Greater Good Science Center • Magazine • In Action • In Education

Does Ethics Require Religion?

There is a spectrum of views about how religion and ethics are related—from the view that religion is the absolute bedrock of ethics to one that holds that ethics is based on humanistic assumptions justified mainly, and sometimes only, by appeals to reason. These two extremes tend to be argued in a way that offers little room for compromise or pragmatic solutions to real issues we face everyday.

The relationship between religion and ethics is about the relationship between revelation and reason. Religion is based in some measure on the idea that God (or some deity) reveals insights about life and its true meaning. These insights are collected in texts (the Bible, the Torah, the Koran, etc.) and presented as “revelation.” Ethics, from a strictly humanistic perspective, is based on the tenets of reason: Anything that is not rationally verifiable cannot be considered justifiable. From this perspective, ethical principles need not derive their authority from religious doctrine. Instead, these principles are upheld for their value in promoting independent and responsible individuals—people who are capable of making decisions that maximize their own well-being while respecting the well-being of others.

Even though religious and secular ethics don’t derive their authority from the same source, we still must find a way to establish common ground between them; otherwise we’re condemning ourselves to live amidst social discord and division.

ethics in religion essay

I believe we can accommodate the requirements of reason and religion by developing certain qualities that we would bring to our everyday ethical discussions. Aristotle said that cultivating qualities (he called them “virtues”) like prudence, reason, accommodation, compromise, moderation, wisdom, honesty, and truthfulness, among others, would enable us all to enter the discussions and conflicts between religion and ethics—where differences exist—with a measure of moderation and agreement. When ethics and religion collide, nobody wins; when religion and ethics find room for robust discussion and agreement, we maximize the prospects for constructive choices in our society.

About the Author

James a. donahue.

James A. Donahue, Ph.D., is the president and a professor of ethics at the Graduate Theological Union.

You May Also Enjoy

ethics in religion essay

Empathy vs. Logic vs. Morality

Moral intuition.

ethics in religion essay

The Science of Spirituality: A Review of Fingerprints of God

Moral monkeys.

ethics in religion essay

Do we need God to be good?

GGSC Logo

Rega Academy

The Role of Religion in Ethics: A Comprehensive Examination

ethics in religion essay

The relationship between religion and ethics has been a topic of profound philosophical, theological, and societal interest for centuries. Throughout human history, various religions have played a significant role in shaping moral values, guiding ethical conduct, and influencing the moral decision-making of individuals and communities. This complex interplay between religion and ethics has sparked extensive debates and investigations, making it a crucial subject of study.

ethics in religion essay

A. Significance of the Topic:

Understanding the role of religion in ethics is essential as it provides insights into how belief systems and values impact human behavior and societal norms. By exploring the connections between religious teachings and ethical frameworks, we can gain a deeper appreciation for the diverse range of moral perspectives in the world and how they shape human interactions, laws, and cultural practices.

B. Purpose of the Research:

The primary purpose of this research is to comprehensively examine the multifaceted relationship between religion and ethics. By delving into historical perspectives, philosophical theories, psychological and sociological studies, as well as contemporary debates, we aim to shed light on the various ways in which religion influences ethical decision-making and moral behavior.

C. Thesis Statement:

This research article aims to explore the role of religion in ethics by investigating its historical significance, theological and philosophical underpinnings, empirical evidence, and contemporary implications. Through a rigorous analysis of diverse perspectives and case studies, we seek to provide a nuanced understanding of how religion shapes ethical principles and contributes to the complex landscape of morality in the modern world.

I. Understanding Ethics and Religion

A. definitions and concepts of ethics:.

Ethics refers to the philosophical study of moral principles and values that guide human behavior and decision-making. It involves the examination of what is right or wrong, good or bad, and just or unjust. Ethical theories provide frameworks for analyzing moral dilemmas, and they often focus on concepts such as virtue, duty, consequences, and moral character. Ethical systems attempt to address fundamental questions about how individuals should live, treat others, and make choices in various contexts.

B. Definitions and Concepts of Religion:

Religion encompasses a broad spectrum of belief systems and practices centered around the existence of a higher power or powers that influence and govern the universe and human life. It includes various rituals, traditions, doctrines, scriptures, and teachings that guide the spiritual and moral aspects of believers’ lives. Religions often involve shared values, moral codes, and ethical teachings that shape the ethical outlook of their followers.

C. Overview of the Relationship Between Ethics and Religion:

The relationship between ethics and religion has been a topic of ongoing discussion and contention. There are various perspectives on how religion and ethics intersect and influence each other:

  • Religious Ethics : Many religions provide their adherents with explicit moral guidelines and ethical principles derived from sacred texts or the teachings of revered figures. These religious ethical systems often offer absolute moral truths and a sense of duty grounded in divine authority. Examples include the Ten Commandments in Judaism and Christianity or the Five Pillars of Islam.
  • Theological Approaches : Theological perspectives on ethics, such as divine command theory and natural law theory, propose that moral obligations are derived from God or a higher cosmic order. These views suggest that ethical principles are intrinsic to religious belief and that ethical conduct aligns with the will of a divine entity.
  • Secular Ethics and Religious Influence : While some ethical theories are independent of religious beliefs, it is undeniable that religion has historically played a crucial role in shaping moral values and cultural norms. Religious teachings often contribute to the ethical framework of societies, even for individuals who do not identify as religious.
  • Diverse Ethical Perspectives : Different religions hold distinct ethical perspectives, which can sometimes lead to conflicting moral viewpoints. Additionally, the presence of multiple religions in a society may lead to ethical pluralism, where different religious communities coexist with diverse moral codes.
  • Challenges and Critiques : The role of religion in ethics has faced criticism, particularly when religious teachings conflict with evolving social values or when they are used to justify harmful actions or discrimination. Overall, the relationship between ethics and religion is multifaceted and varies across different cultures, religions, and historical periods. Understanding this complex interplay is essential for comprehending the foundations of moral values and ethical decision-making in diverse societies.

II. Historical Perspectives on the Relationship Between Ethics and Religion

A. ancient religious ethics:.

  • Mesopotamia: In ancient Mesopotamia, ethical principles were often intertwined with religious beliefs. The Code of Hammurabi, one of the earliest known legal codes, included moral precepts and laws inspired by the Babylonian god Marduk. The concept of divine justice and social order influenced ethical norms and punishment for wrongdoing.
  • Egypt: Ancient Egyptian ethics were deeply rooted in religious practices, rituals, and beliefs in the afterlife. Ma’at, the concept of cosmic order and justice, played a central role in guiding ethical conduct. Individuals were expected to adhere to Ma’at’s principles of truth, justice, and harmony to maintain social order.
  • Greece: Ancient Greek philosophers, such as Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, explored ethical questions independently of religious doctrines. However, religious beliefs in Greek society still influenced moral values. For instance, concepts like the Golden Rule and the idea of virtues were found in both religious and philosophical teachings.
CivilizationEthical SystemKey CharacteristicsPrinciples and Values
MesopotamiaBabylonian EthicsTheocracy, Hammurabi’s CodeJustice, Retribution, Social Hierarchy
EgyptMa’atHarmony, Order, Divine BalanceTruth, Justice, Righteousness
GreeceVirtue EthicsPhilosophical inquiryArete (Excellence), Wisdom, Courage
India (Hindu)DharmaDuty, Moral LawAhimsa (Non-harm), Righteous Conduct
India (Buddhist)Noble Eightfold PathElimination of SufferingRight View, Right Intention, Right Action
ChinaConfucian EthicsFilial Piety, Ren (Humaneness)Benevolence, Respect for Tradition

B. Influence of Major World Religions on Ethical Frameworks:

  • Christianity: Christian ethics are heavily based on the teachings of Jesus Christ, as recorded in the Bible’s New Testament. The Sermon on the Mount, for example, emphasizes love, compassion, forgiveness, and the golden rule: “Do to others as you would have them do to you.” Christian ethical frameworks also include moral absolutes derived from divine command, such as the Ten Commandments.
  • Islam: Islamic ethics are shaped by the teachings of the Quran and the Hadith, which provide guidance on personal conduct and social responsibility. Key ethical principles in Islam include the Five Pillars, which encompass acts of worship, charity, and ethical behavior towards others. Islam also emphasizes the importance of justice, mercy, and ethical treatment of fellow human beings.
  • Buddhism: Buddhist ethics are founded on the Four Noble Truths and the Eightfold Path, which outline the path to enlightenment and liberation from suffering. Ethical principles in Buddhism include non-harming, compassion, right action, and mindfulness. Buddhists strive to cultivate positive virtues and abandon harmful behaviors.
  • Hinduism: Hindu ethics are intertwined with the concepts of dharma (righteousness) and karma (the law of cause and effect). The ethical teachings of Hinduism promote selflessness, compassion, non-violence, and respect for all living beings. Ethical conduct is also guided by different stages of life (ashramas) and social duties (varnas).
Major World ReligionEthical FrameworkKey Ethical PrinciplesMoral BasisMoral Exemplars
ChristianityDivine Command TheoryLove, compassion, forgiveness, and moral absolutesGod’s commands and teachingsJesus Christ, Mother Teresa
IslamDivine Command TheoryJustice, mercy, honesty, and submission to AllahQuran and HadithProphet Muhammad, Malala Yousafzai
BuddhismEthical Relativism (Karma)Compassion, non-violence, and mindful livingLaw of cause and effect (Karma)Dalai Lama, Thich Nhat Hanh
HinduismNatural Law TheoryDharma, ahimsa (non-violence), and self-realizationDivine order and cosmic harmonyMahatma Gandhi, Swami Vivekananda
JudaismDivine Command TheoryJustice, righteousness, and covenant with GodTorah and TalmudMoses, Abraham
SikhismVirtue EthicsEquality, honesty, and selfless service (Seva)Moral virtues and spiritual growthGuru Nanak, Bhai Kanhaiya
ConfucianismVirtue EthicsFilial piety, righteousness, and social harmonyJen (benevolence) and Li (rituals)Confucius, Mencius
DaoismEthical Relativism (Wu Wei)Simplicity, harmony, and living in accordance with TaoFollowing the natural flow (Tao)Laozi, Zhuangzi
JainismEthical Relativism (Ahimsa)Non-violence, non-possession, and non-attachmentPrinciple of non-harm (Ahimsa)Mahavira, Acharya Kundakunda
ShintoismEthical Relativism (Kami)Respect for nature and kami (spirits)Kami and ancestral traditionsEmperor Jimmu, Izanami and Izanagi

C. Critiques and Debates on Religious Ethics:

  • Ethical Relativism: Critics argue that religious ethics can lead to moral relativism, where ethical principles are contingent on subjective beliefs rather than objective truths. This relativism can result in conflicting moral codes among different religious groups.
  • Moral Inflexibility: Some critiques argue that strict adherence to religious doctrines can lead to moral inflexibility, preventing adaptation to changing societal norms and ethical challenges.
  • Interpretation and Selective Application: Debates arise over the interpretation of religious texts and the selective application of ethical teachings, which can lead to differing moral judgments even within the same religious tradition.
  • Ethical Dilemmas: In certain cases, religious ethics may clash with secular ethical principles, leading to ethical dilemmas where individuals must reconcile conflicting moral imperatives.

Despite these critiques and debates, religious ethics continue to be influential in shaping the ethical landscape of societies worldwide. Understanding the historical development and impact of religious ethics provides valuable insights into the complexities of moral frameworks across cultures and belief systems.

III. Theological Approaches to the Role of Religion in Ethics

Theological ApproachKey Tenets and ConceptsStrengthsCriticisms
Divine Command Theory– Ethical principles are derived from the commands of a higher power (God).– Provides a clear foundation for moral obligations based on divine authority.– Raises questions about the arbitrariness of morality and different interpretations of divine commands.
Natural Law Theory– Ethical principles are inherent in the natural order of the universe and can be discovered through reason.– Offers a universal and objective basis for ethics that transcends religious beliefs.– Potential challenges in identifying and applying natural law principles in complex ethical situations.
Virtue Ethics– Focuses on developing virtuous character as the foundation for ethical decision-making.– Emphasizes the cultivation of moral virtues, guiding behavior beyond rigid rules.– Critics argue that virtue ethics may lack specific guidance in resolving moral dilemmas.
Ethical Relativism and Pluralism– Ethical principles vary across religious traditions and cultural contexts.– Acknowledges and respects diverse ethical perspectives within and between religions.– Raises questions about finding common ground and resolving ethical conflicts in a pluralistic world.

A. Divine Command Theory:

Divine command theory is a theological approach to ethics that posits that ethical principles and moral obligations are derived from the commands of a higher power, usually seen as a deity or God. According to this theory, what is morally right or wrong is determined solely by the divine will. Actions are deemed morally good if they align with God’s commands, and they are morally wrong if they go against God’s will. This view often emphasizes the importance of obedience to religious teachings and the belief that moral duties are grounded in the authority of the divine. However, critics argue that this approach raises questions about the arbitrariness of morality and the potential for ethical dilemmas when different interpretations of divine commands arise.

B. Natural Law Theory:

Natural law theory is another theological approach that asserts that ethical principles are inherent in the natural order of the universe. It proposes that human beings can discern moral truths through reason and observation of the natural world. According to this view, there is a set of universal moral principles that guide human behavior and are applicable to all individuals, regardless of religious beliefs. Natural law theorists argue that ethical principles are objective and independent of specific religious doctrines. While religious beliefs may inform one’s understanding of natural law, the theory posits that ethical truths can be discovered through rational reflection on the nature of humanity and the world. Critics, however, question the extent to which natural law can provide concrete ethical guidance and the potential for different interpretations of what constitutes natural law.

C. Virtue Ethics and Religious Character:

Virtue ethics is a philosophical and theological approach that emphasizes the development of virtuous character as the foundation for ethical decision-making. In a religious context, this approach involves striving to embody the virtues espoused by the faith. Religious traditions often promote the cultivation of virtues such as compassion, humility, patience, and integrity as essential elements of ethical living. The focus on character development is seen as vital for guiding moral behavior rather than merely adhering to rules or commands. Virtue ethics also emphasizes the importance of moral exemplars, often revered figures in religious traditions, whose lives serve as models of ethical conduct. This approach encourages individuals to emulate these exemplars and aspire to their level of moral excellence.

D. Ethical Relativism and Pluralism in Religious Contexts:

Ethical relativism is a perspective that suggests ethical principles and moral judgments are contingent on cultural, societal, or individual beliefs and vary across different contexts. In religious contexts, ethical relativism recognizes that diverse religious traditions may hold distinct ethical frameworks, leading to ethical pluralism. This pluralistic view acknowledges the coexistence of multiple moral perspectives within and among religious traditions. It recognizes that different religious groups may have contrasting moral codes, and there might not be a single absolute ethical truth. Ethical relativism allows for a more inclusive understanding of moral diversity, but it also raises questions about the possibility of finding common ground and resolving ethical conflicts when moral perspectives diverge.

These theological approaches to the role of religion in ethics provide diverse lenses through which religious traditions shape and inform ethical beliefs and practices. Each approach offers unique insights into the relationship between religious beliefs and moral values, contributing to the ongoing dialogue about the interplay of religion and ethics in various cultural and philosophical contexts.

