosophy of language and mind , Maite Ezcurdia, Robert J. Stainton, and Christopher Viger (eds.), Calgary: University of Calgary, 341–390.
  • Stone, Jeff, and Joel Cooper, 2001, “A self-standards model of cognitive dissonance”, Journal of Experimental Social Psychology , 37: 228–243.
  • Summerfield, Christopher, Anthony Ian Jack, and Adrian Philip Burgess, 2002, “Induced gamma activity is associated with conscious awareness of pattern masked nouns”, International Journal of Psychophysiology , 44: 93–100.
  • Taylor, Shelley E., and Jonathon D. Brown, 1988, “Illusion and well-being: A social psychological perspective on mental health”, Psychological Bulletin , 103: 193–210.
  • Thomas, Nigel, 1999, “Are theories of imagery theories of imagination?”, Cognitive Science , 23: 207–245.
  • Titchener, E.B., 1901–1905, Experimental psychology , New York: Macmillan.
  • –––, 1908/1973, Lectures on the elementary psychology of feeling and attention , New York: Arno.
  • –––, 1912a, “Prolegomena to a study of introspection”, American Journal of Psychology , 23: 427–448.
  • –––, 1912b, “The schema of introspection”, American Journal of Psychology , 23: 485–508.
  • Tong, Frank, Ming Meng, and Randolf Blake, 2006, “Neural bases of binocular rivalry”, Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 10: 502–511.
  • Tong, Frank, Ken Nakayama, J. Thomas Vaughan, and Nancy Kanwisher, 1998, “Binocular rivalry and visual awareness in human extrastriate cortex”, Neuron , 21: 753–759.
  • Tononi, Giulio, and Christof Koch, 2008, “The neural correlates of consciousness: An update”, Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences: The Year in Cognitive Neuroscience 2008 , 1124: 239–261.
  • Tononi, Giulio, Ramesh Srinivasan, D. Patrick Russell, and Gerald M. Edelman, 1998, “Investigating neural correlates of conscious perception by frequency-tagged neuromagnetic responses”, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences , 95: 3198–3203.
  • Tye, Michael, 1995, Ten problems about consciousness , Cambridge, MA: MIT.
  • –––, 2000, Consciousness, color, and content , Cambridge, MA: MIT.
  • –––, 2002, “Representationalism and the transparency of experience” Noûs , 36: 137–151.
  • –––, 2009, Consciousness revisited , Cambridge, MA: MIT.
  • Van Gulick, Robert, 1993, “Understanding the phenomenal mind: Are we all just armadillos?”, in Consciousness: Psychological and philosophical essays , Martin Davies and Glyn W. Humphreys (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell, 134–154.
  • Vanman, Eric J., Brenda Y. Paul, Tiffany A. Ito, and Norman Miller, 1997, “The modern face of prejudice and structural features that moderate the effect of cooperation on affect” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 73: 941–959.
  • Varela, Francisco J., 1996, “Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 3(4): 330–49.
  • Vazire, Simine, 2010, “Who knows what about a person? The Self-Other Knowledge Asymmetry (SOKA) model”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 98: 281–300.
  • Velleman, J. David, 2000, The possibility of practical reason , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Watson, John B., 1913, “Psychology as the behaviorist views it”, Psychological Review , 20: 158–177.
  • Wegner, Daniel M., 2002, The illusion of conscious will , Cambridge, MA: MIT.
  • Wegner, Daniel M. and Thalia Wheatley, 1999, “Apparent mental causation”, American Psychologist , 54: 480–492.
  • White, Peter A., 1988, “Knowing more about what we can tell: ‘Introspective access’ and causal report accuracy ten years later”, British Journal of Psychology , 79: 13–45.
  • Williams, Amanda C. de C., Huw Talfryn Oakley Davies, and Yasmin Chadury, 2000, “Simple pain rating scales hide complex idiosyncratic meanings”, Pain , 85: 457–463.
  • Wilson, Timothy D., 2002, Strangers to ourselves , Cambridge, MA: Harvard.
  • Wilson, Timothy D., Samuel Lindsey, and Tonya T. Schooler, 2000, “A model of dual attitudes”, Psychological Review , 107: 101–126.
  • Wittenbrink, Bernd, Charles M. Judd, and Bernadette Park, 1997, “Evidence for racial prejudice at the implicit level and its relationship with questionnaire measures”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 72: 262–274.
  • Wittenbrink, Bernd, and Norbert Schwarz (eds.), 2007, Implicit measures of attitudes , New York: Guilford.
  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1953/1968, Philosophical investigations , 3rd edition, G.E.M. Anscombe (translator), New York: Macmillan.
  • Wollheim, Richard, 1981, Sigmund Freud , New York: Cambridge.
  • –––, 2003, “On the Freudian unconscious”, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association , 77(2): 23–35.
  • Wright, Crispin, 1989, “Wittgenstein's later philosophy of mind: Sensation, privacy, and intention”, Journal of Philosophy , 86: 622–634.
  • –––, 1998, “Self-knowledge: The Wittgensteinian legacy”, in Knowing our own minds , Crispin Wright, Barry C. Smith, and Cynthia Macdonald (eds.), Oxford: Oxford.
  • Wundt, Wilhelm, 1874/1908, Grundzüge der physiologischen Psychologie (6th ed.), Leipzig: Wilhelm Engelmann.
  • –––, 1888, Selbstbeobachtung und innere Wahrnehmung, Philosophische Studien , 4: 292–309.
  • –––, 1896/1902, Outlines of psychology (4th ed.), 2nd English ed., Charles Hubbard Judd (trans.), Leipzig: Wilhelm Engelmann.
  • –––, 1907, “Über Ausfrageexperiments und über die Methoden zur Psychologie des Denkens”, Psychologische Studien , 3: 301–360.
  • Zimmerman, Aaron, 2007, “The nature of belief”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 14(11): 61–82.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Implicit Association Test , from Project Implicit, Harvard University.
  • Difference Tone Training , Schwitzgebel's (2005) recreation of an introspective training procedure from Titchener's (1901–1905) lab manual.
  • Color Wheels; Color Systems , An image of the Munsell color solid can be found at in the pages for the course 2D Design (Art 107), by Curt Heuer at the University of Wisconsin at Green Bay.

behaviorism | belief | Brentano, Franz | consciousness | consciousness: and intentionality | consciousness: higher-order theories | consciousness: representational theories of | consciousness: unity of | delusion | Descartes, René: epistemology | folk psychology: as a theory | folk psychology: as mental simulation | functionalism | Helmholtz, Hermann von | James, William | Kant, Immanuel: view of mind and consciousness of self | mental content: externalism about | mental content: narrow | mental imagery | pain | perception: the problem of | phenomenology | propositional attitude reports | qualia | Ryle, Gilbert | self-consciousness: phenomenological approaches to | self-deception | self-knowledge | Wundt, Wilhelm Maximilian

Copyright © 2014 by Eric Schwitzgebel < eschwitz @ citrus . ucr . edu >

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

Stanford Center for the Study of Language and Information

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2016 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Center for the Study of Language and Information (CSLI), Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

  • Skip to main content
  • Skip to primary sidebar

IResearchNet

Introspection

Introspection definition.

The term introspection is generally used by psychologists to refer to people’s observation and contemplation of their own thoughts, feelings, and sensations. In early psychology, trained introspection was viewed as a useful tool for acquiring data about the nature of such cognitions, though the methodology fell into disfavor and was largely abandoned during the past century. However, introspective self-reports are still employed in social psychology to assess such constructs as attitudes, leading to continuing debate over the proper role of introspection in scientific psychology.

History of Introspection

Introspection

The method of trained introspectionism ultimately became bogged down with reliability and validity issues, especially because training inherently colored the reports of introspecting subjects. The approach was criticized by Gestalt theorists, who argued that the overall organization of thoughts is more important than individual elements, and by behaviorists, who argued that behavior, not thought, is the proper focus of scientific psychology. Over the next 50 years, these two approaches dominated Europe and the United States, respectively, and the method of trained introspection was abandoned.

Validity of Introspective Self-Reports

The behaviorist critique calls into question any research method that relies on people’s introspective self-reports of their perceptions, thoughts, or feelings. Yet, such self-report measures are commonly used in social psychology, especially to assess moods, emotions, beliefs, and attitudes, often to good effect. True, concerns are raised periodically that people may distort their self-reports, especially if the attitudes they hold are socially undesirable. And recently researchers have demonstrated that people sometimes hold implicit attitudes of which they are not even aware and which, therefore, cannot be assessed with common self-report measures. One view is that such attitudes reflect an elaborate adaptive subconscious that inherently colors all perceptions, communications, and actions. An alternative view is that implicit attitudes may be relatively rare and frequently overridden by conscious ones.

Critics also argue that introspection necessarily changes the cognitions that people contemplate and report. One program of research suggests that simply thinking about one’s attitudes causes them to become more extreme. Another indicates that thinking about the reasons for one’s attitudes can fundamentally change those attitudes in important ways. For example, in one study, subjects introspected about why they preferred one of two posters before deciding which to take home; others made their choice without introspecting. When contacted weeks later, those who had introspected before choosing were generally less happy with their selection than those who had not. The researchers suggest that introspecting focused subjects on easy-to-communicate justifications for their choice that did not reflect their actual feelings, leading to choices they ultimately found unsatisfying.

One common view is that people are ordinarily better at discerning their own attitudes than they are at introspecting the reasons for, or processes underlying, those attitudes. In one study, shoppers felt several nightgowns, reported which they preferred, and then described the reasons for their preference. In actuality, all the gowns were the same, though people tended to prefer the one on the right, due to a common serial position effect. However, no one correctly reported that their preference was determined by serial position; instead, people made up justifications for their preferences. People’s tendency to introduce theories about their thoughts and preferences, rather than to report such thoughts objectively, underlies many criticisms of introspective methods.

Nonetheless, some psychologists argue that introspection ought to be treated like any other scientific methodology, including modern brain-imaging tasks that may seem more scientific. In other words, researchers need to develop sophisticated theories of the cognitive processes involved in introspection, the factors that affect such processes, and thus the circumstances under which introspection can or cannot provide useful data. In general, introspection is expected to yield more valuable data about the way that stimuli and events are experienced than about the mechanisms or causes of those experiences. And, in general, converging results from several different methods will be more definitive than the results of any one method alone.

Consider, for example, introspective reports of pain. Doctors generally assume that self-reports of the nature, severity, and location of pain are highly informative, even if not totally accurate. When a patient says, “It hurts when I raise my right arm,” this is a key piece of evidence in framing the problem to be addressed and in diagnosing the ailment. Other kinds of data, such as x-rays or brain imaging may also provide useful data, especially when combined with those self-reports. But doctors are much more skeptical of a patient’s speculations about the causes of reported pain, such as “It feels like I tore the bursa.” This is where other methodologies may be more useful. Even so, when the patient has the appropriate knowledge (e.g., she is a doctor herself), even introspections about causation may be valuable. Some writers therefore suggest that refinement of introspective methods may ultimately require that subjects receive special training, a controversial proposal given past criticisms of the method of trained introspection.