IV. Secular Philosophical Perspectives on the Role of Religion in Ethics

PerspectiveDescriptionKey FeaturesCriticisms
Absence of belief in deities or higher powersEthical principles based on reason and empathyCriticized for potential lack of moral foundation
Emphasizes human value and agencyHuman reason, critical thinking, and evidence-based ethicsCritiqued for perceived relativism and subjectivity
Focuses on maximizing overall happinessConsequentialist approach, seeks to maximize utilityCriticized for potential neglect of individual rights
Emphasizes moral principles and dutiesNon-consequentialist, emphasizes universal moral lawsCritiqued for potential inflexibility in moral decision-making
Derives ethical principles from social contractsEmphasizes cooperation and mutual benefitCriticized for lack of universal moral foundation

A. Atheism and Ethical Systems:

Atheism is the absence of belief in any deities or higher powers. Despite lacking religious foundations, atheism can still offer ethical systems based on secular principles. Ethical atheism often centers on human reason, empathy, and compassion as the basis for moral decision-making. Without the guidance of religious teachings, atheists may adopt various ethical theories and philosophies to inform their moral principles. Some atheists embrace utilitarianism, virtue ethics, or other secular ethical frameworks as a means to navigate moral dilemmas and promote ethical behavior. Atheistic ethics emphasizes the importance of human well-being, social responsibility, and moral autonomy, independent of religious beliefs.

B. Secular Humanism and Ethical Principles:

Secular humanism is a philosophical worldview that emphasizes the value and dignity of human beings and their ability to determine their own destinies through reason, science, and critical thinking. Secular humanists derive their ethical principles from human reason and empirical evidence rather than religious revelations. Ethical considerations in secular humanism focus on promoting human flourishing, individual autonomy, and the well-being of all people. Secular humanists often advocate for principles such as human rights, social justice, equality, and compassion, grounded in a commitment to the welfare of humanity and the broader ecosystem .

C. Ethical Theories without Religious Foundations (e.g., Utilitarianism, Deontology):

Several ethical theories do not rely on religious foundations and provide secular approaches to moral decision-making:

  • Utilitarianism : Utilitarianism is a consequentialist ethical theory that emphasizes maximizing overall happiness or well-being for the greatest number of individuals. Actions are considered morally right if they produce the greatest amount of happiness or utility and wrong if they lead to more suffering. Utilitarianism is often associated with secular ethical reasoning and empirical measurements to assess the outcomes of actions.
  • Deontology : Deontology, formulated by philosophers like Immanuel Kant, is a non-consequentialist ethical theory that emphasizes the importance of moral principles and duties. According to deontology, certain actions are intrinsically right or wrong, regardless of their consequences. Ethical decisions are guided by universal moral principles and categorical imperatives, which serve as a foundation for ethical obligations. Deontology provides a secular framework for understanding ethical duties without relying on religious beliefs.
  • Contractualism : Contractualist theories propose that moral principles are derived from hypothetical social contracts or agreements. These theories do not necessitate religious beliefs but instead focus on the rational self-interest of individuals forming a social contract for mutual benefit and cooperation. Ethical obligations arise from the terms of the social contract, ensuring cooperation and harmonious living.

These secular ethical perspectives offer alternatives to religiously grounded moral frameworks and contribute to the ongoing discourse on the role of religion in ethics. While some individuals may derive their ethical principles from religious beliefs, others find moral guidance and ethical insights through secular philosophical perspectives that emphasize human reason, empathy, and the pursuit of human welfare and flourishing.

V. Contemporary Debates on Religion’s Influence on Ethical Decisions

A. religion and moral behavior:.

One of the significant debates centers around the relationship between religion and moral behavior. Some argue that religious beliefs and practices positively influence individuals to act morally and ethically. They contend that religious teachings often promote virtues, empathy, and compassion, which guide adherents to make ethical decisions and lead morally upright lives. However, others question this correlation, pointing to instances where religious individuals may engage in immoral behavior or use their beliefs to justify harmful actions. This debate raises questions about the extent to which religion genuinely impacts moral behavior and whether moral behavior is solely dependent on religious affiliations.

B. Religious Fundamentalism and Moral Absolutism:

Religious fundamentalism refers to a strict, literal interpretation of religious texts and dogmas, often leading to moral absolutism—the belief in objective, unchanging moral truths. Critics argue that religious fundamentalism can lead to rigid moral frameworks that do not account for changing social contexts and ethical complexities. Moral absolutism may also lead to intolerance towards differing perspectives and a lack of flexibility in adapting to diverse moral challenges. On the other hand, proponents of religious fundamentalism argue that adhering to absolute moral truths is necessary for upholding the integrity of religious teachings and preserving moral consistency.

C. The Intersection of Religious Freedom and Ethical Obligations:

The debate on religious freedom and ethical obligations arises when religious beliefs or practices come into conflict with broader societal norms or laws. While religious freedom is a fundamental human right, it can intersect with ethical obligations when certain religious practices are seen as discriminatory, harmful, or infringing on the rights of others. This debate poses complex questions about how to balance individual religious freedoms with the ethical responsibility to ensure equality, inclusivity, and protection of human rights for all members of society.

D. The Role of Religious Institutions in Shaping Ethical Values:

Religious institutions, such as churches, mosques, temples, and synagogues, have historically played a significant role in shaping the ethical values of their communities. These institutions often act as moral authorities, providing guidance on ethical conduct and influencing the moral outlook of their followers. However, contemporary debates surround the accountability of religious institutions and their leaders concerning ethical misconduct or abuses of power. Some argue that religious institutions must uphold high ethical standards to maintain credibility as moral influencers, while others emphasize the need for transparency, accountability, and checks and balances within religious organizations.

These contemporary debates highlight the complexity of religion’s role in shaping ethical decisions and the diverse perspectives on how religious beliefs intersect with ethical values in the modern world. The ongoing discussions contribute to a deeper understanding of the nuances involved in navigating the relationship between religion and ethics in diverse cultural, social, and legal contexts.

VI. Psychological and Sociological Studies on the Link Between Religion and Ethics

AspectPsychological StudiesSociological Studies
Focus of StudyInvestigates how religious beliefs, practices, and experiences influence an individual’s moral development and decision-making.Explores the broader impact of religious norms, values, and institutions on societal ethical conduct and attitudes.
MethodologyEmploys experimental studies, surveys, and psychological assessments to analyze the relationship between religion and moral behavior.Utilizes qualitative and quantitative research methods, such as ethnography, interviews, and statistical analyses to study the influence of religion on social ethics.
Key FindingsReligious upbringing correlates with higher levels of prosocial behavior, empathy, and adherence to moral rules in children.Religious communities play a significant role in establishing moral norms and influencing ethical behavior within society.
Moral Identity and Religious IdentityStudies explore how moral identity is often intertwined with religious identity, where religious beliefs can become integral to an individual’s sense of moral self.Research examines how religious institutions and leaders shape the moral identity of their members, contributing to a shared sense of ethical identity within religious communities.
Religious Practices and Ethical BehaviorInvestigates how engaging in religious rituals and practices can influence altruistic behavior and prosocial tendencies.Studies analyze the relationship between religious participation and charitable actions, activism for social justice, and involvement in community service.
Cross-Cultural PerspectivesStudies explore how religious beliefs and ethics may vary across different cultural and religious contexts.Research investigates the role of religious ethics in diverse societies, addressing challenges posed by cultural pluralism and religious diversity.
Psychological Mechanisms and Moral ReasoningExamines cognitive and emotional factors that mediate the relationship between religious beliefs and moral decision-making.Studies analyze how religious values and teachings influence moral reasoning and ethical judgments at individual and societal levels.
Implications for Moral EducationFindings inform the development of moral education programs that consider the influence of religious beliefs on moral development.Research provides insights into the role of religious institutions in promoting moral education and ethical values within communities.
Limitations and Future DirectionsChallenges include potential biases in self-report data and limited generalizability across diverse religious traditions.Future research may explore the intersection of religious ethics with emerging ethical issues, such as AI ethics and global challenges.

A. Psychological Aspects of Religious Influences on Moral Development:

Psychological research explores how religious beliefs, practices, and experiences can influence an individual’s moral development. Studies suggest that religious upbringing and exposure to religious teachings during childhood can shape moral reasoning and values. For example, children raised in religious environments may exhibit greater empathy, prosocial behavior, and adherence to moral rules compared to their non-religious counterparts. Additionally, religious communities may provide moral guidance, moral exemplars, and reinforcement of ethical behavior through religious rituals and practices. Psychological studies delve into the cognitive and emotional aspects of how religion influences moral development and how moral identity may be intertwined with religious identity.

B. Societal Impact of Religious Norms and Values on Ethical Conduct:

Sociological research explores the broader impact of religious norms and values on ethical conduct within societies. Religious communities often establish moral norms and social expectations that influence the behavior of their members. These norms may extend beyond individual behavior to shape societal attitudes toward various ethical issues, such as abortion, LGBTQ+ rights, and social justice. Sociologists investigate how religious institutions and religious leaders influence public opinion and policy decisions on ethical matters. They also examine how religious pluralism can lead to debates and conflicts over ethical values within diverse societies.

C. Comparative Studies on Ethical Behavior Between Religious and Non-Religious Individuals:

Comparative studies compare the ethical behavior and moral decision-making of religious individuals and those who identify as non-religious or atheist. Research in this area aims to explore whether religious beliefs and practices have a significant impact on ethical conduct compared to secular or non-religious perspectives. These studies often examine various ethical dimensions, such as honesty, empathy, altruism, and cooperation, to determine if there are notable differences in ethical behavior between religious and non-religious individuals. Comparative studies contribute to the ongoing discussion about whether religious adherence is a crucial factor in promoting ethical behavior or if secular ethics can produce similar moral outcomes.

These psychological and sociological studies provide valuable insights into the complex relationship between religion and ethics at individual and societal levels. By examining the psychological mechanisms of moral development, the societal impact of religious values, and the differences in ethical behavior between religious and non-religious individuals, researchers contribute to a deeper understanding of the multifaceted role that religion plays in shaping ethical conduct and moral reasoning. Such studies help inform discussions on the integration of religious and secular perspectives in ethical debates and the promotion of ethical behavior in diverse cultural and religious contexts.

VII. Critiques and Challenges to Religion’s Role in Ethics

A. secular criticisms of religious ethics:.

Secular critics raise several concerns regarding the role of religion in ethics. One major critique is the potential for religiously driven ethics to be exclusionary and discriminatory. Some argue that religious ethical frameworks may promote a sense of moral superiority among believers and lead to the marginalization of individuals with differing beliefs or non-believers. Moreover, secular critics argue that religious ethics can be resistant to change, hindering progress in addressing contemporary ethical challenges. They emphasize the need for a more inclusive and universal ethical approach that accommodates diverse perspectives and is adaptable to evolving societal norms.

B. Ethical Dilemmas Arising from Religious Teachings:

Certain religious teachings and dogmas can give rise to ethical dilemmas when they conflict with modern ethical principles or human rights. For instance, debates may arise over issues like reproductive rights, LGBTQ+ rights, euthanasia, or gender equality, where religious beliefs may clash with secular ethical frameworks. Ethical dilemmas can emerge when individuals must navigate between adhering to their religious teachings and upholding broader societal ethical norms. These dilemmas can be emotionally and morally challenging, prompting individuals to question the ethical validity of certain religious doctrines.

C. Potential Biases and Limitations in Religiously Driven Ethics:

Critics also highlight potential biases and limitations in religiously driven ethics. Some argue that religious ethical frameworks may be based on texts or interpretations that are historically and culturally contingent, leading to anachronistic moral judgments. Moreover, religious ethics may rely heavily on religious authorities or doctrines, which can stifle individual moral autonomy and critical thinking. Additionally, the diversity of religious perspectives can result in conflicting ethical views within and among religious communities, leading to disputes over the interpretation and application of religious teachings.

Overall, these critiques and challenges demonstrate the complexities of religion’s role in ethics and the need for ongoing dialogue and critical reflection. While religion has undoubtedly played a pivotal role in shaping ethical values and guiding moral behavior throughout history, it is essential to address these critiques and challenges to foster a more inclusive and nuanced understanding of the interplay between religion and ethics in contemporary societies. By acknowledging potential biases, ethical dilemmas, and limitations in religiously driven ethics, individuals and societies can work toward a more informed and constructive approach to addressing moral questions and promoting ethical conduct.

VIII. Case Studies and Examples

A. the role of religion in social justice and human rights:.

Case Study: Civil Rights Movement in the United States During the Civil Rights Movement in the 1950s and 1960s, religion played a crucial role in advocating for social justice and human rights. Religious leaders, such as Martin Luther King Jr., drew upon the teachings of Christianity to promote nonviolent resistance, racial equality, and the end of segregation and discrimination. The concept of human dignity and the belief in the intrinsic value of all individuals, derived from religious teachings, served as a moral foundation for the fight against racial injustice. The involvement of religious communities and their ethical principles significantly contributed to the success of the civil rights movement and influenced the broader human rights discourse worldwide.

B. Ethical Implications of Religious Rituals and Practices:

Case Study: Animal Sacrifice in Religious Traditions Animal sacrifice is a practice found in several religious traditions worldwide. For example, in ancient cultures like those in ancient Mesopotamia and ancient Greece, animals were sacrificed as part of religious rituals to appease deities or seek blessings. In contemporary times, this practice remains in some religious contexts. The ethical implications of animal sacrifice have sparked debates regarding animal rights, cruelty, and the clash between religious freedom and ethical concerns. Critics argue that animal sacrifice raises ethical dilemmas related to the treatment of sentient beings and the necessity of such practices in modern societies that prioritize animal welfare.

C. Religious Ethics in the Context of Environmental Issues:

Case Study: Indigenous Spiritual Practices and Environmental Conservation In many indigenous cultures, religious and spiritual practices are closely tied to the natural world. Indigenous communities often possess a deep sense of environmental ethics, believing that the Earth and its ecosystems are sacred and must be protected and preserved. For example, the beliefs of the Maasai people in East Africa or the Native American tribes in North America emphasize the interconnectedness between humans, nature, and the spiritual realm. Such religious ethics have informed indigenous efforts to conserve biodiversity, preserve traditional lands, and sustainably manage natural resources. The inclusion of these perspectives in environmental conservation efforts showcases how religious beliefs can positively impact the ecological well-being of the planet.

These case studies and examples demonstrate the diverse ways in which religion intersects with ethics in real-world contexts. They illustrate how religious beliefs and practices can both contribute to social justice and human rights advocacy and raise complex ethical questions related to rituals, practices, and environmental issues. By examining these case studies, researchers and policymakers can gain a deeper understanding of the multifaceted role of religion in shaping ethical values and influencing ethical decision-making in various cultural and environmental settings.

IX. Contemporary Perspectives and Future Outlook

A. emerging trends in the role of religion in ethics:.

  • Interfaith Dialogue: Increasing globalization and interconnectedness have facilitated interfaith dialogue, allowing diverse religious communities to engage in conversations about shared ethical values and common goals. Interfaith initiatives seek to promote understanding, respect, and cooperation among different religious traditions, fostering a more inclusive approach to addressing ethical challenges on a global scale.
  • Environmental Ethics and Religion: With growing concerns about climate change and environmental degradation, there is a rising recognition of the importance of religious ethics in promoting environmental stewardship. Many religious traditions are reexamining their teachings to emphasize the sacredness of nature and the ethical responsibility to protect the environment.
  • Social Justice Movements: Religious communities continue to play an active role in social justice movements, advocating for equality, human rights, and social reforms. The integration of religious ethics with broader social justice issues is likely to shape the discourse on ethical conduct and public policies.

B. Relevance of Religious Ethics in a Globalized and Diverse World:

  • Moral Pluralism: In an increasingly diverse world, religious ethics offer unique perspectives and cultural insights that contribute to the rich tapestry of moral pluralism. Embracing and understanding different religious ethical systems can foster a more tolerant and inclusive society that respects diverse ethical perspectives.
  • Ethical Reflection and Meaning-Making: Religion often provides individuals with a framework for reflecting on life’s meaning, purpose, and ethical dilemmas. In a globalized and fast-paced world, religious ethics can offer a sense of stability and guidance in navigating complex moral choices.
  • Addressing Global Challenges: In the face of global challenges, such as poverty , conflict, and environmental crises, religious ethics can offer principles and motivations to address these issues collectively. The shared values found in various religious traditions can serve as a unifying force in tackling global challenges and promoting ethical behavior.

C. Possibilities for Integrating Religious and Secular Ethical Principles:

  • Dialogical Approaches: Encouraging dialogue between religious and secular ethical perspectives can foster mutual understanding and pave the way for finding common ground on ethical issues. Engaging in respectful conversations about shared values can lead to collaborative efforts in promoting ethical conduct.
  • Ethical Pragmatism: Integrating religious and secular ethical principles pragmatically may involve finding practical solutions that respect diverse perspectives while upholding universal ethical principles, such as human dignity, justice, and compassion.
  • Bridging Divides: Emphasizing the similarities and complementarities between religious and secular ethical frameworks can bridge divides and create a more cohesive ethical discourse that transcends cultural and religious boundaries.

As the world continues to evolve, the role of religion in ethics will likely remain a dynamic and evolving field of study. By recognizing emerging trends, embracing diversity, and fostering constructive dialogue between religious and secular perspectives, societies can harness the potential of religious ethics to address ethical challenges and build a more harmonious and ethically aware global community.

A. Summary of Key Findings: Throughout this exploration of the role of religion in ethics, several key findings have emerged:

  • Religion has historically played a significant role in shaping ethical values, moral behavior, and societal norms across diverse cultures and belief systems.
  • The relationship between religion and ethics is complex and multifaceted, involving theological, philosophical, psychological, and sociological dimensions.
  • Various theological approaches, such as divine command theory, natural law theory, and virtue ethics, provide frameworks for understanding the connection between religion and ethics.
  • Secular perspectives, including atheism, secular humanism, and non-religious ethical theories, contribute alternative ethical foundations that do not rely on religious beliefs.
  • Contemporary debates highlight the influence of religion on moral behavior, the challenges of religious fundamentalism, and the balance between religious freedom and ethical obligations.
  • Psychological and sociological studies reveal how religion impacts moral development, ethical conduct, and societal values.
  • Case studies illustrate how religion intersects with social justice, rituals, and environmental ethics in practical contexts.

B. Reiteration of the Significance of Religion in Ethics:

Religion continues to hold significant relevance in shaping ethical values and influencing moral decision-making for individuals and societies worldwide. The ethical teachings, rituals, and spiritual practices found in religious traditions provide valuable guidance and meaning for individuals as they navigate moral dilemmas and seek to live ethically meaningful lives. Moreover, religion’s impact on social justice, environmental ethics, and broader societal values demonstrates its profound role in addressing pressing ethical challenges.

C. Future Directions for Research and Dialogue:

As our understanding of religion’s role in ethics continues to evolve, several directions for future research and dialogue can be explored:

  • Inclusivity and Pluralism: Emphasizing interfaith dialogue and embracing moral pluralism can promote greater understanding and cooperation among diverse religious and ethical perspectives.
  • Ethics in a Globalized World: As societies become more interconnected, research should focus on the relevance and challenges of religious ethics in a globalized and multicultural world.
  • Environmental Ethics: Studying the ecological implications of religious beliefs and practices can contribute to the conservation of the environment and sustainable development efforts.
  • Ethical Education: Exploring how religious ethics can be integrated into ethical education curricula can foster moral development and critical thinking in students.
  • Ethical Leadership: Investigating the impact of religious ethics on ethical leadership and the responsibilities of religious institutions in promoting ethical conduct can enhance societal well-being.

In conclusion, the role of religion in ethics is a multifaceted and dynamic field of study that encompasses a wide range of perspectives, debates, and implications. Understanding the interplay between religion and ethics is essential for appreciating the diverse ethical frameworks that guide individuals and societies. By acknowledging the significance of religious ethics, embracing pluralism, and promoting constructive dialogue, we can foster a more inclusive and morally engaged global community.

Share this:

Related posts, basics of ethics: gs paper 4, what is ethics definition, sources, theories, and applications – (gs-4), ethical scrutiny of human conduct | ethics in human action (gs 4 ethics), ethics and law: definition, relationship, differences and conflict (gs4), leave a comment cancel reply.

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed .

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Religion and Morality

From the beginning of the Abrahamic faiths and of Greek philosophy, religion and morality have been closely intertwined. This is true whether we go back within Greek philosophy or within Christianity and Judaism and Islam. The present entry will not try to step beyond these confines, since there are other entries on Eastern thought (see, for example, the entries on Ethics in Indian and Tibetan Buddhism and Chinese Ethics ). The entry proceeds chronologically, giving greatest length to the contemporary period. It cannot, within the present compass, aspire to be comprehensive. But it will be able to describe the main options as they have occurred historically. The purpose of proceeding historically is to substantiate the claim that morality and religion have been inseparable until very recently, and that our moral vocabulary is still deeply infused with this history. Since there are historically so many different ways to see the relation, a purely schematic or typological account is not likely to succeed as well. The entry will not try to enter deeply into the ethical theories of the individual philosophers mentioned, since this encyclopedia already contains individual entries about them; it will focus on what they say about the relation between morality and religion.

The term ‘morality’ as used in this entry will not be distinguished from ‘ethics.’ Philosophers have drawn various contrasts between the two at various times (Kant for example, and Hegel, and more recently R.M. Hare and Bernard Williams). But etymologically, the term ‘moral’ comes from the Latin mos , which means custom or habit, and it is a translation of the Greek ethos , which means roughly the same thing, and is the origin of the term ‘ethics’. In contemporary non-technical use, the two terms are more or less interchangeable, though ‘ethics’ has slightly more flavor of theory, and has been associated with the prescribed practice of various professions (e.g., medical ethics, etc.). In any case, this entry will assume that morality is a set of customs and habits that shape how we think about how we should live or about what is a good human life. The term ‘religion’ is much disputed. Again, we can learn from the etymology. The origin of the word is probably the Latin religare , to bind back. Not all uses of the term require reference to a divinity or divinities. But this entry will use the term so that there is such a reference, and a religion is a system of belief and practice that accepting a ‘binding’ relation to such a being or beings. This does not, however, give us a single essence of religion, since the conceptions of divinity are so various, and human relations with divinity are conceived so variously that no such essence is apparent even within Western thought. The ancient Greeks, for example, had many intermediate categories between full gods or goddesses and human beings. There were spirits (in Greek daimones ) and spiritual beings like Socrates's mysterious voice ( daimonion ) ( Apology , 31d1–4, 40a2–c3). There were heroes who were offspring of one divine and one human parent. There were humans who were deified, like the kings of Sparta. This is just within the culture of ancient Greece. If we included Eastern religions in the scope of the discussion, the hope for finding a single essence of religion would recede further. Probably it is best to understand ‘religion’ as a term for a group of belief/practice amalgams with a family resemblance to each other, but no set of necessary and sufficient conditions tying them together (see Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations , 65–7).

1. Ancient Greek Philosophy

  • 2. The Hebrew Bible and the New Testament

3. The Middle Ages

4. modern philosophy, 5. contemporary philosophy, other internet resources, related entries.

We can start with the Greeks, and this means starting with Homer, a body of texts transmitted first orally and then written down in the seventh century BCE. So what does the relation between morality and religion look like in Homer? The first thing to say is that the gods and goddesses of the Homeric poems behave remarkably like the noble humans described in the same poems, even though the humans are mortal and the gods and goddesses immortal. Both groups are motivated by the desire for honor and glory, and are accordingly jealous when they receive less than they think they should while others receive more, and work ceaselessly to rectify this. The two groups are not however symmetrical, because the noble humans have the same kind of client relation to the divinities as subordinate humans do to them. There is a complex pattern that we might call ‘an honor-loop’ (see Mikalson, Honor Thy Gods ). The divinities have their functions (in Greek, the word is the same as ‘honors’), such as Poseidon's oversight of the sea, and humans seek their favor with ‘honor’, which we might here translate as ‘worship’. This includes, for example, sanctuaries devoted to them, dedications, hymns, dances, libations, rituals, prayers, festivals and sacrifices. In all of these the gods take pleasure, and in return they give ‘honor’ to mortals in the form of help or assistance, especially in the areas of their own expertise. There is a clear analogy with purely human client-relations, which are validated in the Homeric narrative, since the poems were probably originally sung at the courts of the princes who claimed descent from the heroes whose exploits make up the story. The gods and goddesses are not, however, completely at liberty. They too are accountable to fate or justice, as in the scene in the Iliad , where Zeus wants to save Hector, but he cannot because ‘his doom has long been sealed’ ( Iliad , 22: 179).

It is sometimes said that the Presocratic philosophers come out of Homer by rejecting religion in favor of science. There is a grain of truth in this, for when Thales (who flourished around 580) is reported as saying ‘Water is the origin (or principle) of all things,’ this is different from saying, for example, that Tethys is mother of all the rivers, because it deletes the character of narrative or story (Aristotle's Metaphysics , 983b20–8). When Anaximenes (around 545) talks of air as the primary element differing in respect of thinness and thickness, or Heraclitus explains all change as a pattern in the turnings of fire igniting in measures and going out in measures, they are not giving stories with plot-lines involving quasi-human intentions and frustrations (DK 13, A 5, DK 22, B 30). But it is wrong to say that they have left religion behind. Heraclitus puts this enigmatically by saying that the one and only wisdom does and does not consent to be called Zeus (DK 22, B 14). He is affirming the divinity of this wisdom, but denying the anthropomorphic character of much Greek religion. ‘To god all things are beautiful and good and just but humans suppose some things to be just and others unjust’ (DK 22, B 102). He ties this divine wisdom to the laws of a city, ‘for all human laws are nourished by the one divine law’ (DK 22, B 114), though he does not have confidence that ‘the many’ are capable of making law. The sophists, to whom Socrates responded, rejected this tie between human law and divine law and this was in part because of their expertise in rhetoric, by which they taught their students how to manipulate the deliberations of popular assemblies, and so change the laws to their own advantage. The most famous case is Protagoras (c. 490–21), who stated in the first sentence of his book Truth that ‘A human being is the measure of all things, of what is that it is, and of what is not that it is not’ (Plato's Theaetetus , 152a). Protagoras is not correctly seen here as skeptical about morality or religion. It is true that he claimed he was not in a position to know either the manner in which the gods are or are not (another translation is ‘that they are or are not’) or what they are like in appearance (DK 80, B 4). But as Plato (c. 430–347) presents him, he told the story that all humans have been given by the gods the gifts of shame and justice, so as to make possible the founding of cities; this is why each human is the measure. Even Thrasymachus, in the first book of Plato's Republic , thinks of justice as the same thing amongst gods and humans ( Republic , 388c). His view of what this justice is, namely the interest of the stronger, is disputed by Plato. But the claim that justice operates at both the divine and human levels is common ground.

Socrates (c. 470–399) in one of the early dialogues debates the nature of the holy with Euthyphro, who is a religious professional. Euthyphro is taking his own father to court for murder, and though ordinary Greek morality would condemn such an action as impiety, Euthyphro defends it on the basis that the gods behave in the same sort of way, according to the traditional stories. Socrates makes it clear that he does not believe these stories, because they attribute immorality to the gods. This does not mean, however, that he does not believe in the gods. He was observant in his religious practices, and he objects to the charge of not believing in the city's gods that was one of the bases of the prosecution at his own trial. He points to the spirit who gives him commands about what not to do ( Apology , 31d), and we learn later that he found it significant that this voice never told him to stop conducting his trial in the way that in fact led to his death ( Ibid ., 40a-c). Socrates interpreted this as an invitation from the gods to die, thus refuting the charge that, by conducting his trial in the way he did, he was guilty of theft – i.e., depriving the gods of his life that properly belonged to them ( Phaedo , 62b). His life in particular was a service to god, he thought, because his testing of the wisdom of others was carrying out Apollo's charge given by the oracle at Delphi, implicit in the startling pronouncement that he was the wisest man in Greece ( Apology , 21a-d).

Socrates's problem with the traditional stories about the gods gives rise to what is sometimes called ‘the Euthyphro dilemma’. If we try to define the holy as what is loved by all the gods (and goddesses), we will be faced with the question ‘Is the holy holy because it is loved by the gods, or do they love it because it is holy?’ ( Euthyphro , 10a). Socrates makes it clear that his view is the second (though he does not argue for this conclusion in addressing this question, and he is probably relying on the earlier premise, at Euthyphro , 7c10f, that we love things because of the properties they have). (See Hare, Plato's Euthyphro , on this passage.) But his view is not an objection to tying morality and religion together. He hints at the end of the dialogue ( Euthyphro , 13de) that the right way to link them is to see that when we do good we are serving the gods well. Plato probably does not intend for us to construe the dialogues together as a single philosophical system, and we must not erase the differences between them. But it is significant that in the Theaetetus (176b), Socrates says again that our goal is to be as like the god as possible, and since the god is in no way and in no manner unjust, but as just as it is possible to be, nothing is more like the god than the one among us who becomes correspondingly as just as possible. In several dialogues this thought is connected with a belief in the immortality of the soul; we become like the god by paying attention to the immortal and best part of ourselves (e.g., Symposium , 210A-212B). The doctrine of the immortality of the soul is also tied to the doctrine of the Forms, whereby things with characteristics that we experience in this life (e.g., beauty) are copies or imitations of the Forms (e.g., The Beautiful-Itself) that we see without the distraction of the body when our souls are separated at death. The Form of the Good, according to the Republic , is above all the other Forms and gives them their intelligibility (as, by analogy, the sun gives visibility), and is (in a pregnant phrase) ‘on the other side of being’ ( Republic , 509b). Finally, in the Laws (716b), perhaps Plato's last work, the character called ‘the Athenian’ says that the god can serve for us in the highest degree as a measure of all things, and much more than any human can, whatever some people say; so people who are going to be friends with such a god must, as far as their powers allow, be like the gods themselves.

This train of thought sees the god or gods as like a magnet, drawing us to be like them by the power of their goodness or excellence. In Plato's Ion (533d), the divine is compared to a magnet to which is attached a chain of rings, through which the attraction is passed. This conception is also pervasive in Aristotle (384–22), Plato's student for twenty years. In the Nicomachean Ethics , for example, the words ‘god’ and ‘divine’ occur roughly twice as often as the words ‘happiness’ and ‘happy’. This is significant, given that Aristotle's ethical theory is (like Plato's) ‘eudaimonist’ (meaning that our morality aims at our happiness). Mention of the divine is not merely conventional for Aristotle, but does important philosophical work. In the Eudemian Ethics (1249b5–22) he tells us that the goal of our lives is service and contemplation of the god. He thinks that we become like what we contemplate, and so we become most like the god by contemplating the god. Incidentally, this is why the god does not contemplate us; for this would mean becoming less than the god, which is impossible. As in Plato, the well-being of the city takes precedence over the individual, and this, too, is justified theologically. It is nobler and more divine to achieve an end for a city than for an individual ( NE 1094b9–10). Aristotle draws a distinction between what we honor and what we merely commend ( NE , 1101b10–35). There are six states for a human life, on a normative scale from best to worst: divine (which exceeds the merely human on the one extreme), virtuous (without wrongful desire), strong-willed (able to overcome wrongful desire), weak-willed (unable to do so), vicious and bestial (which exceeds the merely human on the other extreme, and which Aristotle says is mostly found among barbarians) ( NE , 1145a15–22). The highest form of happiness, which he calls blessedness, is something we honor as we honor gods, whereas virtue we merely commend. It would be as wrong to commend blessedness as it would be to commend gods ( NE , 1096a10–1097a15). Sometimes Aristotle uses the phrase ‘God or understanding’ (in Greek, nous ) (e.g., Politics , 1287a27–32). The activity of the god, he says in the Metaphysics , is nous thinking itself (1074b34). The best human activity is the most god-like, namely thinking about the god and about things that do not change. Aristotle's virtue ethics, then, needs to be understood against the background of these theological premises. He is thinking of the divine, to use Plato's metaphor, as magnetic, drawing us, by its attractive power, to live the best kind of life possible for us. This gives him a defense against the charge sometimes made against virtue theories that they simply embed the prevailing social consensus into an account of human nature. Aristotle defines ethical virtue as lying in a mean between excess and defect, and the mean is determined by the person of practical wisdom (actually the male, since Aristotle is sexist on this point). He then gives a conventional account of the virtues such a person displays (such as courage, literally manliness, which requires the right amount of fear and confidence, between cowardice and rashness). But the virtuous person in each case acts ‘for the sake of the noble (or beautiful)’, and Aristotle continually associates the noble with the divine (e.g., NE , 1115b12).