References:

  • Jack, A. I., & Roepstorff, A. (Eds.). (2003). Trusting the subject: The use of introspective evidence in cognitive science (2 vols.). Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic.
  • Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84, 231-259.

introspection a research tool used by early

Live revision! Join us for our free exam revision livestreams Watch now →

Reference Library

Collections

  • See what's new
  • All Resources
  • Student Resources
  • Assessment Resources
  • Teaching Resources
  • CPD Courses
  • Livestreams

Study notes, videos, interactive activities and more!

Psychology news, insights and enrichment

Currated collections of free resources

Browse resources by topic

  • All Psychology Resources

Resource Selections

Currated lists of resources

Study Notes

Introspection (Early Use)

Last updated 22 Mar 2021

  • Share on Facebook
  • Share on Twitter
  • Share by Email

Introspection means “looking into” and refers to the process of observing and examining your own conscious thoughts or emotions.

Before Wundt, introspection had been used by philosophers for studying how new ideas are created. These philosophers did not set any limits on the tasks they studied or make any judgments about the relevance of thoughts.

In contrast, Wundt strictly controlled the environments where introspection took place, controlled the stimuli and tasks that participants were asked to think about, limited the range of responses they might give and trained his participants so that they could give the most detailed observations possible.

Wundt’s use of introspection inspired others to apply it to more complex mental processes, such as learning, language and emotion. This required the researchers to exert less control on the way that introspection took place and very soon it became clear that introspection was not a reliable method for finding out about mental states - we can only report a fragment of what we are actually thinking and often have little awareness of the processes that actually influence our decisions.

Similarly, although the fact that participants needed to be trained to introspect gave them a sense of authority, it also meant that their observations were biased by their training and tended to support the theories of the researchers who trained them.

These problems meant that by 1913, Watson was able to argue that introspection should play no part in a scientific psychology and Behaviourism became the dominant approach in psychology.

  • Introspection

You might also like

Wundt’s contribution to psychology, lesson powerpoint: approaches - origins of psychology.

16th September 2016

Origins of Psychology

Quizzes & Activities

Three Essential Paper 2 Approaches in Psychology Videos for A Level Psychology Students

9th June 2017

Example Answers for Approaches in Psychology: A Level Psychology, Paper 2, June 2018 (AQA)

Exam Support

Introspection & the Cognitive Approach

Emergence of psychology as a science: the laboratory experiment, the birth of psychology. was it wundt.

4th January 2017

Our subjects

  • › Criminology
  • › Economics
  • › Geography
  • › Health & Social Care
  • › Psychology
  • › Sociology
  • › Teaching & learning resources
  • › Student revision workshops
  • › Online student courses
  • › CPD for teachers
  • › Livestreams
  • › Teaching jobs

Boston House, 214 High Street, Boston Spa, West Yorkshire, LS23 6AD Tel: 01937 848885

  • › Contact us
  • › Terms of use
  • › Privacy & cookies

© 2002-2024 Tutor2u Limited. Company Reg no: 04489574. VAT reg no 816865400.

U.S. flag

An official website of the United States government

The .gov means it’s official. Federal government websites often end in .gov or .mil. Before sharing sensitive information, make sure you’re on a federal government site.

The site is secure. The https:// ensures that you are connecting to the official website and that any information you provide is encrypted and transmitted securely.

  • Publications
  • Account settings

Preview improvements coming to the PMC website in October 2024. Learn More or Try it out now .

  • Advanced Search
  • Journal List

Logo of brainsci

A Scientific Approach to Conscious Experience, Introspection, and Unconscious Processing: Vision and Blindsight

Although subjective conscious experience and introspection have long been considered unscientific and banned from psychology, they are indispensable in scientific practice. These terms are used in scientific contexts today; however, their meaning remains vague, and earlier objections to the distinction between conscious experience and unconscious processing, remain valid. This also applies to the distinction between conscious visual perception and unconscious visual processing. Damage to the geniculo-striate pathway or the visual cortex results in a perimetrically blind visual hemifield contralateral to the damaged hemisphere. In some cases, cerebral blindness is not absolute. Patients may still be able to guess the presence, location, shape or direction of movement of a stimulus even though they report no conscious visual experience. This “unconscious” ability was termed “blindsight”. The present paper demonstrates how the term conscious visual experience can be introduced in a logically precise and methodologically correct way and becomes amenable to scientific examination. The distinction between conscious experience and unconscious processing is demonstrated in the cases of conscious vision and blindsight. The literature on “blindsight” and its neurobiological basis is reviewed. It is shown that blindsight can be caused by residual functions of neural networks of the visual cortex that have survived cerebral damage, and may also be due to an extrastriate pathway via the midbrain to cortical areas such as areas V4 and MT/V5.

1. Introduction: The Theoretical Background

The psychologist J.B. Watson considered psychology as an experimental science. In Watson’s view, introspection does not belong to its methods, and does not contribute to scientific knowledge. Watson was convinced that “the time seems to have come when psychology must discard all reference to consciousness; when it need no longer delude itself into thinking that it is making mental states the object of observation” [ 1 ] (p. 263). Radical behaviorist positions have also been held by philosophers, among which the most recognized advocates are Ludwig Wittgenstein [ 2 ] and Gilbert Ryle [ 3 ]. Wittgenstein argues that the terms of an intersubjectively valid, objective language cannot refer to subjective sensations to which only those who have these sensations have access. In this case, there is no way for the community of speakers to decide whether the relation between a sensation and the term that designates it is correct. Since such an objective criterion for the correctness of this relation is missing, it is not possible to speak of “correct” and “incorrect” here. These terms belong to a private language, that is not intersubjectively understandable. Wittgenstein compared conscious subjective experiences with a beetle in a box, where each person owns a box and claims to know what a beetle was by looking into his own box. However, no one can look into another person’s box. Then, it was possible that everyone had something else in his box or his box could also be empty. The word “beetle” does not designate an object, and can be eliminated from the language game [ 2 ] (§293) [ 4 ]. Similarly, the English philosopher Gilbert Ryle [ 3 ] regards consciousness as a ghost in the human machine and claims that no person has privileged access to himself. Ryle claims that what one can find out about oneself is based on the same methods as what one finds out about other people. However, the claim that no one has privileged access to himself contradicts everyday observations. Imagine that a person P is asked to press one of three keys, where gains and losses are identical for each key-press. From an observer’s perspective, each key-press has the same a priori probability. If a person other than P attempts to predict which key P will press next, s/he needs to observe P’s reaction in numerous similar situations. However, it is hardly possible to predict with certainty which key P will press next. Nevertheless, we can state in an objectively verifiable manner that P can predict with absolute certainty which key s/he will press next. P never needs to have performed such a task before, and s/he never needs to have observed his/her behavior in such a task. There is no doubt that P has privileged access to his/her decision which key s/he will press next.

Positivism and the resulting behaviorism advocated by philosophers of the Vienna Circle can be considered one of the cornerstones of the philosophy of science. From the perspective of Rudolf Carnap, one of the most prominent advocates of this philosophical school, every proposition of psychology can be formulated in physical language. Carnap subsumes the philosophical behaviorism of the Wiener Circle with the words “The introspective statements of a psychologist are not, in principle, to be interpreted differently than the statements of his experimental subject about whom he reports. Additionally, the statements of an experimental subject are not, in principle, to be interpreted differently than his other voluntary or involuntary movements, though his speech movements may under favorable circumstances be regarded as especially informative. Again, the movements of the speech organs and of the other experimental subject’s body parts are not, in principle, to be interpreted differently than the movements of an animal.... The movements of an animal are not, again in principle, to be interpreted any differently than those of a voltmeter.... Finally, the movements of a voltmeter are not, in principle, to be interpreted differently than the movements of a raindrop...” [ 5 ] (p. 140). A few years later, Carnap recognized that the “...psychological movement of Behaviorism had, on the one hand, a very healthful influence because of its emphasis on the observation of behavior as an intersubjective and reliable basis for psychological investigations, while, on the other hand, it imposed too narrow restrictions. First, its total rejection of introspection was unwarranted. Although many of the alleged results of introspection were indeed questionable, a person’s awareness of his own state of imagining, feeling, etc., must be recognized as a kind of observation, in principle not different from external observation, and therefore as a legitimate source of knowledge, though limited by its subjective character” [ 6 ] (pp. 70–71). Additionally, B.F. Skinner, one of the outstanding American psychologists of the 20th century, father of operant conditioning and founder of a school of thought he designated “radical behaviorism”, did not deny the existence of subjective sensations, and he did not consider introspective reports merely as verbal behavior. Skinner advocated only that subjective states do not contribute to the analysis of behavior, and that they are not suitable for explaining behavior [ 7 , 8 ].

Terms that designate conscious, subjective experiences do not designate behavior and environmental conditions under which behavior occurs, and they cannot be defined by describing behavior and environmental conditions. This raises the question of whether conscious sensations can be introduced into the language of science at all. One objective of the present paper is to demonstrate how terms that designate conscious experiences can be introduced into science and how conscious experiences and unconscious processing be can be distinguished from each other scientifically. To achieve this, the concepts “conscious experience” and “unconscious processing” must be translated into a language of mathematical logic that clarifies its semantic nature and does not lead to contradictions or obscure assertions. The distinction between “conscious”, “unconscious” and “reduced conscious experience” is demonstrated with the example of the processing of visual stimuli in the presence of different levels of conscious visual experience. The literature on vision with reduced visual experience (blindsight) will be reviewed. The neurobiological foundations of blindsight are reviewed on the basis of the literature and our own studies of adult patients with injury to the occipital lobe, children with one or both occipital lobes missing, children after hemispherectomy, and children without the telencephalon. The review is based on several thousand publications about the anatomy, physiology, and neuropsychology of the visual system in humans which were available in the Max-Planck-Institute for Psychiatry, the Bavarian State Library, the Library of the Medical Faculty of the University of Munich, Pubmed, Science Direct, Psycnet or other internet-based databases, which the author collected over about 40 years up to the year 2022. A total of 190 studies that were considered the most relevant to the questions posed in the present review were included.