There are tensions in Aristotle's account of virtue and happiness. It is not clear whether the Nicomachean Ethics has a consistent view of the relation between the activity of contemplation and the other activities of a virtuous life (see Hare, God and Morality , chapter 1, and Sarah Broadie, Ethics with Aristotle , chapter 7). But the connection of the highest human state with the divine is pervasive in the text. One result of this connection is the eudaimonism mentioned earlier. If the god does not care about what is not divine (for this would be to become like what is not divine), the highest and most god-like human also does not care about other human beings except to the degree they contribute to his own best state. This degree is not negligible, since humans are social animals, and their well-being depends on the well-being of the families and cities of which they are members. Aristotle is not preaching self-sufficiency in any sense that implies we could be happy on our own, isolated from other human beings. But our concern for the well-being of other people is always, for him, contingent on our special relation to them. Within the highest kind of friendship ‘a friend is another self’, he says, and within such friendship we care about friends for their own sake, but if the friend becomes divine and we do not, then the friendship is over ( NE , 1159a7). We therefore do not want our friends to become gods, even though that would be the best thing for them. Finally, Aristotle ties our happiness to our end (in Greek, telos ); for humans, as for all living things, the best state is its own activity in accordance with the natural function that is unique to each species. For humans the best state is happiness, and the best activity within this state is contemplation ( NE , 1178b17–23).

The Epicureans and Stoics who followed Aristotle differed with each other and with him in many ways, but they agreed in tying morality and religion together. For the Epicureans, the gods do not care about us, though they are entertained by looking at our tragicomic lives (rather as we look at soap operas on television). We can be released from a good deal of anxiety, the Epicureans thought, by realizing that the gods are not going to punish us. Our goal should be to be as like the gods as we can, enjoying ourselves without interruption, but for us this means limiting our desires to what we can obtain without frustration. They did not mean that our happiness is self-interested in any narrow sense, because they held that we can include others in our happiness by means of our sympathetic pleasures. The Stoics likewise tied the best kind of human life, for them the life of the sage, to being like the divine. The sage follows nature in all his desires and actions, and is thus the closest to the divine. One of the virtues he will have is ‘apathy’ (in Greek apatheia ), which does not mean listlessness, but detachment from wanting anything other than what nature, or the god, is already providing. Like the Epicureans, the Stoics had an argument against any narrow self-interest, but this time based on their conception of right reason which is directed by the law common to all, ‘which pervades everything and is the same as Zeus, lord of the ordering of all that exists’ (Diogenes Laertius, Lives of the Philosophers , VII 88. For the views of the Epicureans and Stoics about morality and religion, see Julia Annas, The Morality of Happiness , chapters 5 and 7.)

2. The Hebrew Bible And The New Testament

The second line of thought to be traced in this entry starts with the Hebrew Bible and continues with the Greek scriptures called by Christians ‘The New Testament’. Morality and religion are connected in the Hebrew Bible primarily by the category of God's command. Such commands come already in the first chapter of Genesis . God created by command, for example ‘Let there be light’ ( Gen . 1:3). Then, after the creation of animals, God gives the command, ‘Be fruitful and multiply’, and repeats the command to the humans he creates in the divine image ( Gen . 1:22). In the second chapter God tells Adam that he is free to eat from any tree in the garden, but he must not eat from the tree of the knowledge of good and evil. When Eve and Adam disobey and eat of that fruit, they are expelled from the garden. There is a family of concepts here that is different from what we met in Greek philosophy. God is setting up a kind of covenant by which humans will be blessed if they obey the commands God gives them. Human disobedience is not explained in the text, except that the serpent says to Eve that they will not die if they eat the fruit, but will be like God, knowing good and evil, and Eve sees the fruit as good for food and pleasing to the eye and desirable for gaining wisdom. After they eat, Adam and Eve know that they are naked, and are ashamed, and hide from God. There is a turning away from God and from obedience to God that characterizes this as a ‘fall into sin’. As the story goes on, and Cain kills Abel, evil spreads to all the people of the earth, and Genesis describes the basic state as a corruption of the heart (6:9). This idea of a basic orientation away from or towards God and God's commands becomes in the Patristic period of early Christianity the idea of a will. There is no such idea in Plato or Aristotle, and no Greek word that the English word ‘will’ properly translates.

In the Pentateuch, the story continues with Abraham, and God's command to leave his ancestral land and go to the land God promised to give him and his offspring ( Gen . 17:7–8). Then there is the command to Abraham to kill his son, a deed prevented at the last minute by the provision of a ram instead ( Gen . 22:11–14). Abraham's great grandchildren end up in Egypt, because of famine, and the people of Israel suffer for generations under Pharaoh's yoke. Under Moses the people are finally liberated, and during their wanderings in the desert, Moses receives from God the Ten Commandments, in two tables or tablets ( Exod . 20:1–17, 31:18). The first table concerns our obligations to God directly, to worship God alone and keep God's name holy, and keep the Sabbath. The second table concerns our obligations to other human beings, and all of the commands are negative (do not kill, commit adultery, steal, lie, or covet) except for the first, which tells us to honor our fathers and mothers. God's commands taken together give us the law (on some lists there are 613 mitzvot , Hebrew for ‘commands’.) One more term belongs here, namely ‘kingdom’. The Greeks had the notion of a kingdom, under a human king (though the Athenians were in the classical period suspicious of such an arrangement). But they did not have the idea of a kingdom of God, though there is something approaching this in some of the Stoics. This idea is explicable in terms of law, and is introduced as such in Exodus in connection with the covenant on Mt. Sinai. The kingdom is the realm in which the laws obtain.

This raises a question about the extent of this realm. The Ten Commandments are given in the context of a covenant with the people of Israel, though there are references to God's intention to bless the whole world through this covenant. The surrounding laws in the Pentateuch include prescriptions and proscriptions about ritual purity and sacrifice and the use of the land that seem to apply to this particular people in this particular place. But the covenant that God makes with Noah after the flood is applicable to the whole human race, and universal scope is explicit in the Wisdom books, which make a continual connection between how we should live and how we were created as human beings. For example, in Proverbs 8 Wisdom raises her voice to all humankind, and says that she detests wickedness, which she goes on to describe in considerable detail. She says that she was the artisan at God's side when God created the world and its inhabitants. Judaism distinguishes seven ‘Noahide’ laws given to Noah before the covenant with Abraham.

In the writings which Christians call ‘The New Testament’ the theme of God's commands is recapitulated. Jesus sums up the commandments under two, the command to love God with all one's heart and soul and mind (see Deuteronomy 6:5), and the command to love the neighbor as the self (see Leviticus 19:18). The first of these probably sums up the first ‘table’ of the Ten Commandments to Moses, and the second sums up the second. The New Testament is unlike the Hebrew Bible, however, in presenting a narrative about a man who is the perfect exemplification of obedience and who has a life without sin. New Testament scholars disagree about the extent to which Jesus actually claimed to be God, but the traditional interpretation is that he did make this claim; in any case the Christian doctrine is that we can see in his life the clearest possible revelation in human terms both of what God is like and at the same time of what our lives ought to be like. In the ‘Sermon on the Mount’ ( Matthew 5–7) Jesus issues a number of radical injunctions. He takes the commandments inside the heart; for example, we are required not merely not to murder, but not to be angry, and not merely not to commit adultery, but not to lust (see Ezekiel 11:19, ‘I will give them a heart of flesh, that they may walk in my statutes.’) We are told, if someone strikes us on the right cheek, to turn to him also the left. Jesus tells us to love our enemies and those who hate and persecute us, and in this way he makes it clear that the love commandment is not based on reciprocity ( Matt 5:43–48; Luke 6:27–36). Finally, when he is asked ‘Who is my neighbor?’, he tells the story ( Luke 10) of a Samaritan (traditional enemies of the Jews) who met a wounded Jew he did not know by the side of the road, was moved with compassion, and went out of his way to meet his needs; Jesus commends the Samaritan for being ‘neighbor’ to the wounded traveler.

The theme of self-sacrifice is clearest in the part of the narrative that deals with Jesus' death. This event is understood in many different ways in the New Testament, but one central theme is that Jesus died on our behalf, an innocent man on behalf of the guilty. Jesus describes the paradigm of loving our neighbors as the willingness to die for them. This theme is connected with our relationship to God, which we violate by disobedience, but which is restored by God's forgiveness through redemption. In Paul's letters especially we are given a three-fold temporal location for the relation of morality to God's work on our behalf. We are forgiven for our past failures on the basis of Jesus' sacrifice ( Rom . 3:21–26). We are reconciled now with God through God's adoption of us in Christ ( Rom . 8:14–19). And we are given the hope of future progress in holiness by the work of the Holy Spirit ( Rom . 5:3–5). All of this theology requires more detailed analysis, but this is not the place for it.

There is a contrast between the two traditions I have so far described, namely the Greek and the Judeo-Christian. The idea of God that is central in Greek philosophy is the idea of God attracting us, like a kind of magnet, so that we desire to become more like God, though there is a minority account by Socrates of receiving divine commands. In the Jewish and Christian scriptures, the notion of God commanding us is central. It is tempting to simplify this contrast by saying that the Greeks favor the good , in their account of the relation of morality and religion, and the Judeo-Christian account favors the right or obligation. It is true that the notion of obligation makes most sense against the background of command. But the picture is over-simple because the Greeks had room in their account for the constraint of desire; thus the temperate or brave person in Aristotle's picture has desires for food or sex or safety that have to be disciplined by the love of the noble. On the other side, the Judeo-Christian account adds God's love to the notion of God's command, so that the covenant in which the commands are embedded is a covenant by which God blesses us, and we are given a route towards our highest good which is union with God.

The rest of the history to be described in this entry is a cross-fertilization of these two traditions or lines of thought. In the patristic period, or the period of the early Fathers, it was predominantly Plato and the Stoics amongst the Greek philosophers whose influence was felt. The Eastern and Western parts of the Christian church split during the period, and the Eastern church remained more comfortable than the Western with language about humans being deified (in Greek theosis ). In the Western church, Augustine (354–430) emphasized the gap between the world we are in as resident aliens and our citizenship in the heavenly Jerusalem, and even in our next life the distance between ourselves and God. He describes in the Confessions the route by which his heart or will, together with his understanding, moved from paganism through Neo-Platonism to Christianity. The Neo-Platonists (such as Plotinus, 205-270) taught a world-system of emanation, whereby the One (like Plato's Form of the Good) flowed into Intellect (the realm of the Forms) and from there into the World-Soul and individual souls, where it encountered the realm of bodies, from where it returned to itself (‘the flight of the alone to the alone’). Augustine accepted that the Platonists taught, like the beginning of the prologue of John , that the Word (in Greek, logos ) is with God and is God, since the Intellect is the mediating principle between the One and the Many ( John 1:1–5). Augustine held that Plato had asserted that the supreme good, possession of which alone gives us blessedness, is God, ‘and therefore (Plato) thought that to be a philosopher is to be a lover of God.’ ( De Civ. Dei VIII.8). But the Platonists did not teach, like the end of John's prologue, that the Word is made flesh in Jesus Christ, and so they did not have access to the way to salvation revealed in Christ or God's grace to us through Christ's death. Nonetheless, it is surprising how far Augustine can go in rapprochement. The Forms, he says, are in the mind of God and God uses them in the creation of the world. Human beings were created for union with God, but they have the freedom to turn towards themselves instead of God. If they turn to God, they can receive divine illumination through a personal intuition of the eternal standards (the Forms). If they turn towards themselves, they will lose the sense of the order of creation, which the order of their own loves should reflect. Augustine gives primacy to the virtue of loving what ought to be loved, especially God. In his homily on I John 4:8, he says, ‘Love and do what you will.’ But this is not a denial of the moral law. He held that humans who truly love God will also act in accord with the other precepts of divine and moral law; though love not merely fulfills the cardinal virtues (wisdom, justice, courage and temperance) but transforms them by supernatural grace.

The influence of Augustine in the subsequent history of ethics resulted from the fact that it was his synthesis of Christianity (the official religion of the Roman Empire after 325) and Greek philosophy that survived the destruction of the Western Roman Empire, especially in the monasteries where the texts were still read. Boethius (c. 480–524) gave us the definition of the concept of ‘person’ that has been fundamental to ethical theory. To understand this, we need to go back into the history of the development of the doctrine of the Trinity. The church had to explain how the Father, the Son and the Holy Spirit could be distinct and yet not three different gods. They used, in Latin, the term persona , which means ‘role’ but which was also used by the grammarians to distinguish what we call ‘first person, second person and third person’ pronouns and verb-forms. The same human being can be first person ‘I’, second person ‘you’, and third person ‘he’ or ‘she’, depending on the relations in which he or she stands. The doctrine of the Trinity comes to be understood in terms of three persons, one God, with the persons standing in different relations to each other. But then this term ‘person’ is also used to understand the relation of the second person's divinity to his humanity. The church came to talk about one person with two natures, the person standing under the natures. This had the merit of not making either the humanity or the divinity less essential to who Jesus was. Plato and Aristotle did not have any term that we can translate ‘person’ in the modern sense, as some one (as opposed to some thing ) that stands under all his or her attributes. Boethius, however, defines ‘person’ as ‘individual substance of rational nature,’ a key step in the introduction of our present concept.

In the West knowledge of most of Aristotle's texts was lost, but not in the East. They were translated into Syriac, and Arabic, and eventually (in Muslim Spain) into Latin, and re-entered Christian Europe in the twelfth century accompanied by translations of the great Arabic commentaries. In the initial prophetic period of Islam (CE 610–32) the Qur'an was given to Mohammad, who explained it and reinforced it through his own teachings and practices. The notion of God's (Allah's) commands is again central, and our obedience to these commands is the basis of our eventual resurrection. Disputes about political authority in the period after Mohammad's death led to the split between Sunnis and Shiites. Within Sunni Muslim ethical theory in the Middle Ages two major alternative ways developed of thinking about the relation between morality and religion. The first, the Mu'tazilite, was given its most developed statement by ‘Abd al-Jabbar from Basra (d. 1025). ‘Abd al-Jabbar defines a wrongful act as one that deserves blame, and holds that the right and wrong character of acts is known immediately to human reason, independently of revelation. These standards that we learn from reason apply also to God, so that we can use them to judge what God is and is not commanding us to do. He also teaches that humans have freedom, in the sense of a power to perform both an act and its opposite, though not at the same time. (For Mu'tazilite ethical theory, see Sophia Vasalou, Moral Agents and Their Deserts: The Character of Mu'tazilite Ethics and George Hourani, Islamic Rationalism: The Ethics of ‘Abd al-Jabbar .) The second alternative was taught by al-Ashari (d. 935), who started off as a Mu'tazilite, but came to reject their view. He insists that God is subject to none and to no standard that can fix bounds for Him. Nothing can be wrong for God, who sets the standard of right and wrong. This means that ‘if God declared lying to be right, it would be right, and if He commanded it, none could gainsay Him’ ( The Theology of al-Ash'ari , 169-70). With respect to our freedom, he holds that God gives us only the power to do the act (not its opposite) and this power is simultaneous to the act and does not precede it. A figure contemporary with al-Ashari, but in some ways intermediate between Mu'tazilites and Asharites, is al-Maturidi of Samarqand (d. 944). He holds that because humans have the tendency in their nature towards ugly or harmful actions as well as beautiful or beneficial ones, God has to reveal to us by command what to pursue and what to avoid. He also teaches that God gives us two different kinds of power, both the power simultaneous with the act (which is simply to do the act) and the power preceding the act (to choose either the act or its opposite). (For the work of al-Maturidi, see Ulrich Rudolph, Al-Maturidi and Sunni Theology in Samarkand .)