2. Psychological Terms Understood as Theoretical Concepts

Carnap realized that many major psychological concepts cannot be defined by terms that designate observational entities such as observable behavior under given observable circumstances [ 9 ]. For example, if we attempted to define the term “arachnophobia” by the statement “P has arachnophobia” it would mean “whenever P sees a spider, P displays fear reactions R”, this led, for formal logical reasons, to the absurd consequence that one could diagnose arachnophobia if this person has never seen a spider. Carnap therefore suggested that terms introduced by specifying a certain reaction under certain conditions should be introduced by so called “reduction sentences” [ 9 ]. A reduction sentence by which the term “arachnophobia” is introduced has the following logical form: “If a Person P sees a spider, then, if P has arachnophobia, P displays fear reaction R, and if P has no arachnophobia, P does not display fear reaction R” [ 9 ] (p. 440), [ 10 ]. In terms of formal logic: S(P) → (A(P) ↔ R(P)), whereby S(P) represents “Person P sees a spider”, A(P) “P has arachnophobia”, R(P) “P displays fear reaction R”, → is the logical sign for implication, and ↔ is the logical sign for equivalence. However, people with arachnophobia do not display only a single reaction under one environmental condition. The Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM5), [ 11 ] (pp. 197–198). specifies different reactions that occur under different conditions for the diagnosis of a specific phobia. Therefore, we can introduce the concept of arachnophobia not with a single reduction sentence, but with several reduction sentences. Over time, new reduction sentences can be added and others may be abandoned, and new psychobiological statements can further specify a particular type of phobia. This introduction of a term violates all conditions that apply to a definition and should therefore not be regarded as an “operational definition” as is often the case in psychological texts. Carnap [ 6 , 12 ] designated these terms as “theoretical concepts”. Theoretical concepts are linked to terms that designate observables, but are not defined by them. What has been said so far is also true for all terms introduced by specifying the conditions under which a given reactions must occur in order for us to say that a term can be applied. Terms, such as “seeing”, “hearing”, “pain”, “fear”, “restlessness”, “depression”, “euphoria”, etc. are introduced by behavior under given environmental conditions. If a person sees something, hears something, feels pain, fear, or restlessness, or is depressed or euphoric, these can only be known by investigating his/her behavior under given environmental conditions. These terms can be regarded as theoretical terms that, like theoretical terms in physics, need not refer to introspectively accessible conscious experiences. However, we assume that many of these terms designate conscious experiences. Experimental findings demonstrate that a distinction between conscious experiences and unconscious processing is inevitable. Studies on conscious visual experience and unconscious visual processing of stimuli in an apparently blind visual field, termed “blindsight”, is an example that demonstrates the importance of a distinction between conscious experience and unconscious processes. The questions are how this distinction can be achieved and how these conscious experiences can be accounted for in a scientifically accurate manner.

3. Conscious Visual Experience and Unconscious “Vision” (Blindsight)

If we assess a person’s luminance difference threshold, the reduction sentences indicate under which visual stimulation which response should occur for a stimulus to be considered as “seen”. Then, the term “a subject has seen the stimulus” is introduced by appropriate reduction sentences. In scientific practice, it is already known how to measure an incremental and a decremental threshold. If we assess the visual field using visual perimetry, we can instruct the subject to press a button whenever s/he sees a light spot; by “seeing” we mean the “conscious experience of seeing”. Thus, we presuppose an everyday understanding of the term “conscious seeing” in the subject´s instruction. However, seeing does not always presuppose the presence of conscious visual experience. Visual stimuli can also be registered and localized by the human visual system in the absence of conscious experience. Pöppel, Held and Frost [ 13 ] were the first to demonstrate that patients who were apparently blind in an area of their visual field after damage to the occipital lobe, and who also asserted that they could not see anything at all in the affected visual field, could nevertheless locate stimuli correctly when asked to guess the location of stimuli, and to point to the location where they guessed the presence of the stimuli. Weiskrantz et al. [ 14 ] termed this phenomenon “blindsight”. Subsequent experiments (e.g., [ 15 , 16 , 17 , 18 , 19 , 20 , 21 , 22 , 23 , 24 , 25 , 26 , 27 , 28 , 29 , 30 ]) not only confirmed that patients are able to locate stimuli in an apparently blind area but also that they can distinguish shapes, colors, and objects in an area that is perimetrically blind in which patients assert that they have no conscious visual experience. Zihl and von Cramon [ 19 ] demonstrated that patients who had performed several hundred practice trials were able to register the presence or absence of a light stimulus that was presented in the apparently cerebrally blind visual field even though they denied any conscious visual experience. A patient examined by Zihl and Werth [ 21 , 22 ] had a right homonymous hemianopia due to a stroke of the left cerebral hemisphere. The right half of the visual field of both eyes was blinded. The visual field of the patient was assessed using the Tuebingen perimeter. The patient looked into the perimetric hemissphere (diameter 66 cm) with his head stabilized and directed his gaze to a point in the center. Light spots were presented alternately at five different locations on the horizontal meridian in the perimetric hemisphere for 100 ms so that all light spots were projected into the blind visual hemifield of the retina. In all experiments scattering light was measured, and its influence was excluded [ 31 ]. An acoustic signal indicated when a light spot was present. Since the patient claimed not to see anything in the right visual hemifield, he was asked to guess where the light spot was located and to look at the location where he guessed the presence of the light spot. The presentation time of the light spots was so short that they had disappeared by the time the eyes began moving to the guessed location. Surprisingly, there was a clear correlation between the location to which the patient looked and the location where the light spots appeared. If this ability to guess the locations was not spontaneous it could be trained in a short period of time [ 20 ]. Weiskranz et al. [ 32 ] demonstrated that a patient with damage to the primary visual cortex (V1) could discriminate the direction of stimuli when the possible influence of scattering light was also excluded. When the contrast was increased and the stimuli moved with high velocity, the patients became aware of the stimuli. Ffytche and Zeki [ 33 ] showed that in direction of motion experiments that visual awareness was more likely when stimuli were moving compared to static stimuli. Whether a patient became aware of a moving stimulus depended only on the magnitude of activation of the cortex in area V5 [ 34 ]. The phenomenon that stationary stimuli were not detected in a visual field affected by a lesion of the occipital cortex, whereas moving stimuli were consciously seen, was first described by Riddoch [ 35 ]. This kind of awareness of some stimuli in a visual field where the patient is unaware of other stimuli presented in the affected visual field, was termed as “type 2 blindsight”. The case of type 2 blindsight, in which the stimulus is not seen but a non-visual sensation is reported, (for example, the feeling that something is present when the stimulus is presented in the blind field) must be distinguished from the Riddoch phenomenon, which has also been designated as “type 2 blindsight” [ 36 , 37 , 38 , 39 , 40 , 41 , 42 , 43 , 44 , 45 , 46 , 47 , 48 ].

4. How to Distinguish between Conscious Vision, Non-Visual Experience and Blindsight?

In many studies on visual abilities in an apparently blind visual field, the patients were asked, only after the experiment, whether they had a visual experience. Even if the patients claim not to have seen anything, one cannot be sure that they did not have a subjective experience during the experiment. Patients may also not direct their attention to any weak sensation whatsoever, and consequently, may not remember any such sensation at the end of the experiment. Therefore, it is more appropriate to ask the patients immediately after each experimental trial if they only guessed, whether they could see something or whether any sensation occurred. However, unusual visual experiences can occur after brain damage, for which everyday language has no terms. Patients are often unsure if such experiences can be designated as “seeing” and, therefore, deny the question of whether they saw something. Instead of merely relying on the patient’s statement that they had no visual experience and were merely guessing, patients can be asked to indicate their level of confidence on a scale [ 49 ]. The response with which a person indicates the presence or absence of a stimulus, its location, shape, color, etc., will be named “first-order response”, the response with which s/he indicates what confidence s/he has in the correctness of the first-order response, whether s/he only guessed or any conscious sensation occurred, will be named “second-order response”. For example, Mazzi et al. [ 50 , 51 ] used a four-level scale to examine a patient’s subjective experience. A patient who had developed right homonymous hemianopia due to a hemorrhagic stroke was able to discriminate the orientation, color and contrast of a stimulus in her blind visual hemifield when she declared that she responded only by guessing. The patient was asked to rate her subjective experience as either “no visual experience”, “brief glimpse”, “almost clear visual experience”, or “clear visual experience”. The patient was unable to discriminate between two stimulus orientations, motion direction or between two colors when she reported no visual experience or perceiving a small glimpse. Contrast discrimination was only possible at instances when the patient experienced a small glimpse or when she saw the stimuli almost clearly. This experiment demonstrates that it is not sufficient to ask patients whether their responses were made on the grounds of guessing or whether the stimuli were visible. A rating procedure yields more information about the patients´ subjective experiences, but still does not exclude the case where the stimuli elicit a conscious experience which the patients do not term “seeing”, “perceiving a glimpse”, or having any other conscious experience for which the ordinary language has no words. However, it has already been demonstrated earlier [ 36 ] that there are more accurate ways to exclude feelings elicited in blindsight experiments. This study has shown that the degree to which a patient can introspectively recognize his ability of blindsight depends on the experimental conditions. The subjective experience of a 34-year-old hemianopic patient (HU) who was involved in a car accident was extensively investigated in a blindsight experiment [ 36 ]. A CT-scan revealed damage to the geniculostriate projection and its target areas in the left cerebral hemisphere. The lesion caused a right homonymous visual field defect. During the examination, the patient looked into the bowl of a Tuebingen perimeter. Light stimuli (diameter: 69 min/arc; luminance 126.7 cd/m 2 ; background luminance: 3.2 cd/m 2 ) were presented for 500 ms at a location within the blind area of the patient’s visual field. Fixation was controlled through the telescope of the perimeter. An acoustic signal indicated the beginning of a time interval in which either a light stimulus was provided or no light stimulus was present. Intervals in which a light stimulus was present and intervals in which no light stimulus appeared alternated in random order. In 50% of the acoustically marked intervals, a light stimulus was present. No light stimulus was present in the remaining acoustically marked intervals. The patient assured that he could not see anything in the blind area; hence he was asked to guess whether or not a light spot was present. Although the patient affirmed that he had never seen a light stimulus, he guessed correctly in 99% of the 290 experimental trials. The scattering light was measured to exclude its effect. In addition, the stimuli were presented in an area of the visual field that was completely blind and where no unconscious visual processing took place. In a subsequent experiment (Experiment 2), which will also be called “second order experiment”, the same stimuli were presented under the same conditions as in Experiment 1 which will also be called “first order experiment”. Experiment 2 differed from experiment 1 in that the stimuli were presented alternately in a pseudorandom order in 50% of the trials at a location where no processing of stimuli was discovered, and in 50% of the trials at a location where blindsight was demonstrated. The patient was asked to rate his ability to detect the stimulus on a three-level scale. If he was absolutely convinced that he could not detect a stimulus, he was asked to say “no”. If the patient even had the faintest idea that he could detect the stimulus, he should say “weak”, and if he was somewhat sure that he could detect the presence of a stimulus he should say “good”. The latter answer never occurred.

In 61% of 300 trials, the patient’s second-order responses (i.e., the verbal responses “no” and “weak”) were correct. This means that he answered “no” if the stimulus was presented at a location of the visual field where no processing of stimuli had been discovered in a previous experiment, and he answered “weak” if the stimuli appeared at a location where blindsight had been demonstrated in a previous experiment. When the patient was asked after the experiment which subjective experiences he had during the experiment, he stated that he had not even a faint feeling of the presence or absence of a stimulus. The control experiment was identical to the second-order experiment except that a stimulus was always presented outside the patient´s visual field. The difference between the result of the second-order experiment and the result of the control experiment was significant (chi-square test: p  ≤ 0.005). Although a chi-square test showed the result to be significant, this should be interpreted with caution. The percentage (61%) can only be regarded as the degree to which the patient was aware that he was able to distinguish the presence or absence of a stimulus, if it is presupposed that this result did not come about by chance. Therefore, repeated control experiments must demonstrate that subjects cannot achieve a result of 61% correct responses when they generate a sequence of the answers “no” and “weak” in the presence or absence of a stimulus that does not influence their responses. This is, for instance, the case if the stimuli are always presented outside the visual field. Only if it is demonstrated that control subjects cannot achieve a result of 61% correct responses in repeated control experiments, the result of the above described second-order experiment can be regarded as being affected by the presence of the stimulus on a location where no blindsight was possible or on a location where blindsight was possible. Only then the result of 61% can be regarded as a very low level of awareness.