Medieval reflection within Judaism about morality and religion has, as its most significant figure, Maimonides (d. 1204) who was born in Muslim Spain, and was familiar with much of the Muslim discussion of these questions. The Guide of the Perplexed was written for young men who had read Aristotle and were worried about the tension between the views of the philosopher and their faith. Maimonides teaches that we do indeed have some access just as human beings to the rightness and wrongness of acts; but what renders conforming to these standards obligatory is that God reveals them in special revelation. The laws are obligatory whether we understand the reasons for them or not, but sometimes we do see how it is beneficial to obey, and Maimonides is remarkably fertile in providing such reasons.

The reentry of Aristotle into Europe caused a rebirth (a ‘renaissance’), but it also gave rise to a crisis, because it threatened to undermine the harmony established from the time of Augustine between the authority of reason, as represented by Greek philosophy, and the authority of faith, as represented by the doctrines of the Christian church. There were especially three ‘errors of Aristotle’ that seemed threatening: his teaching that the world was eternal, his apparent denial of personal immortality, and his denial of God's active agency in the world. (See, for example, Bonaventure, In Hexaemeron , VI.5 and In II Sent ., lib. II, d.1, pars 1, a.1, q.2.) These three issues (‘the world, the soul, and God’) become in one form or another the focus of philosophical thought for the next six centuries.

Thomas Aquinas (c. 1224–74) undertook the project of synthesis between Aristotle and Christianity, though his version of Christianity was already deeply influenced by Augustine, and so by Neo-Platonism. Aquinas, like Aristotle, emphasized the ends (vegetative, animal and typically human) given to humans in the natural order. He described both the cardinal virtues and the theological virtues of faith, hope and love, but he did not feel the tension that current virtue ethicists sometimes feel between virtue and the following of rules or principles. The rules governing how we ought to live are known, some of them by revelation, some of them by ordinary natural experience and rational reflection. But Aquinas thought these rules consistent in the determination of our good, since God only requires us to do what is consistent with our own good. Aquinas's theory is eudaimonist; ‘And so the will naturally tends towards its own last end, for every man naturally wills beatitude. And from this natural willing are caused all other willings, since whatever a man wills, he wills on account of the end.’ ( Summa Theologiae I, q.60. a.2) God's will is not exercised by arbitrary fiat; but what is good for some human being can be understood as fitting for this kind of agent, in relation to the purpose this agent intends to accomplish, in the real environment of the action, including other persons individually and collectively. The principles of natural moral law are the universal judgments made by right reasoning about the kinds of actions that are morally appropriate and inappropriate for human agents. They are thus, at least in principle and at a highly general level, deducible from human nature. Aquinas held that reason, in knowing these principles, is participating in the eternal law, which is in the mind of God ( Summa Theologiae I, q.91. a.2). Aquinas was not initially successful in persuading the church to embrace Aristotle. In 1277 the Bishop of Paris condemned 219 propositions (not all Thomist), including the thesis that a person virtuous in Aristotle's terms ‘is sufficiently disposed for eternal happiness.’ But in the Counter-Reformation, the synthesis which Aquinas achieved became authoritative in Roman Catholic education.

Aquinas was a Dominican friar. The other major order of friars, the Franciscan, had its own school of philosophy, starting with Bonaventure (c. 1217–74), who held that while we can learn from both Plato and Aristotle, and both are also in error, the greater error is Aristotle's. One other major figure from this tradition is John Duns Scotus (literally John from Duns, the Scot, c. 1266–1308), and there are three significant differences between him and Aquinas on the relation between morality and religion. First, Scotus is not a eudaimonist. He takes a double account of motivation from Anselm (1033–1109), who made the distinction between two affections of the will, the affection for advantage (an inclination towards one's own happiness and perfection) and the affection for justice (an inclination towards what is good in itself independent of advantage) (Anselm, De Concordia 3.11, 281:7–10; De Casu Diaboli 12, 255:8–11). Original sin is a ranking of advantage over justice, which needs to be reversed by God's assistance before we can be pleasing to God. Scotus says that we should be willing to sacrifice our own happiness for God if God were to require this. Second, he does not think that the moral law is self-evident or necessary. He takes the first table to be necessary, since it derives (except for the ‘every seventh day’ provision of the command about the Sabbath) from the necessary principle that God is to be loved. But the second table is contingent, though fitting our nature, and God could prescribe different commands even for human beings ( Ord . I, dist. 44). One of his examples is the proscription on theft, which applies only to beings with property, and so not necessarily to human beings (since they are not necessarily propertied). God also gives dispensation from the commands, according to Scotus, for example the command to Abraham to kill Isaac ( Ord III, suppl. Dist. 37). Third, Scotus denied the application of teleology to non-intentional nature, and thus departed from the Aristotelian and Thomist view. This does not mean that we have no natural end or telos , but that this end is related to the intention of God in the same way a human artisan intends his or her products to have a certain purpose (see Hare 2006, chapter 2).

Europe experienced a second Renaissance when scholars fled Constantinople after its capture by the Muslims in 1453, and brought with them Greek manuscripts that were previously inaccessible. In Florence Marsilio Ficino (1433–99) identified Plato as the primary ancient teacher of wisdom, and (like Bonaventure) cited Augustine as his guide in elevating Plato in this way. His choice of Plato was determined by the harmony he believed to exist between Plato's thought and the Christian faith, and he set about making Latin translations of all the Platonic texts so that this wisdom could be available for his contemporaries who did not know Greek. He was also the first Latin translator of Plotinus, the Neo-Platonist.

Many of the central figures in the Reformation were humanists in the Renaissance sense (where there is no implication of atheism). But there is also a fundamental similarity in the way the relation between morality and religion is conceived between Scotus and the two Reformers Martin Luther (1483–1546) and John Calvin (1509–64), though neither of them make the distinctions about natural law that Scotus (the ‘subtle doctor’) does. Luther says ‘What God wills is not right because he ought or was bound so to will; on the contrary, what takes place must be right, because he so wills.’ ( Bondage of the Will , Works , pp. 195–6). Calvin says ‘God's will is so much the highest rule of righteousness that whatever he wills, by the very fact that he wills it, must be considered righteous’ ( Institutes 3. 23. 2). The historical connection between Scotus and the Reformers can be traced through William of Ockham (d. 1349) and Gabriel Biel (1410–95). The Counter-Reformation in Roman Catholic Europe, on the other hand, took the work of Aquinas as authoritative for education. Francisco de Suarez (1548–1617) claimed that the precepts of natural law can be distinguished into those (like ‘Do good and avoid evil’) which are known immediately and intuitively by all normal human beings, those (like ‘Do no injury to anyone’) which require experience and thought to know them, but which are then self-evident, and those (like ‘Lying is always immoral’) which are not self-evident but can be derived from the more basic precepts ( De Legibus , 2. 7. 5). However, Suarez accepted Scotus's double account of motivation.

The next two centuries in European philosophy can be described in terms of two lines of development, rationalism and empiricism, both of which led, in different ways, to the possibility of a greater detachment of ethics from theology. The history of rationalism from René Descartes (1596–1650) to Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) is a history of re-establishing human knowledge on the foundation of rational principles that could not be doubted, after modern science started to shake the traditional foundations supported by the authority of Greek philosophy and the church. Descartes was not primarily an ethicist, but he located the source of moral law (surprisingly for a rationalist) in God's will. The most important rationalist in ethics was Benedict de Spinoza (1623–77). He was a Jew, but was condemned by his contemporary faith community as unorthodox. Like Descartes, he attempted to duplicate the methods of geometry in philosophy. Substance, according to Spinoza, exists in itself and is conceived through itself ( Ethics , I, def. 3); it is consequently one, infinite, and identical with God ( Ethics , I, prop. 15). There is no such thing as natural law, since all events in nature (‘God or Nature’) are equally natural. Everything in the universe is necessary, and there is no free will, except in as far as Spinoza is in favor of calling someone free who is led by reason ( Ethics , I, prop. 32). Each human mind is a limited aspect of the divine intellect. On this view (which has its antecedent in Stoicism) the human task is to move towards the greatest possible rational control of human life. Leibniz was, like Descartes, not primarily an ethicist. He said, however, that ‘the highest perfection of any thinking being lies in careful and constant pursuit of true happiness’ ( New Essays on Human Understanding , XXI, 51). The rationalists were not denying the centrality of God in human moral life, but their emphasis was on the access we have through the light of reason rather than through sacred text or ecclesiastical authority.

After Leibniz there was in Germany a long-running battle between the rationalists and the pietists, who tried to remain true to the goals of the Lutheran Reformation. Examples of the two schools are Christian Wolff (1679–1754) and Christian August Crusius (1715–75), and we can understand Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), like his teacher Martin Knutzen (1713–51), as trying to mediate between the two. Wolff was a very successful popularizer of the thought of Leibniz, but fuller in his ethical system. He took from Leibniz the principle that we will always select what pleases us most, and the principle that pleasure is the apprehension of perfection, so that the amount of pleasure we feel is proportional to the amount of perfection we intuit ( New Essays on Human Understanding , XXI, 41). He thought we are obligated to do what will make us and our condition, or that of others, more perfect, and this is the law of nature that would be binding on us even if ( per impossible ) God did not exist. He saw no problem about the connection between virtue and happiness, since both of them result directly from our perfection, and no problem about the connection between virtue and duty, since a duty is simply an act in accordance with law, which prescribes the pursuit of perfection. His views were offensive to the pietists, because he claimed that Confucius already knew (by reason) all that mattered about morality, even though he did not know anything about Christ. Crusius by contrast accepted Scotus's double theory of motivation, and held that there are actions that we ought to do regardless of any ends we have, even the end of our own perfection and happiness. It is plausible to see here the origin of Kant's categorical imperative. But he also added a third motivation, what he called ‘the drive of conscience’ which is ‘the natural drive to recognize a divine moral law’ (“A Guide to Rational Living,” Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to Kant , §132, 574). His idea was that we have within us this separate capacity to recognize divine command and to be drawn towards it out of a sense of dependence on the God who prescribes the command to us, and will punish us if we disobey (though our motive should not be to avoid punishment) (Ibid., §135).

The history of empiricism in Britain from Hobbes to Hume is also the history of the attempt to re-establish human knowledge, but not from above (from indubitable principles of reason) but from below (from experience and especially the experience of the senses). Thomas Hobbes (1588–1649) said that all reality is bodily (including God), and all events are motions in space. Willing, then, is a motion, and is merely the last act of desire or aversion in any process of deliberation. His view is that it is natural, and so reasonable, for each of us to aim solely at our own preservation or pleasure. In the state of nature, humans are selfish, and their lives are ‘solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short’, a war of all against all ( Leviathan , Ch. 13). The first precept of the law of nature is then for each of us, pursuing our own interest, ‘to endeavor peace, as far as he has hope of attaining it; and when he cannot obtain it, that he may seek, and use, all helps, and advantages of war.’ ( Ibid ., Ch. 14). The second precept is that each of us should be willing to lay down our natural rights to everything to the extent that others are also willing, and Hobbes concludes with the need to subordinate ourselves to a sovereign who alone will be able to secure peace. The second and longest portion of Leviathan is devoted to religion, where Hobbes argues for the authority of Scripture (‘God's word’), which he thinks is needed for the authority of law. He argues for the authority in the interpretation of Scripture to be given to that same earthly sovereign, and not to competing ecclesiastical authorities (whose competition had been seen to exacerbate the miseries of war both in Britain and on the continent) ( Ibid ., Ch. 33).

John Locke (1632–1704) followed Hobbes in deriving morality from our need to live together in peace given our natural discord, but he denied that we are mechanically moved by our desires. He agreed with Hobbes in saying that moral laws are God's imposition, but disagreed by making God's power and benevolence both necessary conditions for God's authority in this respect ( Treatises , IV. XIII. 3). He also held that our reason can work out counsels or advice about moral matters; but only God's imposition makes law (and hence obligation), and we only know about God's imposition from revelation ( The Reasonableness of Christianity , 62–5). He therefore devoted considerable attention to justifying our belief in the reliability of revelation.

The deists (e.g., William Wollaston, 1659–1724) believed that humans can reason from their experience of nature to the existence and some of the attributes of God, that special revelation is accordingly unnecessary, that God does not intervene in human affairs (after creation) and that the good life for humans finds adequate guidance in philosophical ethics. Frances Hutcheson (1694–1746) was not a deist, but does give a reading of the sort of guidance involved here. He distinguished between objects that are naturally good, which excite personal or selfish pleasure, and those that are morally good, which are advantageous to all persons affected. He took himself to be giving a reading of moral goodness as agape , the Greek word for the love of our neighbor that Jesus prescribes. This love is benevolence, Hutcheson said, and it is formulated in the principle ‘That Action is best, which procures the greatest Happiness for the greatest Numbers’ ( Inquiry II, III, VIII). Because these definitions of natural and moral good produce a possible gap between the two, we need some way to believe that morality and happiness are coincident. Hutcheson thought that God has given us a moral sense for this purpose ( Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions , II). This moral sense responds to examples of benevolence with approbation and a unique kind of pleasure, and benevolence is the only thing it responds to, as it were the only signal it picks up. It is, like Scotus's affection for justice, not confined to our perception of advantage. The result of our having moral sense is that when intending the good of others, we ‘undesignedly’ end up promoting our own greatest good as well because we end up gratifying ourselves along with others. God shows benevolence by first making us benevolent and then giving us this moral sense that gets joy from the approbation of our benevolence. To contemporary British opponents of moral sense theory, this seemed too rosy or benign a picture; our joy in approving benevolence is not enough to make morality and happiness coincident. We need also obligation and divine sanction.

Joseph Butler (1692–1752, Bishop of Bristol and then of Durham) held that God's goodness consists in benevolence, in wanting us to be happy, and that we should want the same for each other. He made the important point that something can be good for an agent because it is what he wants without this meaning that the content of what he wants has anything to do with himself ( Fifteen Sermons , 126–27).

David Hume (1711–76) is the first figure in this narrative who can properly be attached to the Enlightenment, though this term means very different things in Scotland, in France and in Germany. Hume held that reason cannot command or move the human will. Since morals clearly do have an influence on actions and affections, ‘it follows that they cannot be derived from reason; and that because reason alone, as we have already proved, can never have any such influence’ ( Treatise III.1). For Hume an action, or sentiment, or character, is virtuous or vicious ‘because its view causes a pleasure or uneasiness of a particular kind’ ( Ibid ., III.2). The denial of motive power to reason is part of his general skepticism. He accepted from Locke the principle that our knowledge is restricted to sense impressions from experience and logically necessary relations of ideas in advance of experience (in Latin, a priori ). From this principle he derived more radical conclusions than Locke had done. For example, we cannot know about causation or the soul. The only thing we can know about morals is that we get pleasure from the thought of some things and pain from the thought of others. Since the idea of morality implies something universal, there must be some sentiment of sympathy or (he later says) humanity, which is common to all human beings, and which ‘recommends the same object to general approbation’ ( Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals , IX. I. 221). Hume thought we could get conventional moral conclusions from these moral sentiments, which nature has fortunately given us. He was also skeptical about any attempt to derive conclusions containing ‘ought’ from premises containing only ‘is’, though scholars debate about the scope of the premises he is talking about here. Probably he included premises about God's will or nature or action. This does not mean he was arguing against the existence of God. He thought (like Calvin) that we cannot rely on rational proofs of God's existence, even though humans have what Calvin called a sense of the divine and Human called ‘true religion’. But Hume never identified himself as an atheist, though he had opportunity in the atheist circles he frequented in Paris, and his Dialogues on Natural Religion end with the sentiment that ‘to be a philosophical skeptic is, in a man of letters, the first and most essential step towards being a sound, believing Christian’ ( Dialogues , part XII, penultimate paragraph). Some scholars take this remark (like similar statements in Hobbes) as purely ironic, but this goes beyond the evidence.

The Enlightenment in France had a more anti-clerical flavor (in part because of the history of Jansenism, unique to France), and for the first time in this narrative we meet genuine atheists, such as Baron d'Holbach (1723–89) who held not only that morality did not need religion, but that religion, and especially Christianity, was its major impediment. François-Marie Voltaire (1694-1778) was, especially towards the end of his life, opposed to Christianity, but not to religion in general ( Letters of Voltaire and Frederick the Great , letter 156). He accepted from the English deists the idea that what is true in Christian teachings is the core of human values that are universally true in all religions, and (like the German rationalists) he admired Confucius. Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-78) said, famously, that mankind is born free, but everywhere he is in chains ( The Social Contract , Ch. 1). This supposes a disjunction between nature and contemporary society, and Rousseau held that the life of primitive human beings was happy inasmuch as they knew how to live in accordance with their own innate needs; now we need some kind of social contract to protect us from the corrupting effects of society upon the proper love of self. Nature is understood as the whole realm of being created by God, who guarantees its goodness, unity, and order. Rousseau held that we do not need any intermediary between us and God, and we can attain salvation by returning to nature in this high sense and by developing all our faculties harmoniously. Our ultimate happiness is to feel ourselves at one with the system that God created.

Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) is the most important figure of the Enlightenment in Germany, but his project is different in many ways from those of his French contemporaries. He was brought up in a pietist Lutheran family, and his system retains many features from, for example, Crusius. But he was also indebted through Wolff to Leibniz. Moreover, he was ‘awoken from his dogmatic slumbers’ by reading Hume, though Kant is referring here to Hume's attack on causation, not his ethical theory ( Prolegomena , 4:260). Kant's mature project was to limit human knowledge ‘in order to make room for faith’ ( KrV , B xxx). He accepted from Hume that our knowledge is confined within the limits of possible sense experience, but he did not accept skeptical conclusions about causation or the soul. Reason is not confined, in his view, to the same limits as knowledge, and we are rationally required to hold beliefs about things as they are in themselves, not merely things as they appear to us. In particular, we are required to believe in God, freedom and immortality. These are three ‘postulates of practical reason’, required to make rational sense of the fact of moral obligation, the fact that we are under the moral law (the ‘categorical imperative’) that requires us to will the maxim of an action (the prescription of the action together with the reason for it) as a universal law (removing any self-preference) and to treat humanity in any person as always at the same time an end and never merely as a means ( Groundwork , 4.421, 429). Kant thought that humans have to be able to believe that morality in this demanding form is consistent in the long run with happiness (both their own and that of the people they affect by their actions), if they are going to be able to persevere in the moral life without rational instability. He did not accept the three traditional theoretical arguments for the existence of God (though he was sympathetic to a modest version of the teleological argument). But the practical argument was decisive for him, though he held that it was possible to be morally good without being a theist, despite such a position being rationally unstable.

In Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason he undertook the project of using moral language in order to translate the four main themes of Biblical revelation (accessible only to particular people at particular times) into the revelation to Reason (accessible to all people at all times). This does not mean that he intended to reduce Biblical faith to morality, though some scholars have taken him this way. The translated versions of Creation, Fall, Redemption and Second Coming are as follows (see Hare 1996): Humans have an initial predisposition to the good, which is essential to them, but is overlaid with a propensity to evil, which is not essential to them. Since they are born under ‘the Evil Maxim’ that subordinates duty to happiness, they are unable by their own devices to reverse this ranking, and require ‘an effect of grace’ ( Religion , 6.53). Providence ushers in progress (though not continuous) towards an ‘ethical commonwealth’ in which we together make the moral law our own law, by appropriating it as authoritative for our own lives (this is what Kant means by ‘autonomy’) ( Religion , 6.98–99; Groundwork , 4.433–34).

A whole succession of Kant's followers tried to ‘go beyond’ Kant by showing that there was finally no need to make the separation between our knowledge and the thing-in-itself beyond our knowledge. One key step in departing from the surviving influence in Kant of Lutheran pietism was taken by Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762–1814), who identified (as Kant did not) the will of the individual with the infinite Ego which is ordering the universe morally. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770–1831) accomplished a somewhat similar end by proposing that we should make the truth of ideas relative to their original historical context against the background of a history that is progressing towards a final stage of ‘absolute knowledge’, in which Spirit (in German Geist , which means also ‘mind’) understands that reality is its own creation and there is no ‘beyond’ for it to know. Hegel is giving a philosophical account of the Biblical notion of all things returning to God, ‘so that God may be all in all.’ ( I Cor . 15:28) In this world-history, Hegel located the Reformation as ‘the all-enlightening sun’ of the bright day that is our modern time ( The Philosophy of History , 412). He thought that Geist moves immanently through human history, and that the various stages of knowledge are also stages of freedom, each stage producing first its own internal contradiction, and then a radical transition into a new stage. The stage of absolute freedom will be one in which all members freely by reason endorse the organic community and the concrete institutions in which they actually live ( Phenomenology , BB, VI, B, III).

One of Hegel's opponents was Arthur Schopenhauer (1799–1860), the philosopher of pessimism. Schopenhauer thought that Hegel had strayed from the Kantian truth that there is a thing-in-itself beyond appearance, and that the Will is such a thing. He differed from Kant, however, in seeing the Will as the source of all our endless suffering, a blind striving power without ultimate purpose or design ( The World as Will and Representation , §56 p. 310 and §57 p. 311). It is, moreover, one universal Will that underlies the wills of all separate individuals. The intellect and its ideas are simply the Will's servant. On this view, there is no happiness for us, and our only consolation is a (quasi-Buddhist) release from the Will to the limited extent we can attain it, especially through aesthetic enjoyment.

Hegel's followers split into what are sometimes called ‘Right Hegelians’ and ‘Left Hegelians’ (or ‘Young Hegelians’). Right Hegelians promoted the generally positive view of the Prussian state that Hegel expressed in the Philosophy of Right . Left Hegelians rejected it, and with it the Protestant Christianity which they saw as its vehicle. In this way Hegel's peculiar way of promoting Christianity ended up causing its vehement rejection by thinkers who shared many of his social ideals. David Friedrich Strauss (1808–74) wrote The Life of Jesus Critically Examined , launching the historical-critical method of Biblical scholarship with the suggestion that much of the Biblical account is myth or ‘unconscious invention’ that needs to be separated out from the historical account. Ludwig Andreas Feuerbach (1804–72) wrote The Essence of Christianity in which he pictured all religion as the means by which ‘man projects his being into objectivity, and then again makes himself an object to this projected image of himself’ ( The Essence of Christianity , 30). Feuerbach thought religion resulted from humanity's alienation from itself, and philosophy needed to destroy the religious illusion so that we could learn to love humankind and not divert this love onto an imaginary object. Karl Marx (1818–83) followed Feuerbach in this diagnosis of religion, but he was interested primarily in social and political relations rather than psychology. He became suspicious of theory (for example Hegel's), on the grounds that theory is itself a symptom of the power structures in the societies that produce it. “Theory,” Marx writes, “is realized in a people only in so far as it is a realization of the people's needs” (“Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right,” Early Writings , 252). And ‘ideologies’ and ‘religion,’ he believes, arise from “conditions that require [these] illusions” (Ibid., 244). Marx returned to Hegel's thoughts about work revealing to the worker his value through what the worker produces, but Marx argues that under capitalism the worker was alienated from this product because other people owned both the product and the means of producing it. Marx urged that the only way to prevent this was to destroy the institution of private property (“Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts,” Early Writings , 348). Thus he believed, like Hegel, in progress through history towards freedom, but he thought it would take Communist revolution to bring this about.

A very different response to Hegel (and Kant) is found in the work of Søren Kierkegaard (1813–55), a religious thinker who started, like Hegel and Kant, from Lutheranism. Kierkegaard mocked Hegel constantly for presuming to understand the whole system in which human history is embedded, while still being located in a particular small part of it. On the other hand, he used Hegelian categories of thought himself, especially in his idea of the aesthetic life, the ethical life and the religious life as stages through which human beings develop by means of first internal contradiction and then radical transition. Kierkegaard's relation with Kant was problematic as well. In Either/Or he caricatured Kant's ethical thought (as well as Hegel's) in the person of Judge William, who is stuck within the ethical life and has not been able to reach the life of faith. On the other hand, his own description of the religious life is full of echoes of Kant's Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason . Kierkegaard wrote most of his work pseudonymously, taking on the names of characters who lived the lives he describes. In the aesthetic life the goal is to keep at bay the boredom that is constantly threatening, and this requires enough distance from one's projects that one is not stuck with them but can flit from engagement to engagement without pain ( Either/Or , II. 77). This life deconstructs, because it requires (in order to sustain interest) the very commitment that it also rejects. The transition is accomplished by making a choice for one's life as a whole from a position that is not attached to any particular project, a radical choice that requires admitting the aesthetic life has been a failure. In this choice one discovers freedom, and thus the ethical life ( Either/Or , II. 188). But this life too deconstructs, because it sets up the goal of living by a demand, the moral law, that is higher than we can live by our own human devices. Kierkegaard thought we have to realize that God is (contrary to Fichte) ‘another’ ( Sickness unto Death xi 128), with whom we have to relate, and whose assistance is necessary even for the kind of repentance that is the transition into the religious life. He also suggested that within the religious life, there is a ‘repetition’ of the aesthetic life and the ethical life, though in a transformed version.

Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) was the son of a Lutheran pastor in Prussia. He was trained as a classical philologist, and his first book, The Birth of Tragedy , was an account of the origin and death of ancient Greek tragedy. Nietzsche was deeply influenced by Schopenhauer, especially his view of the will (which Nietzsche called ‘the Will to Power’), and was first attracted and then repelled by Wagner, who was also one of Schopenhauer's disciples. The breaking point seems to have been Wagner's Parsifal . Nietzsche by this time was opposed to orthodox Christianity and was promoting Ancient Greece instead, and he thought that Wagner was betraying his integrity by using an ‘anti-Greek’ Christian story for the opera. Nietzsche saw clearly the intimate link between Christianity and the ethical theories of his predecessors in Europe, especially Kant. In On the Genealogy of Morals , he says, ‘The advent of the Christian God, as the maximum god attained so far, was therefore accompanied by the maximum feeling of guilty indebtedness on earth. Presuming we have gradually entered upon the reverse course, there is no small probability that with the irresistible decline of faith in the Christian God, there is now also a considerable decline in mankind's feeling of guilt’ ( On the Genealogy of Morals , 90–1). This is the ‘death of God’ which Nietzsche announced, and which he predicted would also be the end of Kantian ethics ( The Gay Science , §108, 125, 343). It is harder to know what Nietzsche was for, than what he was against. This is partly an inheritance from Schopenhauer, who thought any system of constructive ethical thought a delusion. But Nietzsche clearly admired the Ancient Greeks, and thought we would be better off with a ‘master’ morality like theirs, rather than a ‘slave’ morality like Christianity. ‘Mastery over himself also necessarily gives him mastery over circumstances, over nature, and over all more short-willed and unreliable creatures’ ( Genealogy , 59-60). By this last clause, he meant mastery over other people, and the model of this mastery is the ‘overman’ who is free of the resentment by the weak of the strong that Nietzsche thought lay at the basis of Christian ethics.

To return to Britain, Hume had a number of successors who accepted the view (which Hume took from Hutcheson) that our fundamental obligation is to work for the greatest happiness of the greatest number. Four are especially significant. William Paley (1743–1805) thought he could demonstrate that morality derived from the will of God and required promoting the happiness of all, that happiness was the sum of pleasures, and that we need to believe that God is the final granter of happiness if we are to sustain motivation to do what we know we ought to do ( The Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy , II. 4). Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) rejected this theological context. His grounds were radically empiricist, that the only ‘real’ entities are publicly observable, and so do not include God (or, for that matter, right or time or relations or qualities). He thought he could provide a scientific calculus of pleasures, where the unit that stays constant is the minimum state of sensibility that can be distinguished from indifference. He thought we could then separate different ‘dimensions’ in which these units vary, such as intensity, duration, certainty, propinquity (how soon the pleasures will come), fecundity (how many other pleasures this pleasure will produce) and purity. Discarding the theological context made moral motivation problematic, for why should we expect (without God) more units of pleasure for ourselves by contributing to the greater pleasure of others? Bentham's solution was to hope that law and social custom could provide individuals with adequate motives through the threat of social sanctions, and that what he called ‘deontology’ (which is personal or private morality) could mobilize hidden or long-range interests that were already present but obscure.

John Stuart Mill (1806–73) was raised on strict utilitarian principles by his father, a follower of Bentham. Unlike Bentham, however, Mill accepted that there are qualitative differences in pleasures simply as pleasures, and he thought that the higher pleasures were those of the intellect, the feelings and imagination, and the moral sentiments. He observed that those who have experienced both these and the lower pleasures, tend to prefer the former. At the age of twenty he had a collapse and a prolonged period of ‘melancholy’. He realized that his education had neglected the culture or cultivation of feelings , of which hope is a primary instance ( Autobiography , 1. 84). In his Three Essays on Religion (published posthumously in 1874) he returned to the idea of hope, saying that ‘the indulgence of hope with regard to the government of the universe and the destiny of man after death, while we recognize as a clear truth that we have no ground for more than a hope, is legitimate and philosophically defensible’; without such hope, we are kept down by ‘the disastrous feeling of “not worth while”’ ( Three Essays 249–50). Mill did not believe, however, that God was omnipotent, given all the evil in the world, and he insisted, like Kant, that we have to be God's co-workers, not merely passive recipients of God's assistance.

Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900) in Methods of Ethics distinguished three methods: Intuitionism (which is, roughly, the common sense morality that some things, like deliberate ingratitude to a benefactor, are self-evidently wrong in themselves independently of their consequences), Egoistic Hedonism (the view that self-evidently an individual ought to aim at a maximum balance of happiness for herself, where this is understood as the greatest balance of pleasure over pain), and Utilitarianism or Universalistic Hedonism, (the view that self-evidently she ought to aim at the maximum balance of happiness for all sentient beings present and future, whatever the cost to herself). Of these three, he rejected the first, on the grounds that no concrete ethical principles are self-evident, and that when they conflict (as they do) we have to take consequences into account in order to decide how to act. But Sidgwick found the relation between the other two methods much more problematic. Each principle separately seemed to him self-evident, but when taken together they seems to be mutually inconsistent. He considered two solutions, psychological and metaphysical. The psychological solution was to bring in the pleasures and pains of sympathy, so that if we do good to all we end up (because of these pleasures) making ourselves happiest. Sidgwick rejected this on the basis that sympathy is inevitably limited in its range, and we feel it most towards those closest to us, so that even if we include sympathetic pleasures and pains under Egoism, it will tend to increase the divergence between Egoistic and Utilitarian conduct, rather than bring them closer together. The metaphysical solution was to bring in a god who desires the greatest total good of all living things, and who will reward and punish in accordance with this desire. Sidgwick recognized this as a return to the utilitarianism of Paley (Compare Methods of Ethics , II. 1, 2 and IV. 4, 5). He thought this solution was both necessary and sufficient to remove the contradiction in ethics. But this was only a reason to accept it, if in general it is reasonable to accept certain principles (such as the Uniformity of Nature) which are not self-evident and which cannot be proved, but which bring order and coherence into a central part of our thought. Sidgwick did not commit himself to an answer to this, one way or the other.