In a second-order experiment, the level of awareness may have a value between 50% and 100%. Therefore, it seems more reasonable to assume that there is a continuous transition between visual processing without awareness (blindsight) and conscious visual perception instead of drawing an arbitrary boundary between type 1 and type 2 blindsight. To investigate the patient´s ability to rate his capacity to process visual stimuli in his apparently blind field in more detail, Experiment 2 was slightly modified and repeated. This experiment was identical to that previously described. The stimuli were again presented alternately in random order in 50% of the trials at a location where no processing of stimuli was possible, and in 50% of the trials the stimuli appeared at a location where blindsight had been demonstrated. The patient was informed that a light spot would be present in every trial. Before the experiment, the light spot was presented at a location where processing of stimuli was possible (blindsight), and the patient was informed that he would be able to detect the presence or absence of the light spot under these conditions. The light spot was also shown at the location where no blindsight occurred, and the patient was informed that under these conditions he could not detect the presence or absence of the stimuli. The patient was asked to compare the trials and indicate the trial in which he felt it was more likely that he could detect the stimuli. In this experiment, the patient´s answer was 100% correct in 300 trials. Such an experiment has the advantage that the patient receives feedback about the sensations associated with the ability to distinguish between the presence and absence of the stimuli. If the presence or absence of a light spot is accompanied by different non visual sensations he can identify them, and he can recognize their significance. In experiments where the patient does not receive such feedback, different non-visual sensations may also be associated with the presence or absence of the light stimulus. In this case, the patient may not recognize that these sensations indicate the presence or absence of a stimulus.

The control experiment was identical to this second-order experiment except that no light stimulus was shown in any trial. The difference between the result of the second-order experiment and the result of the control experiment was significant (chi-square test: p  ≤ 0.0001). Here what has already been stated above is true. Control experiments must demonstrate that the experimental result is not due to chance, and that the outcome of the second-order experiment differs significantly from the outcome of the control experiments. The result of such a second-order experiment (i.e., the degree to which a person can correctly state whether the stimulus was presented at a location of the visual field where s/he was able to discriminate between the presence or absence of a light spot in a first-order experiment or whether the stimulus was presented at a location of the visual field where s/he was unable to discriminate between the presence and absence of a light spot in the first-order experiment) can be interpreted as the degree of introspection in his/her ability to detect the presence or absence of a stimulus. The first-order experiment investigates whether a patient can discriminate between the presence or absence of a stimulus. The second-order experiment investigates whether a person has introspective access to his/her ability to discriminate the presence or absence of a stimulus. The result of this experiment also can have values between 50% and 100%. This also suggests that we should not draw a sharp boundary between “no processing of stimuli”, “type 1 blindsight” and “type 2 blindsight”.

It is noteworthy to state that presenting a light spot at a location of the retina that does not lead to conscious perception or blindsight is not the same as presenting no light stimulus. A light stimulus at this location can elicit activation in a cortical area that leads to neither conscious experience nor blindsight [ 52 ]. If no stimulus is presented, no activation occurs. In the experiment described here, the difference between insufficient and sufficient activation was assessed.

The results of this study demonstrated that the diagnosis of “blindsight” cannot be made on the basis of the patients’ assertion that they don´t see anything and that they only have to guess. The necessity of a scientific introduction of the terms “conscious” and “unconscious” is demonstrated by the example of the insufficient attempt of Railo and Hurme [ 53 ] to characterize the terms “conscious” and “unconscious”. The authors write: “We use the term “conscious” vision to refer to visual perception that is accompanied by experiences that can be introspected by the subject. We use “unconscious” visual perception to refer to situations where the stimuli that the subject denies consciously seeing can nevertheless influence their behavior in some way” [ 53 ] (Section 2.1, first paragraph). An unclear term (conscious) cannot be introduced by characterizing it using another unclear terms such as “visual perception that is accompanied by experiences that can be introspected by the subject”. What is the scientific meaning of “visual perception that is accompanied by experiences” what is the meaning of “introspection”? To date, these terms are used in an unscientific, obscure way in scientific writing. Next it is shown how the concepts “conscious vision” and “blindsight” can be introduced in a logically and experimentally correct way.

5. Introducing the Concepts “Introspection”, “Conscious Vision” and “Blindsight”

As already explained above, the term “conscious vision” must be understood as a theoretical term, introduced by reduction sentences that specify the responses in the second-order experiment under given experimental conditions. If a person is aware of his/her ability to discover the presence or absence of stimuli, shape, color, location, orientation, or direction of movement in the sense mentioned above, s/he has correctly evaluated his/her own abilities without being informed by the experimenter about the outcome of the experiment. In this case, we say that s/he has introspective access to his/her conscious experiences, and that s/he can consciously see the stimuli. These terminologies are common in the interpretation of neuropsychological results, but it misses any scientific justification, and behaviorist objections are still valid. This gives rise to the question, of how one can demystify “conscious experience” and introduce it logically into a contradiction-free language. Hence, the concept “conscious visual experience” must be translated into a language of mathematical logic that clarifies its semantic nature and does not lead to contradictions or obscure assertions.

If D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa)) represents “a Person P can, under experimental conditions Ec, discriminate between the stimuli Sp and Sa”, this is a theoretical term (disposition predicate) which denotes the disposition of a person to respond in a given way when certain experimental conditions are established. If I+(D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa))) represents “P can correctly evaluate his/her ability to discriminate under experimental conditions Ec between the stimuli Sp and Sa” this is also a theoretical term (disposition predicate) which denotes the disposition of a person to respond in a given way (i.e., to evaluate his/her ability to discriminate under experimental conditions Ec between the stimuli Sp and Sa) when certain experimental conditions are established in a second-order experiment. Thus, the terms D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa)) and I+(D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa))) designate dispositions, but they do not yet designate conscious experiences. The conscious visual experience of seeing a light stimulus is not a disposition but a subjective visual occurrence. To designate this conscious subjective experience, we use a logical calculus which includes an abstraction operator that creates abstract objects [ 54 ]. If L(a,b) means a loves b, then α (L(a, b) is the abstraction of L(a, b). α (L(a, b) denotes the love of a for b. I+(D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa))) represents “P can correctly evaluate his/her ability to discriminate under experimental conditions Ec between the stimuli Sp and Sa”, then α[I+(D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa)))] is the abstraction of I+(D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa))). As stated above, in this case, person P has privileged access (introspection) to his/her ability to discriminate the stimuli. α[I+(D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa)))] is the abstraction of this privileged access (introspection). If a person has such a priviledged access (introspection) to his/her ability to visually discriminate between stimuli, it can be said that this person has a conscious visual experience. We can express this with scientific precision by stating that the abstraction α[I+(D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa)))] designates the nature of the privileged access (introspection) or what we call in a non-scientific language the “conscious visual experience”. Everyone can experience how it is to have an experience that is designated by the the abstraction α[I+(D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa)))] when s/he is discriminating stimuli.

In summary: D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa)) is a theoretical concept that is introduced with reduction sentences; I+(D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa))) is a theoretical concept that speaks about the theoretical concept D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa)), and is also introduced with reduction sentences; α[I+(D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa)))] is the abstraction of the theoretical concept I+(D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa))) which speaks about the theoretical concept D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa)). Although theoretical concepts cannot be defined with observational terms, they nevertheless play an indispensable role in scientific theories. However, not all psychological terms that are abstractions correspond to conscious experiences. In the case of “blindsight” without any conscious experience, a person cannot evaluate his/her ability to register the presence or absence of visual stimuli and has no privileged access to this ability. This can be expressed as I−(D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa))). In this case, the presence or absence of visual stimuli does not correspond to conscious visual experiences. The abstraction of the predicate “P cannot evaluate his/her visual ability to discriminate between the presence and absence of visual stimuli” then does not designate a conscious visual experience. From our own conscious experiences, we know which abstractions correspond to conscious experiences. We assume that other people have conscious experiences when they demonstrate the same responses under the same conditions, and when they demonstrate privileged access.

So far, only the two cases have been considered: A person can always detect the presence and absence of a stimulus or is unable to do so. In reality, there is often a smooth transition between these two extremes. When the visual ability of a person is impaired, the presence or absence of visual stimuli may only be detected with a given probability. This probability is investigated in the first-order experiment. This probability is represented by the index p1 which is inserted into the expression D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa)), resulting in the expression D p1 (P(Ec, Sp, Sa)). p1 can take values between p = 0% and p = 100%.

To simplify the argument, only two results of experiment two were initially distinguished: (1) a person has no privileged access, i.e., α[I– (D p1 (P(Ec, Sp, Sa)))] designates no conscious experience, and (2) a person has privileged access, i.e., α[I+(D p1 (P(Ec, Sp, Sa)))] designates a conscious experience. If p1 indicates that the person cannot detect the presence or absence of visual stimuli in the first-order experiment, the stimulus cannot generate a visual experience. However, a second-order experiment can also determine the probability with which a person correctly evaluates his or her own visual ability. As described above, this estimation can be assessed in different ways: The least accurate and most questionable method is to ask the patient after each experiment whether s/he has seen anything. It is somewhat more accurate to ask the patient after each experimental trial whether s/he has seen anything. It is even more accurate to ask a person after each experimental trial to indicate on a rating scale how confident s/he is that s/he has perceived anything. The most accurate method is to have the patient compare the presentation of a stimulus in an area of the visual field where no processing of stimuli takes place with the presentation of a stimulus in an area of the visual field where visual stimuli are processed, as described above. The result is always the frequency with which the patient will provide a given response. This is expressed by the index p2 (replacing the indices + and −: α[I p2 (D(P(Ec, Sp, Sa)))]). The result of the second-order experiment can take values between p = 0% and p = 100%.

It must be demonstrated whether the result is due to chance or whether there is a significant relationship between the patient´s response in the second-order experiment indicating that a stimulus evoked a sensation when the stimulus was presented at a location where visual processing occurred. If the first-order experiment demonstrated that a patient can detect the presence or absence of visual stimuli (indicated by a significant p1 value), but if the second-order experiment did not yield a significant result (indicated by an insignificant p2 value), this demonstrates that the patient had no conscious experience when s/he detected the presence or absence of a stimulus. This corresponds to what has been termed “blindsight”. That a p1- or p2-value is “significant” means that it has been demonstrated that this value did not come about by chance but is due to the influence of the presence or absence of a visual stimulus. If p2 is very small, but if the result is significant, we can designate this in colloquial language as a very faint sensation. Increasing p2-values demonstrate an increasing distinctness of conscious sensation. One may term a significant result of a second-order experiment “type two blindsight” [ 32 , 33 , 34 , 35 , 36 , 37 , 38 , 39 , 40 , 41 , 42 , 43 , 44 , 45 , 46 , 47 , 48 ]. p2-values can express the range between unconscious processing of stimuli and conscous visual experience much more precisely than expressions such as “type one blindsight” or “type two blindsight” can do this.

Taken together, the first-order experiment and the second-order experiment may have the following results:

  • (1) p1 not significant: no visual experience;
  • (2) p1 significant and p2 not significant: visual processing at a given level (represented by the value of p1) without conscious experience;
  • (3) p1 significant and p2 significant: visual processing at a given level (represented by the value of p1) and conscious experience at a given level (represented by the value of p2).

The subjective experiences, when explicitly formulated, are abstract entities of mathematical logic, comparable to the wave equation for electrons in quantum mechanics. Whereas the presence of the wave structure of electrons can be demonstrated by the interference pattern on a screen, the presence of conscious experiences can be demonstrated by the behavior of a person under given conditions, the privileged access, and the simultaneous presence of neurobiological processes. A persons’ behavior under given conditions is intersubjectively observable, and the neurobiological processes can also be observed. For example, when a light stimulus hits a location on the retina (a receptive field), neurons receiving information from the retinal area corresponding to the receptive field, respond by increasing their electrical discharge rate, which can be visualized as an observable histogram. The question arises as to what the neurobiological foundations of conscious experience are and which impairments in cerebral functioning lead to blindsight.

6. The Neurobiological Basis of Conscious Vision and Blindsight

6.1. levels of activation of impaired cortical networks resulting in blindsight or conscious vision.

The phenomenon of “blindsight” may be due to residual functional neural networks in the damaged primary visual cortex. Numerous reports on the recovery of visual function in children [ 55 , 56 , 57 ] and adults [ 58 , 59 , 60 ] demonstrate that impaired neural networks can recover, and the patients may regain the ability to see in a formerly blind visual area. In addition, new connections may emerge and cerebral networks may rearrange. After cerebral hemispherectomy new fiber tracts can connect the ganglion cells of the blind retina to the remaining ipsilateral cerebral hemisphere [ 55 ]. Even in children devoid of the occipital lobe, the visual system can rearrange to such an extent that the children have normal luminance difference thresholds in the whole visual field [ 61 ]. The result of a previous experiment demonstrated that it may depend only on the degree of activation of a neural network whether a stimulus is not processed, whether there is only a feeling of the presence of a stimulus, whether a glimpse of a light is seen, or whether a light spot is clearly seen [ 36 , 37 ]. A 54-year-old man (RS) had a left homonymous hemianopia due to an embolic occlusion of the right middle and the right posterior cerebral artery and subsequent infarction of the right cerebral hemisphere. When a light spot (diameter: 69 min of arc; luminance: 101 cd/m 2 ; background-luminance: 3.2 cd/m 2 ) was moved within the affected (left) visual hemifield, four subareas of the visual field could be distinguished: an area where the patient was completely blind and where no visual processing occurred, an area in which the patient always reported the feeling of the presence of a stimulus without seeing anything, an area where the patient reported seeing a glimpse of light, and an area where the patient could see the light spot clearly. Three sessions of the visual field training were completed in 3 weeks. In each session, the light spot was presented at different locations in the left visual hemifield for 500 ms each. Scattering light was measured to exclude stray light artifacts. The visual field expanded after the conclusion of these three sessions. Now the patient could clearly see the light spot in the part of the visual field where he had previously seen only a glimpse of light. The patient could now see a glimpse of light in the visual area where previously he had only the sensation of the presence of a stimulus. In a part of the previously blind visual field, he now had the feeling of the presence of a stimulus without being able to see anything. After two months cessation of the visual field training, the visual field shrunk again and all the different areas returned to their positions before training. It is unlikely that within three weeks a reorganization of visual connections occurred, and disappeared again in the training-free interval. Therefore, it can be assumed that a neural network survived in the area of the primary visual cortex which represents the apparently blind visual field and that the patient´s experience depended on the extent to which the surviving tissue in the visual cortex was activated. This is in agreement with experiments that demonstrated that blindsight may be due to islands of activity in a damaged area V1 when stimuli are presented in the blind visual area. Using perimetry, Fendrich et al. [ 62 ] found islands of vision of which the patients were unaware in an apparently cerebrally blind area. Other authors have demonstrated areas of activation in a damaged primary visual cortex that represented a perimetrical blind visual area in which there were symptoms of blindsight [ 63 , 64 ] or in damaged areas of the primary visual cortex representing a perimetrically blind visual field [ 65 , 66 ].

6.2. Normal and Impaired Neural Networks in the Visual Cortex That Mediate Conscious Vision and Blindsight

As stated above, a functional visual cortex is a necessary condition for normal vision in humans with a normally developed brain. Injury to the visual cortex can lead to blindness, and residual functions of a damaged cortex can be the neural basis for blindsight. Although clear differences exist between the cortical network of different mammalian species [ 67 , 68 , 69 ] most of the knowledge about the architecture and function of the visual cortex is based on examining the visual cortex of primates such as macaques and, in some cases, chimpanzees, because the greatest similarities were found between their cortices and those of humans [ 70 , 71 , 72 , 73 ]. The visual cortex of primates is divided in 6 layers, some of which have been divided into different sublayers [ 74 ]. Information from three different retinal ganglion cells (P-cells, M-cells and K-cells) predominantly reaches the 6- layered lateral geniculate nucleus (LGN) of the thalamus via the optic nerve [ 75 , 76 , 77 ]. At least 80% of ganglion cells in the fovea are P-cells. They convey information about the color and details of the shape of objects due to their high spatial frequency tuning and high visual resolution but transmit information slower than M-cells. M-cells mediate high temporal frequencies, and have lower spatial frequency tuning but higher conduction velocities than P-cells. They provide information about fast movements and high temporal frequencies but have large receptive fields and mediate low visual acuity [ 78 , 79 , 80 ]. The fibers of P-retinal ganglion cells terminate in the four dorsal layers of the LGN whereas the axons of M-cells terminate in the two ventral layers of the LGN [ 81 ]. The fibers of the geniculo-striate pathway end predominantly in area V1 of the visual cortex and to a much lesser extent in area V2, V3 [ 82 , 83 , 84 , 85 ], and V4 [ 86 , 87 , 88 , 89 ] ( Figure 1 ). The magnocellular layers of the LGN project to area MT/V5 [ 90 , 91 , 92 ] and the inferior temporal gyrus including the lower bank of the superior temporal sulcus [ 93 ]. Neurons from these dorsal LGN layers project primarily to layer 4Cβ of area V1 and project to a much lesser extent to layers 6 and 4A and layer 1 of area V1 [ 94 , 95 , 96 , 97 ]. Layer 1 receives feedback input from layer 6 [ 98 ]. The P-cell projection to layer 4Cβ of area V1 constitutes approximately 18% of the synapses in layer 4Cβ. The highest density of synaptic contacts from the thalamus was found in this layer. A much lower rate of afferent thalamic input to spiny stellate cells was detected in layers 4Cα, which receives predominant input from M-cells, and layer 4Cβ. The density of synapses of thalamic afferents in layer 6 is approximately 16% of the density of thalamic afferent synapses in layer 4Cβ. M-neurons originating in the LGN project primarily to layer 4Cβ of area V1 [ 70 , 99 ]. K-ganglion cells of the retina project to thin koniocellular layers between the P- and M-cell layers of the LGN. There is a K-cell projection from the LGN to blob-like structures in layers 1 and 2/3 of area V1 and to area MT/V5 [ 100 , 101 , 102 , 103 , 104 , 105 , 106 ] ( Figure 1 ). Layers that receive koniocellular input are also targeted by fibers from the superior colliculi [ 104 , 105 , 106 ]. The visual cortices of monkeys and humans contain a variety of neurons. Excitatory neurons can be divided into pyramidal cells and spiny stellate cells [ 107 , 108 , 109 ]. Spines are protrusions on the neurons’ dendrites. Interneurons were divided into different cell types such as Martinotti cells, horsetail shaped cells, neurogliaform cells, basket cells and chandelier cells. Inhibitory interneurons are located in all cortical layers. They are usually gamma-aminobutyric acid (GABA)-ergic, and may target the dendrites, the perisomatic region or the axons of pyramidal cells. Interneurons that contact the perisomatic region of pyramidal cells were called “basket cells”, and interneurons that target the initial segment of axons of pyramidal cells were termed “chandelier cells”. Neurons are further classified, but this classification is still a matter of debate [ 110 ]. Spiny stellate neurons in layer 4C project to layers 2–4B. The majority of 4Cβ neurons project to layers 2 and 3. There is a parvocellular and koniocellular input to layer 3Bβ [ 74 ]. Pyramidal cells and spiny stellate cells in layers 2–4B project to pyramidal cells in layer 5. Layer 4B is predominantly made up of pyramidal cells. The majority of layer 4B pyramidal cells project to area V2 whereas most neurons projecting to area MT/V5 are spiny stellate cells. A small number of pyramidal cells also project from area V1 to area MT/V5. Neurons that project to area V2 receive predominant input from M-neurons in layer 4Cα and from P-neurons in layer 4Cβ. Therefore, pyramidal neurons that project from layer V1 to layer V2 appear to integrate input from P-neurons via neurons of layer 4Cβ and input from M-neurons via neurons of layer 4Cα. Spiny stellate cells are a minority of layer 4B neurons. They receive their input exclusively from layer 4Cα which predominantly receives input from M-cells [ 111 ] ( Figure 1 ). Neurons of layer 5 receive input from laminae 4B, 3B/4A, and 2/3A and a scarcer input from lamina 6. Neurons of lamina 5A project back to lamina 2/3A and laminae 3B/4A and 4C [ 112 ]. Area V1 is connected with Areas V2, V3, V3A, V4, MT/V5, the parieto-occipital cortex, and the posterior intraparietal cortex.

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is brainsci-12-01305-g001.jpg

Schematic drawing of layers and cells in primate area V1. Red triangles: pyramidal cells with apical dendrites (dendritic spines are omitted). Red stars: stellate cells (dendritic spines are omitted). Black: basked cell contacting the perisomatic area of a pyramidal cell. Green: double bouquet cell contacting the apical dendrite of a pyramidal cell. Brown: chandelier cell contacting the dendrites of a pyramidal cell. Blue: konio cell (K) ending in a layer III blob. P: input from an LGN parvo cell contacting the dendrites of a pyramidal cell. M: input from an LGN magno-cell contacting the dendrites of a pyramidal cell. V2: axon of a layer IV pyramidal cell sending information to extrastriate visual area V2. MT: axon of a layer IV stellate cell sending information to area MT/V5.