In the twentieth century professional philosophy in the West divided up into two streams, sometimes called ‘Analytic’ and ‘Continental’, and there were periods during which the two schools lost contact with each other. Towards the end of the century, however, there were more philosophers who could speak the languages of both traditions. The beginning of the analytic school is sometimes located with the rejection of a neo-Hegelian idealism by G.E. Moore (1873-1958). One way to characterize the two schools is that the Continental school continued to read and be influenced by Hegel, and the Analytic school (with some exceptions) did not. Another way to make the distinction is geographical; the analytic school is located primarily in Britain, Scandinavia and N. America, and the continental school in the rest of Europe, in Latin America and in certain schools in N. America.

We will start with some figures from the Continental school, and then move to the analytic (which is this writer's own). Martin Heidegger (1889–1976) was initially trained as a theologian, and wrote his dissertation on what he took to be a work of Duns Scotus. He took an appointment under Edmund Husserl (1855–1938) at Freiburg, and was then appointed to succeed him in his chair. Husserl's program of ‘phenomenology’ was to recover a sense of certainty about the world by studying in exhaustive detail the cognitive structure of appearance. Heidegger departed from Husserl in approaching Being through a focus on ‘Human Being’ (in German Dasein ) concerned above all for its fate in an alien world, or as ‘anxiety’ ( Angst ) towards death (see Being and Time I. 6). In this sense he is the first existentialist, though he did not use the term. Heidegger emphasized that we are ‘thrown’ into a world that is not ‘home’, and we have a radical choice about what possibilities for ourselves we will make actual. Heidegger drew here from Kierkegaard, and he is also similar in describing the danger of falling back into mere conventionality, what Heidegger calls ‘the They’ ( das Man ). On the other hand he is unlike Kierkegaard in thinking of traditional Christianity as just one more convention making authentic existence more difficult. In Heidegger, as in Nietzsche and Schopenhauer, it is hard to find a positive or constructive ethics. Heidegger's position is somewhat compromised, moreover, by his initial embrace of the Nazi party. In his later work he moved increasingly towards a kind of quasi-religious mysticism. His Romantic hatred of the modern world and his distrust of system-building led to the espousal of either silence or poetry as the best way to be open to the ‘something’ (sometimes he says ‘the earth’) which reveals itself only as ‘self-secluding’ or hiding itself away from our various conceptualizations. He held the hope that through poetry, and in particular the poetry of Hölderlin, we might be able to still sense something of the unknown god who appears ‘as the one who remains unknown,’ who is quite different from the object of theology or piety, but who can bring us back to the Being we have long lost sight of ( Poetry, Language, Thought , 222).

Jean-Paul Sartre (1905-80) did use the label ‘existentialist’, and said that ‘Existentialism is nothing else than an attempt to draw all the consequences of a coherent atheist position’ ( Existentialism and Human Emotions , 51). He denied (like Scotus) that the moral law could be deduced from human nature, but this was because (unlike Scotus) he thought that we give ourselves our own essences by the choices we make. His slogan was, ‘Existence precedes essence’ (Ibid., 13). ‘Essence’ is here the defining property of a thing, and Sartre gave the example of a paper cutter, which is given its definition by the artisan who makes it. Sartre said that when people believed God made human beings, they could believe humans had a God-given essence; but now that we do not believe this, we have realized that humans give themselves their own essences (‘First of all, man exists, turns up, appears on the scene, and, only afterwards, defines himself.’ Ibid., 15). On this view there are no outside commands to appeal to for legitimation, and we are condemned to our own freedom. Sartre thought of human beings as trying to be God (on a Hegelian account of what God is), even though there is no God. This is an inevitably fruitless undertaking, which he called ‘anguish’. Moreover, we inevitably desire to choose not just for ourselves, but for the world. We want, like God, to create humankind in our own image, ‘If I want to marry, to have children, even if this marriage depends solely on my own circumstances or passion or wish, I am involving all humanity in monogamy and not merely myself. Therefore, I am responsible for myself and for everyone else. I am creating a certain image of man of my own choosing. In choosing myself, I choose man’ (Ibid., 18). To recognize that this project does not make sense is required by honesty, and to hide this from ourselves is ‘bad faith’. One form of bad faith is to pretend that there is a God who is giving us our tasks. Another is to pretend that there is a ‘human nature’ that is doing the same thing. To live authentically is to realize both that we create these tasks for ourselves, and that they are futile.

The twentieth century also saw, within Roman Catholicism, forms of Christian Existentialism and new adaptations of the system of Thomas Aquinas. Gabriel Marcel (1889–1973), like Heidegger, was concerned with the nature of Being as it appears to human being, but he tried to show that there are experiences of love, joy, hope and faith which, as understood from within , give us reason to believe in an inexhaustible Presence, which is God. Jacques Maritain (1882–1973) developed a form of Thomism that retained the natural law, but regarded ethical judgment as not purely cognitive but guided by pre-conceptual affective inclinations. He gave more place to history than traditional Thomism did, allowing for development in the human knowledge of natural law, and he defended democracy as the appropriate way for human persons to attain freedom and dignity. The notion of the value of the person and the capacities given to persons by their creator was at the center of the ‘personalism’ of Pope John Paul II's The Acting Person (1979), influenced by Max Scheler (1874–1928).

Natural law theory has been taken up and modified more recently by three philosophers who write in a style closer to the analytic tradition, John Finnis, Alastair MacIntyre and Jean Porter. Finnis holds that our knowledge of the fundamental moral truths is self-evident, and so is not deduced from human nature. His Natural Law and Natural Rights (1980) was a landmark in integrating the modern vocabulary and grammar of rights into the tradition of Natural Law. MacIntyre, who has been on a long journey back from Marxism to Thomism, holds that we can know what kind of life we ought to live on the basis of knowing our natural end, which he now identifies in theological terms. In After Virtue (1981) he is still influenced by a Hegelian historicism, and holds that the only way to settle rival knowledge claims is to see how successfully each can account for the shape taken by its rivals. A different account of natural law is found in Porter, who in Nature as Reason (2005) retains the view that our final motivation is our own happiness and perfection, but rejects the view that we can deduce absolute action-guiding moral principles from human nature. Another contemporary school is virtue ethics, for example Philippa Foot in Natural Goodness (2001) and Rosalind Hursthouse in On Virtue Ethics (1999). They are not Roman Catholic but they are strongly influenced by Aristotle and Aquinas. They emphasize the notion of virtue which belongs to human nature just as bees have stings. Hursthouse ends her book by saying that we have to hold onto the hope that we can live together, not at each other's expense, a hope which she says used to be called belief in (God's) Providence ( On Virtue Ethics , 265). One final contribution to be mentioned here is Linda Zagzebski's Divine Motivation Theory (2004) which proposes, as an alternative to divine command theory, that we can understand all moral normatively in terms of the notion of a good emotion, and that God's emotions are the best exemplar. We will return to the rebirth of divine command theory at the end of this entry.

Michel Foucault (1926–84) followed Nietzsche in aspiring to uncover the ‘genealogy’ of various contemporary forms of thought and practice (he was concerned, for example, with our treatment of sexuality and mental illness), and how relations of power and domination have produced ‘discourses of truth’ (“Truth and Power,” Power , 131). In his later work he described four different aspects of the ‘practice of the self’: We select the desires, acts, and thoughts that we attend to morally, we recognize ourselves as morally bound by some particular ground, e.g., divine commands, or rationality, or human nature, we transform ourselves into ethical subjects by some set of techniques, e.g., meditation or mortification or consciousness-raising, and finally, we propose a ‘ telos ’ or goal, the way of life or mode of being that the subject is aiming at, e.g., self-mastery, tranquility or purification. Foucault criticized Christian conventions that tend to take morality as a juristic and often universal code of laws, and to ignore the creative practice of self-making. Even if Christian and post-Christian moralists turn their attention to self-expression, he thought they tend to focus on the confession of truth about oneself, a mode of expression which is historically linked to the church and the modern psycho-sciences. Foucault preferred stressing our freedom to form ourselves as ethical subjects, and develop ‘a new form of right’ and a ‘non-disciplinary form of power’ (“Disciplinary Power and Subjection,” Power , 242). He did not, however, tell us much more about what these new forms would be like.

Jürgen Habermas (1929-) proposed a ‘communicative ethics’ that develops the Kantian element in Marxism ( The Theory of Communicative Action , Vols. I and II). By analyzing the structure of communication (using speech-act theory developed in analytic philosophy) he lays out a procedure that will rationally justify norms, though he does not claim to know what norms a society will adopt by using this procedure. The two ideas behind this procedure are that norms are valid if they receive the consent of all the affected parties in unconstrained practical communication, and if the consequences of the general observance of the norms (in terms of how each person's interests are affected) are acceptable to all. Habermas thinks he fulfills in this way Hegel's aim of reconciling the individual and society, because the communication process extends individuals beyond their private perspectives in the process of reaching agreement. Religious convictions need to be left behind when entering the public square, on this scheme, because they are not communicable in the way the procedure requires. In recent work he has modified this position, by recognizing that certain religious forms require their adherents to speak in an explicitly religious way when advancing their prescriptions for public life, and it is discriminatory to try to prevent their doing so.

Within contemporary Jewish ethics mention should be made of Martin Buber (1878–1965) and Emmanuel Levinas (1906–95). Buber's form of existentialism emphasized the I-You relationship, which exists not only between human beings but (out of that) between human beings and God. When we reject I-You relationship, we return to I-It relations, governed by our impositions of our own conceptualizations on objects. Buber said these two relations are exhaustive. ‘There is no I as such but only the I of the basic word I-You and the I of the basic word I-It.’ ( I and Thou , 54). Levinas studied under Husserl, and knew Heidegger, whose work he first embraced and then rejected. His focus, like Buber's, was on the ‘ethics of the Other’, and he held that the face of the Other makes a demand on us even before we recognize our freedom to accept it or reject it. To meet the Other is to have the idea of Infinity ( Ethics and Infinity , 90–1).

We are sometimes said to live now in a ‘post-modern’ age. This term is problematic in various ways. As used within architectural theory in the 1960's and 1970's it had a relatively clear sense. There was a recognizable style that either borrowed bits and pieces from styles of the past, or mocked the very idea (in modernist architecture) of essential functionality. In philosophy, the term is less clearly definable. It combines a distaste for ‘meta-narratives’ and a rejection of any form of foundationalism. The effect on philosophical thinking about the relation between morality and religion is two-fold. On the one hand, the modernist rejection of religion on the basis of a foundationalist empiricism is itself rejected. This makes the current climate more hospitable to religious language than it was for most of the twentieth century. But on the other hand, the distaste for over-arching theory means that religious meta-narratives are suspect to the same degree as any other, and the hospitality is more likely to be towards bits and pieces of traditional theology than to any theological system as a whole. Habermas uses the term ‘post-secular age’ to describe our current condition, in which the secularization hypothesis (that religion was destined to wither away under the impact of science and education) has apparently failed.

Mention should be made of some movements that are not philosophical in a professional sense, but are important in understanding the relation between morality and religion. Liberation theology, of which a leading spokesman from Latin America is Gustavo Gutiérrez (1928-), has attempted to reconcile the Christian gospel with a commitment (influenced by Marxist categories) to revolution to relieve the condition of the oppressed. The civil rights movement (drawing heavily on Exodus ), feminist ethics, animal liberation, environmental ethics, and the gay rights and children's rights movements have shown special sensitivity to the moral status of some particular oppressed class. The leadership of some of these movements has been religiously committed, while the leadership of others has not. At the same time, the notion of human rights, or justified claims by every human being, has grown in global reach, partly through the various instrumentalities of the United Nations. There has, however, been less consensus on the question of how to justify human rights. There are theological justifications, deriving from the image of God in every human being, or the command to love the neighbor, or the covenant between God and humanity (see Wolterstorff, Justice : Rights and Wrongs , chapter 16). Whether there is a non-theological justification is not yet clear. Finally, there has also been a burst of activity in professional ethics, such as medical ethics, engineering ethics, and business ethics. This has not been associated with any one school of philosophy rather than another. The connection of religion with these developments has been variable. In some cases (e.g., medical ethics) the initial impetus for the new sub-discipline was strongly influenced by theology, and in other cases not.

The origin of analytic philosophy can be associated with G.E. Moore. His Principia Ethica (1903) can be regarded as the first major ethical document of the school. He was strongly influenced by Sidgwick at Cambridge, but rejected Sidgwick's negative views about intuitionism. He thought that intrinsic goodness was a real property of things, even though (like the number two) it does not exist in time and is not the object of sense experience. He explicitly aligned himself here with Plato and against the class of empiricist philosophers, ‘to which most Englishmen have belonged’ ( Principia Ethica , 162). His predecessors, Moore thought, had almost all committed the error, which he called ‘the naturalistic fallacy,’ of trying to define this value property by identifying it with a non-evaluative property. For example, they proposed that goodness is pleasure, or what produces pleasure. But whatever non-evaluative property we try to say goodness is identical to, we will find that it remains an open question whether that property is in fact good. For example, it makes sense to ask whether pleasure or the production of pleasure is good. This is true also if we propose a supernatural property to identify with goodness, for example the property of being commanded by God. It still makes sense to ask whether what God commands is good. This question cannot be the same as the question ‘Is what God commands what God commands?’ which is not still an open question. Moore thought that if these questions are different, then the two properties, goodness and being commanded by God, cannot be the same, and to say (by way of a definition) that they are the same is to commit the fallacy. Intrinsic goodness, Moore said, is a simple non-natural property (i.e., neither natural nor supernatural) and indefinable. He thought we had a special form of cognition that he called ‘intuition,’ which gives us access to such properties. By this he meant that the access was not based on inference or argument, but was self-evident (though we could still get it wrong, just as we can with sense-perception). He thought the way to determine what things had positive value intrinsically was to consider what things were such that, if they existed by themselves in isolation, we would yet judge their existence to be good.