The contact between neurons is established by excitatory or inhibitory synapses. Excitatory synapses usually contact dendrites or dendritic spines of neurons. In contrast, inhibitory synapses mainly contact the soma and initial segment of neuronal axons and, to a lesser extent, spiny and non-spiny dendritic shafts. The boutons of presynaptic excitatory synapses contain the transmitter glutamate, which is the major transmitter in the primate brain, whereas the vesicles of inhibitory synapses are filled with gamma-aminobutyric acid (GABA) or glycine [ 113 , 114 , 115 , 116 , 117 ]. The postsynaptic membrane cytoplasm contains neurotransmitter receptors that modulate the effect of the transmitter released in the cleft between presynaptic and postsynaptic membranes [ 114 , 118 ]. When arterial blood flow is interrupted and neurons are no longer supplied with oxygen and nutrients, as was the case in many patients who exhibited blindsight (e.g., [ 18 ], patient 3 [ 22 ], patients SL, AG, EA [ 29 ], patient SL [ 50 ], patients AM, FB, LF [ 51 ], patients RC, PF, RA, JP [ 63 ], patient MC [ 64 ], the production of adenosine triphosphate (ATP) by oxidative phosphorylation, which is the predominant function of mitochondria, stops. As a consequence, the Na+/K+ ATPase pumps fail due to the lack of ATP, and Na+ accumulates inside and K+ outside the neurons. Glutamate is released and there is an increased inflow of calcium resulting in continuous neural discharge [ 119 , 120 ]. The cells either die or survive with severe injuries. In the former case, phagocytes remove dead cells, and over time the area is filled with a network of glia cells. In the latter case, neural metabolism is downregulated due to mitochondrial injury. The function of excitatory pyramidal cells and parvalbumin-positive GABAergic inhibitory interneurons that target the soma and dendrites of pyramidal cells is impaired, resulting in decreased inhibition of pyramidal neurons and impairment of the excitatory-inhibitory balance in the cortical network [ 121 , 122 ]. Mitochondria are transported along the axons to synaptic terminals and dendrites to provide energy at different locations, and are required for the synthesis of neurotransmitters, axonal transport, detoxification, regulation of calcium, ion gradient, and the organization of synaptic vesicles. After cerebral damage these mitochondrial functions may be impaired. Upon a decrease in arterial blood flow, blebs appear on the dendrites of the neurons, and part of the spines are lost [ 123 , 124 ]. The length of pyramidal dendrites decreases, and there is a loss of dendritic branches and shrinkage of the dendritic apical tree of (excitatory) pyramidal cells [ 125 ]. Thus, the function of neurons and the interconnections between neurons are impaired [ 126 ]. Traumatic brain damage, like in the patients described above (patient TU [ 36 ], patient FS (published several times [ 127 , 128 , 129 ], and patient GY, published many times, (see, e.g., [ 26 , 32 , 34 , 38 , 40 , 130 , 131 , 132 , 133 , 134 , 135 , 136 , 137 ], also results in cellular dysfunction and cell death due to cytotoxicity of blood, excitotoxicity, oxidative stress and inflammation, and the disruption of neural network, which results in a decrease in axon density [ 138 , 139 , 140 ]. Over time, surviving neurons can recover to some extent, new axons may grow and the function of spared neuronal networks may recover to some extent [ 141 , 142 ]. These results allow us to conclude that unconscious processing of visual stimuli (blindsight) and the feeling of the presence of a light stimulus without conscious visual experience are consequences of the loss of neurons, and their dendritic and axonal connections, as well as a downregulation of cell metabolism in the adult brain. If brain damage occurs in early childhood, a reorganization of neural connections and brain areas may occur, and neural networks of the visual system may emerge in brain areas that have other than visual functions in the normally developed healthy brain. This means that conscious visual experience requires a sufficiently activated, and sufficiently interconnected neural network that comprises a sufficient number of neurons with adequate metabolism. The availability of adenosine triphosphate (ATP) is a necessary condition for the function of the Na+/K+ pump, which is a prerequisite for an increased discharge rate of neurons when a visual stimulus appears in the receptive field of the neuron. The emergence of conscious experience requires the conduction of action potentials to other neurons in a neural network. Fast conduction of action potentials along axons requires a myelin sheath made up of oligodendrocytes and Schwann cells that wrap axons at regular intervals [ 143 ]. Demyelination causes loss of propagation of action potentials resulting in symptoms that include blurred vision or even blindness. The symptoms of demyelinating diseases demonstrate that the conduction of action potentials and interaction with other neurons is a necessary condition for the emergence of conscious experience ([ 144 , 145 ] for review). Synaptic connections between neurons play a crucial role in the emergence of conscious experiences. Conscious experiences are influenced by transmitters released in the synaptic gap and by experience-dependent dynamic modifications at the (mostly dendritic) postsynaptic membrane [ 146 , 147 ]. Overall, these structural and functional impairments in the primary visual cortex do not necessarily result in cerebral blindness. In some cases, the altered functioning of impaired neural networks may still mediate unconscious visual processing or the feeling that something is present without consciously seeing the target. If the impaired network of the primary visual cortex is highly activated, the visual experience of seeing a glimpse of light may emerge or the target may even be consciously seen. However, the geniculo-striate projection is not the only visual pathway. Therefore, the question arises as to whether a pathway other than the geniculate-striate projection can mediate blindsight.

6.3. Is Blindsight Mediated by the Secondary Visual Pathway?

A PET study [ 130 ] demonstrated activation of area MT/V5 when the stimuli were moved at high velocity and when the patient reported conscious awareness of the stimuli. Thus, area V5 was activated in the assumed absence of activation of area V1. It was concluded that area V1 was not necessary for the conscious awareness of a rapidly moving stimulus. Fibers projecting from the LGN to area V5 bypassing area V1 may have mediated the visual perception of a moving stimulus in the absence of area V1.

Experiments demonstrated activation of area hMT+ ( Figure 2 ), when moving or stationary stimuli were presented in a visual area that was blinded due to a damaged primary visual cortex ([ 66 , 137 , 149 , 150 , 151 , 152 , 153 , 154 ] for reviews). In a study by Pedersini et al. [ 155 ], stationary or moving stimuli were presented in the cerebrally blind visual hemifield of 8 Patients with a homonymous visual field defect due to postgeniculate damage. The patients were asked to discriminate the orientation of a stationary or moving bar which was presented in the blind hemifield. Three out of 8 patients performed above chance in the moving condition and 4 out of 8 patients performed above chance in the static condition. Stimuli presented in the blind area activated visual areas V3, V4, hMT+ bilaterally, parietal and frontal areas and the insular and premotor cortex. The highest activation of area hMT+ was found for moving visual stimuli, of which the patient reported unawareness. Patients who performed above chance when discriminating moving stimuli without awareness demonstrated a higher activation of area MT+ than patients who performed at chance. Patients who performed better than chance in the static condition displayed higher activation of the contralesional area V1 and extrastriate visual areas. When pictures of human bodies and faces, butterflies, cars, or meaningless scrambles were presented to a patient who was blind due to the destruction of area V1 of both cerebral hemispheres, and when the patient was asked to guess (yes, no,) whether the stimulus belonged to a given category (e.g., a face), the patient reported no conscious visual experience for the stimuli. However, he reported seeing only changes of luminance when a new stimulus was presented. Nevertheless, the patient was able to guess the presence of human bodies above chance. Images of bodies activated the right extrastriate body area which is located in the lateral occipito-temporal cortex, in the vicinity of the motion-sensitive region hMT/V5+ [ 148 , 156 , 157 ], the right amygdala, orbitofrontal cortex, insula, superior temporal sulcus, and bilateral cerebellum. Pictures of faces activated the right gyrus cinguli, superior temporal sulcus, supramarginal gyrus, left superior parietal lobule, periaqueductal gray and the amygdala [ 158 ]. Barleben et al. [ 52 ] found activity in area hMT, the superior parietal lobule, supramarginal gyrus, and lateral and middle occipital gyri of 6 patients, whereas no activity was observed in the damaged striate cortex. In two patients who did not show activity in area hMT, lesions included subcortical pathways from the pulvinar to area hMT. None of the patients showed any symptoms of blindsight nor did they see rapidly moving stimuli (Riddoch effect). The authors conclude that there may be activity in area hMT, even though there is neither blindsight nor conscious visual experience. Some patients who participated in experiments on blindsight suffered from long-standing injuries dating back several decades and some patients (e.g., patient GY) participated in numerous experiments [ 26 , 28 , 32 , 126 , 127 , 128 , 129 , 130 , 131 , 132 , 133 , 134 , 135 , 136 ]. Over time, new connections could have developed and structures of the visual system could have been rearranged. Therefore, insights into the function of a damaged brain that has been stimulated in many experiments over many years should be applied with caution to normal brains. Repeated stimulation of cerebrally blind areas has been demonstrated to improve visual functions in a cerebrally blind hemifield [ 36 , 37 , 42 , 56 , 57 , 58 , 59 , 60 ] and can even lead to considerable restitution of visual functions due to a rearrangement of neural networks in children and adult patients [ 55 , 56 , 57 , 58 , 59 ].

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is brainsci-12-01305-g002.jpg

Location of area hMT+ (encircled) on the left hemisphere of the human brain. FL: frontal lobe, TL: temporal lobe, CB: cerebellum [ 148 ].

Activation of area hMT+ can be mediated by a secondary visual pathway from the retina via the superior colliculi (SC) and the pulvinar. In monkeys, there is a direct projection from the retina to the SC [ 159 , 160 , 161 , 162 , 163 , 164 , 165 ]. About 10% of the retinal ganglion cells project to the SC [ 166 ]. Neurons of the SC were responsive to stationary and moving stimuli, size, color, and contrast [ 167 , 168 , 169 , 170 , 171 , 172 ]. The SC projects to the dorsal lateral geniculate nucleus and to the posterior and medial nuclei of the inferior pulvinar. The pulvinar is the largest nucleus of the primate thalamus and is divided into different subnuclei. The ventral pulvinar, which includes ventral parts of the lateral pulvinar and inferior pulvinar is connected with areas V1, V2, V4, and the inferotemporal cortex [ 173 , 174 ]. There is a rather sparse projection to the lateral and medial pulvinar and to the central lateral nucleus of the inferior pulvinar. The cortical area MT, which receives its main input from the medial nucleus of the inferior pulvinar does not receive input from the SC via the medial nucleus of the inferior pulvinar [ 175 , 176 , 177 , 178 , 179 ]. The SC projects to the caudal nucleus of the pulvinar and to the lateral and medial aspects of the rostral pulvinar. The caudal nucleus sends fibers back to the SC. The SC also projects to the dorsal and ventral parts of the lateral geniculate nucleus, to the pretectum, and to the inferior colliculi [ 180 , 181 ]. There is a retinotopic representation in the inferior and lateral pulvinar in rhesus monkeys. The inferior and lateral nuclei of the pulvinar respond to visual stimuli [ 182 ]. The results of a functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) study in patients with bilateral lesions of the primary visual cortex demonstrate a direct connection between the LGN and area hMT+ which conveys visual information after damage to area V1 [ 151 ]. This study also demonstrates that the contralesional normal visual cortex is not needed for visual functions after damage to the primary visual cortex.

6.4. How Much Cortex Is Needed for Conscious Visual Perception?

The question is whether the SC, pretectum, and pulvinar are sufficient for mediating “unconscious” processing of visual stimuli. Georgy et al. [ 183 ] assumed that the SC ( Figure 3 ) plays a pivotal role in processing gestalt-like or structured stimuli and in initiating motor responses. The authors investigated two hemispherectomized patients in whom the route from the retina to the SC on the hemispherectomized side was left intact. Stimulation of both visual hemifields yielded faster reaction times than single stimulation of the unaffected visual hemifield. The increasing speeds of the reaction times were especially pronounced if the stimuli were gestalt-like but not random shapes. However, this does not justify the assumption that the SC is sufficient to mediate the speeding of reaction times. In hemisperectomized patients, new unusual connections can develop over time, resulting in a projection from the visual hemifield contralateral to the hemispherectomy to the normal healthy cerebral hemisphere. Thus, the healthy hemisphere can represent both visual hemifields. Werth [ 55 ] has already demonstrated that light spots in the visual hemifield contralateral to hemispherectomy can be detected, localized, and reported as seen. In the patient who participated in this study, functional hemispherectomy was performed at the age of 135 months. The fibers targeting the frontal and occipital lobes were completely interrupted by undercutting the white matter underlying the frontal and occipital lobe. Light spots in the visual hemifield contralateral to the affected cerebral hemisphere were detected, locatized, and reported as seen up to 30 deg eccentricity. When light spots were presented in the affected left half of the visual field, functional MRI revealed activity in areas V1, V2, and V4 of the ipsilateral (left) hemisphere. These findings demonstrate that after hemispherectomy new fiber connections can be established contacting the occipital lobe of the hemisphere ipsilateral to the affected visual hemifield. Detailed investigation of visual functions in patients who underwend hemispherectomy in early life have demonstrated a rearrangemant of visual fiber connections to such an extent that stimuli were detected and localized up to 90 degrees eccentricity in the visual hemifield contraleteral to the missing cerebral hemisphere. Werth [ 55 ] reported the case of a 28-month-old child (patient FO) in whom the striate cortex and underlying white matter of the left cerebral hemisphere were replaced by a large cyst. Nevertheless, the child had a normally extended visual field with normal luminance difference thresholds in both visual hemifields. The child located light spots that were presented between 10 and 90 deg eccentricity, directed his gaze towards the stimuli and fixated them. Another patient (GI) [ 55 ] had undergone complete hemispherectomy at 4 months of age. This girl also had a normally extended visual field at the age of 59 months. The child detected light spots presented between 10 and 90 degrees eccentricity, directed eye and head movement towards the stimuli, and fixated them subsequently. However, the luminance difference threshold in the visual hemifield contralateral to the removed cerebral hemisphere was elevated. This demonstrates that a healthy hemisphere can represent both visual hemifields. It may be that the ability of “blindsight” in a visual hemifield contralateral to a removed cerebral hemisphere is also due to fiber connections targeting functional areas of the remaining cerebral hemisphere. However, children in whom the visual cortex and underlying white matter in both cerebral hemispheres are missing may still have a normally extended visual field with normal luminance difference thresholds. The child (KU) about whom Werth [ 55 ] reported, was a 19-month-old girl. The girl had developed a large prosencephalic cyst that was located in the occipital lobe of both cerebral hemispheres. The cyst included Brodman’s areas 17, 18, and 19 of both occipital lobes, both banks of the sulcus calcarinus, gyrus occipitotemporalis medialis, gyrus lingualis, and the cuneus and praecuneus. The child detected and located light spots between 10 and 90 deg eccentricity in both halves of the visual field, directed eye- and head movements to them and fixated them subsequently.

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is brainsci-12-01305-g003.jpg

Right superior colliculus (rSC) and right inferior colliculus (rIC) of the human brain. OL: occipital lobe, CB: cerebellum.

6.5. Sensory Capacity of the Human Colliculi

The capacity of the SC ( Figure 3 ) to process sensory information can only be demonstrated in the complete absence of the telencephalon and preserved inferior and superior colliuli. Werth [ 61 ] reported the case of a 6-year-old hydranencephalic boy (patient AG), who regularly directed his head and eyes towards an auditory stimulus, although the child’s telencephalon was completely absent. Only the brainstem including the superior and inferior colliculi and the pretectum was preserved. In another child (patient HE), aged 28 months both cerebral hemispheres were replaced by a liquor filled cyst containing septum-like remnants of glial tissue. Only the brainstem including the pons, superior and inferior colliculi, the pretectum, and remnants of the ventral frontal lobe were preserved. The child was unable to locate light spots presented in her visual field, but regularly followed a face that was presented in the center of the visual field, with eye- and head movements [ 61 ]. If we assume that the presence of the telencephalon is a necessary condition for the emergence of a conscious visual or auditory experience, it could be said that these children also responded unconsciously to visual or auditory stimuli. This presumably unconscious processing of visual or auditory stimuli was mediated by the brain stem, including the inferior and superior colliculi and the pretectum.

6.6. A Functional Visual System Is Not Sufficient for Conscious Visual Experience

If the projection from the retina to the cortex of the occipital lobe is unaffected by a cerebral lesion, and if the function of areas V1–V4 is unimpaired, conscious visual experience can nevertheless be absent. Patients who suffer from a neglect of one half of space after a cerebral lesion, demonstrate that an unimpaired primary and secondary visual system is not sufficient for conscious visual perception. They do not register objects in one half of space to the left or right of their body midline and do not recognize the left or right half of objects. They eat only from one half of a plate and do not notice that the plate has another half, and read only the text on the right half of a sheet and wonder about the incoherence of the text. If they are asked to draw an object, such as a flower, they draw only one half of the flower—usually the right half—and do not recognize that the other half is missing. They do not search for objects in the neglected half of space with eye and head movements, do not wash or dress one half of their body, and shave or apply makeup on only one half of their face [ 184 ]. A survey that also includes French and German literature ([ 185 ], for review), and reviews of the English literature [ 186 , 187 , 188 , 189 ] show that lesions causing a visual neglect of one half of space are predominately located in the the caudal parts of the supramarginal gyrus, angular gyrus, and the superior temporal sulcus of the right cerebral hemisphere. This demonstrates that conscious visual experience can only appear when many brain structures interact with the visual system.

7. Summary and Conclusions

In the present paper, it has been shown that the concepts “conscious visual experience” and “unconscious visual processing” can be introduced in a logically and methodologically correct way in the scientific language. Whether visual performance is classified as conscious or unconscious depends strongly on the experimental procedure used to draw the boundary between conscious and unconscious visual processing of stimuli. It turns out that patients’ claims of seeing nothing in a perimetrically blind visual hemifield and of only guessing the presence, orientation, shape, color or direction of motion of stimuli are not sufficient to determine whether a stimulus elicits a visual or other type of conscious experience. Unconscious processing of visual stimuli (blindsight), the feeling of the presence of a light stimulus, without conscious visual experience, and an elevated threshold for the emergence of conscious visual experience, are a consequence of the loss of neurons, and their dendritic and axonal connections, and downregulation of cell metabolism after damage to the visual cortex. Normal conscious visual experience requires a sufficiently activated number of interconnected neurons with sufficient metabolism. In the complete absence of the visual cortex, blindsight can also be mediated by a secondary visual pathway from the retina via the midbrain to cortical areas V4 and MT/V5.

Funding Statement

This research received no external funding.

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

  • Search Menu

Sign in through your institution

  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Residential and Domestic Buildings
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Learning (Specific Skills)
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Language Acquisition
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethics in Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Culture
  • Music and Religion
  • Music and Media
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Construction Law
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Society
  • Law and Politics
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Study and Revision
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Neuroanaesthesia
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Oncology
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Medical Ethics
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Self-help and Personal Development
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Cell Biology
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Graphical and Digital Media Applications
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Electronics and Communications Engineering
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Ceramics and Glasses
  • Composite Materials
  • Metals, Alloying, and Corrosion
  • Nanotechnology
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business History
  • Business Strategy
  • Business Ethics
  • Business and Government
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic History
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Applied Ecology (Social Science)
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • International Political Economy
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Theory
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Politics and Law
  • Politics of Development
  • Public Administration
  • Public Policy
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • East Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Land Forces and Warfare
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Naval Forces and Warfare
  • Other Warfare and Defence Issues
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution
  • Weapons and Equipment

Introspection and Consciousness

  • < Previous chapter
  • Next chapter >

Introspection and Consciousness

1 Introspection, What?

  • Published: July 2012
  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

Introspection is not a single process but a plurality of processes. It’s a plurality both within and between cases: Most individual introspective judgments arise from a plurality of processes (that’s the within-case claim), and the collection of processes issuing in introspective judgments differs from case to case (that’s the between-case claim). Introspection is not the operation of a single cognitive mechanism or small collection of mechanisms. Introspective judgments arise from a shifting confluence of many processes, recruited opportunistically. Introspection is the dedication of central cognitive resources, or attention, to the task of arriving at a judgment about one’s current, or very recently past, conscious experience, using or attempting to use some capacities that are unique to the first-person case, with the aim or intention that one’s judgment reflect some relatively direct sensitivity to the target state. Cases discussed include visual experience, emotion, and auditory imagery.

Signed in as

Institutional accounts.

  • Google Scholar Indexing
  • GoogleCrawler [DO NOT DELETE]

Personal account

  • Sign in with email/username & password
  • Get email alerts
  • Save searches
  • Purchase content
  • Activate your purchase/trial code
  • Add your ORCID iD

Institutional access

Sign in with a library card.

  • Sign in with username/password
  • Recommend to your librarian
  • Institutional account management
  • Get help with access

Access to content on Oxford Academic is often provided through institutional subscriptions and purchases. If you are a member of an institution with an active account, you may be able to access content in one of the following ways:

IP based access

Typically, access is provided across an institutional network to a range of IP addresses. This authentication occurs automatically, and it is not possible to sign out of an IP authenticated account.

Choose this option to get remote access when outside your institution. Shibboleth/Open Athens technology is used to provide single sign-on between your institution’s website and Oxford Academic.

  • Click Sign in through your institution.
  • Select your institution from the list provided, which will take you to your institution's website to sign in.
  • When on the institution site, please use the credentials provided by your institution. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.
  • Following successful sign in, you will be returned to Oxford Academic.

If your institution is not listed or you cannot sign in to your institution’s website, please contact your librarian or administrator.

Enter your library card number to sign in. If you cannot sign in, please contact your librarian.

Society Members

Society member access to a journal is achieved in one of the following ways:

Sign in through society site

Many societies offer single sign-on between the society website and Oxford Academic. If you see ‘Sign in through society site’ in the sign in pane within a journal:

  • Click Sign in through society site.
  • When on the society site, please use the credentials provided by that society. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.

If you do not have a society account or have forgotten your username or password, please contact your society.

Sign in using a personal account

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members. See below.

A personal account can be used to get email alerts, save searches, purchase content, and activate subscriptions.

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members.

Viewing your signed in accounts

Click the account icon in the top right to:

  • View your signed in personal account and access account management features.
  • View the institutional accounts that are providing access.

Signed in but can't access content

Oxford Academic is home to a wide variety of products. The institutional subscription may not cover the content that you are trying to access. If you believe you should have access to that content, please contact your librarian.

For librarians and administrators, your personal account also provides access to institutional account management. Here you will find options to view and activate subscriptions, manage institutional settings and access options, access usage statistics, and more.

Our books are available by subscription or purchase to libraries and institutions.

  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Rights and permissions
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

Procter Hall exterior image shown

UC College of Nursing researcher accepted for prestigious fellowship for nurse leaders and innovators

headshot of Evelyn  Fleider

Samantha Boch, PhD, RN, assistant professor at the University of Cincinnati College of Nursing and affiliate faculty of the James M. Anderson Center for Health Systems Excellence at Cincinnati Children's Hospital is one of 16 nurse scientists accepted to the fifth cohort of the Betty Irene Moore Fellowship for Nurse Leaders and Innovators . The fellowship program, funded by grants from the Gordon and Betty Moore Foundation , recognizes and advances early-to-mid-career nursing scholars and innovators with a high potential to accelerate leadership in nursing research, practice, education, policy and entrepreneurship.

The Gordon and Betty Moore Foundation seeks to prepare nurses as collaborative leaders with the skills and confidence to inspire others, enact change and challenge the status quo. Through the creation of the Betty Irene Moore Fellowship for Nurse Leaders and Innovators, the foundation supports nurse leaders who take ideas to scale that advance high-quality, high-value care and optimal health outcomes.

“Our motto is UC Nurses. We See Leaders ,” Interim Dean Gordon Gillespie, PhD, DNP, RN, FAAN, says. “Sam is the epitome of a nursing leader and scholar; I can’t wait to see the impact her project will have in advancing health equity and education in our country.”

Samantha Boch, PhD, RN

As a part of the three-year fellowship program , Boch will receive $450,000 to conduct an innovative project focused on better understanding the health of and use of health services by children in foster care who also experience parental incarceration. Mentored by Cincinnati Children’s Hospital CHECK (Comprehensive Health Evaluations for Cincinnati’s Kids) Foster Care Center Medical Director Mary Greiner, MD, MS, and Scientific Director for Child Welfare Research Sarah Beal, PhD, Boch will leverage CHECK’s data to identify opportunities to better care for those children.

She will also partner with Ebony Underwood, CEO & Founder of WE GOT US NOW , the nation’s leading organization advancing the wellbeing of children and young adults with incarcerated parents, to co-design care guidelines for children who experience parental incarceration.

"I am thrilled to be in partnership with Sam,” Underwood says. “Her commitment to uplifting and elevating the subject matter expertise of those closest to this issue is a testament to her leadership and dedication in advancing the health equity and well-being for the vulnerable population of children impacted by parental incarceration."

A forensic nurse scientist, Boch’s program of research centers on the social determinants of health with particular emphasis on understanding and mitigating the consequences of mass incarceration on child and family health.

“I’m deeply honored to have been chosen as part of the cohort for the Betty Irene Moore Fellowship for Nurse Leaders and Innovators,” says Boch. “This is a unique opportunity to further develop my leadership skills and partner with amazing organizations, mentors, and individuals with lived experiences of parental incarceration to positively impact care and the health of these families.”

Featured top image of the UC College of Nursing. Photo provided.

  • Urban Impact
  • College of Nursing

Related Stories

May 29, 2024

Samantha Boch, PhD, RN, assistant professor at the University of Cincinnati College of Nursing and affiliate faculty of the James M. Anderson Center for Health Systems Excellence at Cincinnati Children's Hospital is one of 16 nurse scientists accepted to the fifth cohort of the Betty Irene Moore Fellowship for Nurse Leaders and Innovators. The fellowship program, funded by grants from the Gordon and Betty Moore Foundation, recognizes and advances early-to-mid-career nursing scholars and innovators with a high potential to accelerate leadership in nursing research, practice, education, policy and entrepreneurship

UC research program gives underrepresented students a chance

August 4, 2022

UC’s Undergraduates Pursuing Research in Science and Engineering gives students in underrepresented groups the opportunity to engage with faculty and peers in scientific research.

UC research finds link between poor health, low breast milk production

September 29, 2022

New research from UC shows that poor metabolic health parameters are linked to low breast milk production. The study was published in the journal Breastfeeding Medicine.

IMAGES

  1. Introspection and Observation Method in Psychology

    introspection a research tool used by early

  2. Introspection was employed as a research tool in the late 1800s because

    introspection a research tool used by early

  3. Introspection in Psychology: Definition and Examples (2024)

    introspection a research tool used by early

  4. Early School Of Psychology That Employed The Method Of Introspection

    introspection a research tool used by early

  5. Introspection Psychology

    introspection a research tool used by early

  6. INTROSPECTION METHOD IN PSYCHOLOGY

    introspection a research tool used by early

VIDEO

  1. introspection?

  2. A Fimilar Feeling

  3. Morning Dreams

  4. Village Ambience

  5. Introduction to Educational Research

  6. Shadows

COMMENTS

  1. Introspection: Definition, Uses, Examples, and Tips

    In everyday use, introspection is a way of looking inward and examining one's internal thoughts and feelings. As a research tool, however, the process was much more controlled and structured. ... can be used to describe both an informal reflection process and a more formalized experimental approach that was used early on in psychology's history ...

  2. Introspection as the Basic Method in Psychological Science

    Introspection as a Method to Link Proactive and Retroactive Movements. The history of the advancement of introspection as a research method is closely linked with the names of Oswald Külpe and Karl Bühler. Külpe was one of the assistants of Wilhelm Wundt in Leipzig before establishing himself as a professor in Würzburg in 1894.

  3. Early Psychology—Structuralism and Functionalism

    Structuralism is one of the earliest schools of psychology, focused on understanding the conscious experience through introspection. It was introduced by Wilhelm Wundt and built upon by his student, Edward Titchener. Let's review a brief history of how structuralism was developed by these two scholars. Wilhelm Wundt (1832-1920) was a German ...

  4. Structuralism: Introspection and the Awareness of Subjective Experience

    Structuralists used the method of introspection to attempt to create a map of the elements of consciousness. Introspection involves asking research participants to describe exactly what they experience as they work on mental tasks, such as viewing colors, reading a page in a book, or performing a math problem. A participant who is reading a ...

  5. Unlocking the Power of Introspection and How It Is Used In Psychology

    Introspection is examining your thoughts, emotions, judgments, and perceptions inwardly. It's a valuable tool in psychology research, as it allows researchers to gain insight into the mind's inner workings. Introspection has a long history in psychology, dating back to the early days of the field. While it's not always considered a ...

  6. (PDF) The Meaning of Introspection: Introspection, Scientific

    The "introspectionism" explicitly reject takes aim at the expansive concept of introspection among early structuralists such as Edward B. Titchener (1867-1927) and Oswald Külpe (1862-1915). 3 ...

  7. Introspection

    Introspection. Introspection, as the term is used in contemporary philosophy of mind, is a means of learning about one's own currently ongoing, or perhaps very recently past, mental states or processes. You can, of course, learn about your own mind in the same way you learn about others' minds—by reading psychology texts, by observing ...

  8. Editorial: The Challenges and Opportunities of Introspection in

    He points out how phenomenological research needs to be used to systematize psychopathological experiences rather than understand them via the detour of physiology. In his article Husserlian phenomenology as a kind of introspection , Gutland introduces phenomenology as a form of introspection and gives an overview over Husserl's ...

  9. Researcher introspection for experience-driven design research

    As briefly introduced before, guided introspection can be found in many widely accepted research methods (e.g. verbal protocol analysis, in-depth phenomenological interview, written self-report) in which, under the researcher's guidance, only subjects (other than the researcher) are invited to examine and report their experiences. It appears to be the least problematic from a positivist ...

  10. Introspection

    Introspection, as the term is used in contemporary philosophy of mind, is a means of learning about one's own currently ongoing, or perhaps very recently past, mental states or processes. ... the cognitive processes involved in early visual processing and in the detection of phonemes are generally held to be introspectively impenetrable and ...

  11. Introspection

    Introspection Definition. The term introspection is generally used by psychologists to refer to people's observation and contemplation of their own thoughts, feelings, and sensations. In early psychology, trained introspection was viewed as a useful tool for acquiring data about the nature of such cognitions, though the methodology fell into ...

  12. Introspection

    introspection, (from Latin introspicere, "to look within"), the process of observing the operations of one's own mind with a view to discovering the laws that govern the mind. In a dualistic philosophy, which divides the natural world (matter, including the human body) from the contents of consciousness, introspection is the chief method ...

  13. Introspection (Early Use)

    Introspection (Early Use) Introspection means "looking into" and refers to the process of observing and examining your own conscious thoughts or emotions. Before Wundt, introspection had been used by philosophers for studying how new ideas are created. These philosophers did not set any limits on the tasks they studied or make any judgments ...

  14. Introspection in psychology: Its contribution to theory and method in

    Memory is typically conceptualized as a mental space where information is stored until it is retrieved for current processing. This archive account has been undermined by a multitude of findings, however, calling for a theoretical and also a methodological reorientation. In particular, we consider it timely to include an introspective mode of research into the study of memory because such ...

  15. A Scientific Approach to Conscious Experience, Introspection, and

    2. Psychological Terms Understood as Theoretical Concepts. Carnap realized that many major psychological concepts cannot be defined by terms that designate observational entities such as observable behavior under given observable circumstances [].For example, if we attempted to define the term "arachnophobia" by the statement "P has arachnophobia" it would mean "whenever P sees a ...

  16. Introspection, What?

    Introspection is not the operation of a single cognitive mechanism or small collection of mechanisms. Introspective judgments arise from a shifting confluence of many processes, recruited opportunistically. Introspection is the dedication of central cognitive resources, or attention, to the task of arriving at a judgment about one's current ...

  17. Introspection: Definition (in Psychology), Examples, and Questions

    Introspection is the examination or observation of one's own mental and emotional processes. Through introspection, we can gain knowledge about our inner workings. Introspection is sort of like perception, but also unlike perception in that it doesn't involve the five senses. We don't see, hear, smell, touch, or taste to gain insights.

  18. Psych Exam

    Introspection, a research tool used by early psychologists, is a technique which involves... Self-examination of mental processes. An early school of psychology that used introspection to explore the structural elements of the human mind: Structuralism.

  19. Introspection

    Introspection is the examination of one's own conscious thoughts and feelings. In psychology, the process of introspection relies on the observation of one's mental state, while in a spiritual context it may refer to the examination of one's soul. Introspection is closely related to human self-reflection and self-discovery and is contrasted with external observation.

  20. AP Psychology Unit 1/2 Questions Flashcards

    Introspection, a research tool used by early psychologists, is a technique which involves A. correlational analyses B. machines designed for cognitive analysis C. survey methodology D. self-examination of mental processes E. teaching participants to multitask. D. self-examination of mental processes.

  21. UNIT 1: PSYCHOLOGY Flashcards

    Introspection, a research tool used by early psychologists, is a technique which involves a)correlational analyses B)machines designed for cognitive analysis C)survey methodology D)self-examination of mental processes E)teaching participants to multitask. d) Self-examination of mental processes.

  22. Unit 1

    introspection, a research tool used by early psychologists, is a technique which involves. self-examination of mental processes. the belief that human behavior is the result of unconscious drives and conflicts represents which of the following theoretical perspectives.

  23. UC College of Nursing researcher accepted for prestigious fellowship

    As a part of the three-year fellowship program, Boch will receive $450,000 to conduct an innovative project focused on better understanding the health of and use of health services by children in foster care who also experience parental incarceration.Mentored by Cincinnati Children's Hospital CHECK (Comprehensive Health Evaluations for Cincinnati's Kids) Foster Care Center Medical Director ...

  24. Psych Unit 1 Test Flashcards

    Introspection, a research tool used by early psychologists, is a technique involving. Self examination of mental processes. Psychodynamic Therapy has its roots in. ... A researcher surveyed social adjustment in the same group of 20 people from early childhood through adulthood. In this example, the group of 20 people surveyed was the study's.