At Cambridge Moore was a colleague of Bertrand Russell (1872–1970) and Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951). Russell was not primarily a moral philosopher, but he expressed radically different views at different times about ethics. In 1910 he agreed with Moore that goodness (like roundness) is a quality that belongs to objects independently of our opinions, and that when two people differ about whether a thing is good, only one of them can be right. By 1922 he was holding an error theory (like that of John Mackie, 1917–81) that although we mean by ‘good’ an objective property in this way, there is in fact no such thing, and hence all our value judgments are strictly speaking false (“The Element of Ethics,” Philosophical Essays ). Then by 1935 he had dropped also the claim about meaning, holding that value judgments are expressions of desire or wish, and not assertions at all. Wittgenstein's views on ethics are enigmatic and subject to wildly different interpretations. In the Tractatus (which is about logic) he says at the end, ‘It is clear that ethics cannot be put into words. Ethics is transcendental. (Ethics and aesthetics are one and the same.)’ ( Tractatus , 6.421). Perhaps he means that the world we occupy is good or bad (and happy or unhappy) as a whole, and not piece-by-piece. Wittgenstein (like Nietzsche) was strongly influenced by Schopenhauer's notion of will, and by his disdain for ethical theories that purport to be able to tell one what to do and what not to do. The Tractatus was taken up by the Logical Positivists, though Wittgenstein himself was never a Logical Positivist. The Logical Positivists held a ‘verificationist’ theory of meaning, that assertions can be meaningful only if they can in principle be verified by sense experience or if they are tautologies (for example, ‘All bachelors are unmarried men.’) This seems to leave ethical statements (and statements about God) meaningless, and indeed that was the deliberately provocative position taken by A.J. Ayer (1910–89). Ayer accepted Moore's arguments about the naturalistic fallacy, and since Moore's talk of ‘non-natural properties’ seemed to Ayer just nonsense, he was led to emphasize and analyze further the non-cognitive ingredient in evaluation which Moore had identified. Suppose I say to a cannibal, ‘You acted wrongly in eating your prisoner.’ Ayer thought I am not stating anything more than if I had simply said, ‘You ate your prisoner.’ I am, rather, evincing my moral disapproval of it. It is as if I had said, ‘You ate your prisoner’ in a peculiar tone of horror, or written it with the addition of some special exclamation marks ( Language, Truth and Logic , 107–8).

The emotivist theory of ethics had its most articulate treatment in Ethics and Language by Charles Stevenson (1908–79). Stevenson was a positivist, but also the heir of John Dewey (1859–1952) and the American pragmatist tradition. Dewey had rejected the idea of fixed ends for human beings, and stressed that moral deliberation occurs in the context of competition within a person between different ends, none of which can be assumed permanent. He criticized theories that tried to derive moral principles from self-certifying reason, or intuition, or cosmic forms, or divine commands, both because he thought there are no self-certifying faculties or self-evident norms, and because the alleged derivation disguises the actual function of the principles as devices for social action. Stevenson applied this emphasis to the competition between people with different ends, and stressed the role of moral language as a social instrument for persuasion ( Ethics and Language , Ch. 5). On his account, normative judgments express attitudes and invite others to share these attitudes, but they are not strictly speaking true or false.

Wittgenstein did not publish any book after the Tractatus , but he wrote and taught; and after his death Philosophical Investigations was published in 1953. The later thought of Wittgenstein bears a similar relation to the Tractatus as Heidegger bears to Husserl. In both cases the quest for a kind of scientific certainty was replaced by the recognition that science is itself just one language, and not in many cases prior by right. The later Wittgenstein employed the notion of different ‘forms of life’ in which different ‘language games’ including those of religion are at home ( Philosophical Investigation , §7, 19, 373). In Oxford there was a parallel though distinct development centering round the work of John Austin (1911–60). Austin did not suppose that ordinary language was infallible, but he did think that it preserved a great deal of wisdom that had passed the test of centuries of experience, and that traditional philosophical discussion had ignored this primary material. In How to do Things with Words (published posthumously) Austin labeled ‘the descriptive fallacy’ the mistake of thinking that all language is used to perform the act of describing or reporting, and he attributed the discovery of this fallacy to Kant ( How to do Things with Words , 3).

R.M. Hare (1919–2002) took up the diagnosis of this fallacy, and proposed a ‘universal prescriptivism’ which attributed three characteristics to the language of morality. First, it is prescriptive, which is to say that moral judgments express the will in a way analogous to commands. This preserves the emotivist insight that moral judgment is different from assertion, but does not deny the role of rationality in such judgment. Second, moral judgment is universalizable. This is similar to the formula of Kant's categorical imperative that requires that we be able to will the maxims of our actions as universal laws. Third, moral judgment is overriding. This means that moral prescriptions legitimately take precedence over any other normative prescriptions. In Moral Thinking (1981) Hare claimed to demonstrate that utilitarianism followed from these three features of morality, though he excluded ideals (in the sense of preferences for how the world should be independently of the agent's concurrent desires or experience) from the scope of this argument. God enters in two ways into this picture. First, Hare proposed a figure he calls ‘the archangel’ who is the model for fully critical (as opposed to intuitive) moral thinking, having full access to all the relevant information and complete impartiality between the affected parties. Hare acknowledge that since archangels (e.g., Lucifer) are not reliably impartial in this way, it is really God who is the model. Second, we have to be able to believe (as Kant argued) that the universe sustains morality in the sense that it is worthwhile trying to be morally good. Hare thought that this requires something like a belief (he called it a ‘blik’) in the operation of Providence (“The Simple Believer,” Essays on Religion and Education , appendix, 37–9).

The most important opponent of utilitarianism in the twentieth century was John Rawls (1921–2005). In his Theory of Justice (1971) he gave, like Hare, an account of ethics heavily indebted to Kant. But he insisted that utilitarianism does not capture the Kantian insight that each person is an end in himself or herself, because it ‘does not take seriously the distinction between persons’ ( Theory of Justice , 22). He constructed the thought experiment of the ‘Original Position’ in which individuals imagine themselves not knowing what role in society they are going to play or what endowments of talent or material wealth they possess, and agree together on what principles of justice they will accept. Rawls thought it important that substantive conceptions of the good life were left behind in moving to the Original Position, because he was attempting to provide an account of justice that people with competing visions of the good could agree to in a pluralist society. Like early Habermas he included religions under this prohibition. In Political Liberalism (1993) he conceded that the procedure of the Original Position is itself ideologically constrained, and he moved to the idea of an overlapping consensus: Kantians can accept the idea of justice as fairness (which the procedure describes) because it realizes autonomy, utilitarians because it promotes overall utility, Christians because it is part of divine law, etc. But even here Rawls wanted to insist that adherents of the competing visions of the good leave their particular conceptions behind in public discourse and justify the policies they endorse on grounds that are publicly accessible. He described this as the citizen's duty of civility ( Political Liberalism , iv).

The section of this entry on the continental school discussed briefly the topic of postmodernism. Within analytic philosophy the term is less prevalent. But both schools live in the same increasingly global cultural context. In this context we can reflect on the two main disqualifiers of the project of relating morality intimately to religion that seemed to emerge in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. The first disqualifier was the prestige of natural science, and the attempt to make it foundational for all human knowledge. The various empiricist, verificationist, and reductionist forms of foundationalism have not yet succeeded, and even within modern philosophy there has been a continuous resistance to them. This is not to say they will not succeed in the future (for example we may discover a foundation for ethics in the theory of evolution), but the confidence in their future success has waned. Moreover, the secularization hypothesis seems to have been false, as mentioned earlier. Certainly parts of Western Europe are less attached to traditional institutional forms of religion. But taking the world as a whole, religion seems to be increasing in influence rather than declining as the world's educational standards improve. The second main disqualifier was the liberal idea (present in the narrative of this entry from the time of the religious wars in Europe) that we need a moral discourse based on reason and not religion in order to avoid the hatred and bloodshed that religion seems to bring with it. Here the response to Rawls has been telling. It seems false that we can respect persons and at the same time tell them to leave their fundamental commitments behind in public discourse, and it seems false also that some purely rational but still action-guiding component can be separated off from these competing substantive conceptions of the good (see Wolterstorff, “An Engagement with Rorty”.) It is true that religious commitment can produce the deliberate targeting of civilians in a skyscraper. But the history of the twentieth century suggests that non-religious totalitarian regimes have at least as much blood on their hands. Perhaps the truth is, as Kant saw, that people under the Evil Maxim will use any available ideology for their purposes. Progress towards civility is more likely if Muslims, Christians, Jews, (and Buddhists and Hindus) are encouraged to enter ‘the public square’ with their commitments explicit, and see how much common ethical ground there in fact is. This writer has done some of this discussion, and found the common ground surprisingly extensive, though sometime common language disguises significant differences. Progress seems more likely in this way than by trying to construct a neutral philosophical ground that very few people actually accept.

One recent development in analytic ethical theory has been a revival of divine command theory parallel to the revival of natural law theory that I have already described. A pioneer in this revival was Philip Quinn's Divine Command and Moral Requirements (1978). He defended the theory against the usual objections (one, deriving from Plato's Euthyprho , that it makes morality arbitrary, and the second, deriving from a misunderstanding of Kant, that it is inconsistent with human autonomy), and proposed that we understand the relation between God and moral rightness causally, rather than analyzing the terms of moral obligation as meaning ‘commanded by God’. Though we could stipulate such a definition, it would make it obscure how theists and non-theists could have genuine moral discussion, as they certainly seem to do. Robert M. Adams, in a series of articles and then in Finite and Infinite Goods (1999), first separates off the good (which he analyzes Platonically in terms of imitating the ultimate good, which is God) and the right. He then defends a divine command theory of the right by arguing that obligation is always obligation to someone, and God is the most appropriate person, given human limitations. John Hare, In God and Morality (2007) and Divine Command (2015), defends a version of the theory that derives from God's sovereignty and defends the theory against the objection that obedience to divine command itself requires justification. He also compares Christian, Jewish and Muslim accounts of divine command. Thomas L. Carson's Value and the Good Life (2000) argues that normative theory needs to be based on an account of rationality, and then proposes that a divine-preference account of rationality is superior to all the available alternatives. An objection to divine command theory is mounted by Mark Murphy's An Essay on Divine Authority (2002) and God and Moral Law (2012) on the grounds that divine command only has authority over those persons that have submitted themselves to divine authority, but moral obligation has authority more broadly. William Wainwright's Religion and Morality defends the claim that divine command theory provides a more convincing account of moral obligation than any virtue-based theory, including Zagzebski's divine motivation theory, discussed earlier. Finally, C. Stephen Evans, in Kierkegaard's Ethics of Love : Divine Commands and Moral Obligations (2004) and God and Moral Obligation (2013) articulates both in Kierkegaard and in its own right a divine command theory that is argued to be superior to all the main alternative non-theist accounts of the nature and basis of moral obligation.

To conclude this entry, the revival of interest in divine command theory, when combined with the revival of natural law theory I already discussed, shows evidence that the attempt to connect morality closely to religion is undergoing a robust recovery within professional philosophy.

  • Adams, R. M., 1999, Finite and Infinite Goods , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Annas, Julia, The Morality of Happiness , Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993.
  • Anselm, S. Anselmi Cantuariensis Archiepiscopi Opera Omnia , Franciscus Salesius (ed.), Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Friedrich Fromann Verlag, 1968.
  • Aquinas, T., Summa Theologiae , English Dominicans (trans.), London: Burns, Oats, and Washbourne, 1912–36; repr. New York: Christian Classics, 1981.
  • Aristotle, The Complete Works of Aristotle , Jonathan Barnes (ed.), Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984.
  • –––, Nicomachean Ethics , Roger Crisp (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
  • Al-Ash'ari, The Theology of al-Ash'ari , trans. Richard J. McCarthy, Beyrouth: Imprimerie Catholique, 1953.
  • Augustine, The City of God , Robert Dyson (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
  • –––, Confessions , Henry Chadwick (trans.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991.
  • Austin, J., 1965, How to Do Things With Words , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Ayer, A. J., 1936, Language, Truth and Logic , London: Gollancz.
  • Bourke, V. J., 1968, History of Ethics , Garden City, NY: Doubleday.
  • Broadie, Sarah, Ethics with Aristotle , Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991.
  • Buber, Martin, I and Thou , trans. Walter Kaufmann, New York: Scribner's, 1970.
  • Butler, Joseph, Fifteen Sermons , Charlottesville: Ibis Publishing, 1987.
  • Calvin, John, Institutes of the Christian Religion , John T. McNeill (ed.), Ford Lewis Battles (trans.), 2 vols., Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1960.
  • Carson, T. L., 2000, Value and the Good Life , Notre Dame: Notre Dame Press.
  • Coplestone, F., 1985, A History of Philosophy , Garden City, NY: Image Books.
  • Crusius, Christian August, “A Guide to Rational Living,” Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to Kant , Vol. 2, J.B. Schneewind (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
  • Evans, C. S., 2004, Kierkegaard's Ethics of Love: Divine Command and Moral Obligations , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2013, God and Moral Obligation , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Feuerbach, L., The Essence of Christianity , George Eliot (trans.), Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books, 1989.
  • Finnis, J., 1980, Natural Law and Natural Rights , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Foot, Philippa, Natural Goodness , Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001.
  • Foucault, Michel, 1988, “Disciplinary Power and Subjection,” Power , Steven Lukes (ed.), New York: New York University Press.
  • –––, 1988, “Truth and Power,” Power , Steven Lukes (ed.), New York: New York University Press.
  • Habermas, J., 2010, An Awareness of What s Missing: Faith and Reason in a Post-Secular Age , trans. Ciaran Cronin, Malden, MA: Polity Press.
  • Hare, J., 2006, God and Morality A Philosophical History , Oxford: Blackwell.
  • –––, 1996, The Moral Gap , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • –––, 1985, Plato's Euthyphro , Bryn Mawr Commentaries, Bryn Mawr.
  • –––, 2015, Divine Command , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Hare, R. M., 1981, Moral Thinking , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • –––, 1992, “The Simple Believer,” Essays on Religion and Education , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Hegel, G. W. F., Phenomenology of Spirit , A. V. Miller (trans.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979.
  • –––, The Philosophy of History , C. J. Friedrich (ed.), New York: Dover Publications, 1956.
  • Heidegger, M., 1927, Being and Time , John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (trans.), New York: Harper and Row, 1962.
  • –––, Poetry, Language, Thought , Albert Hofstadter (trans.), New York: Harper & Row, 1971.
  • Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan , Richard Tuck (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, [1991] 1996.
  • Hourani, George, Islamic Rationalism : The Ethics of ‘Abd al-Jabbar , Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971.
  • Hume, David, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion , New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1947.
  • –––, Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals , L. A. Selby-Biggie (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975.
  • –––, A Treatise of Human Nature , L. A. Selby-Bigges (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978.
  • Hursthouse, Rosalind, 1999, On Virtue Ethics , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Hutcheson, F., Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions with Illustrations on the Moral Sense , A. Garrett (ed.), Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1991.
  • –––, Inquiry into the Originial of our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue: In Two Treatises , Wolfgang Leidhold (ed.), Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2004.
  • Irwin, T., 2007, The Development of Ethics , vol. 1, Oxford; Oxford University Press.
  • Kant, Immanuel, Critique of Practical Reason , Mary Gregor (ed. and trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
  • –––, Critique of Pure Reason , Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (eds. and trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
  • –––, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals , Mary Gregor (ed. and trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
  • –––, Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics , Gary Hatfield (ed. and trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
  • –––, Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason , in Religion and Rational Theology , Allen W. Wood and George di Giovanni (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
  • Kierkegaard, S., Samlede Voerker , A. B. Drachmann, J. L. Heiberg and H. O. Lange (eds.), Copenhagen: Gyldendal, 1901–06.
  • Leibniz, G. W., New Essays on Human Understanding , Peter Remnant and Jonathan Bennett (eds. and trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
  • Levinas, E., 1969, Totality and Infinity , trans. Alphonso Lingis, Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
  • –––, 1985, Ethics and Infinity , trans. Richard A. Cohen, Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
  • Locke, John, The Reasonableness of Christianity , I. T. Ramsey (ed.), Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1958.
  • –––, Two Treatises on Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration , Ian Shapiro (ed.), New Haven: Yale University Press, 2003.
  • Luther, Martin, The Bondage of the Will, in Martin Luther: Selections from his Writings , John Dillenberger (ed.), Garden City: Doubleday, 1961.
  • MacIntyre, A., 1988, Whose Justice, Which Rationality , London: Duckworth.
  • Maimonides, The Guide of the Perplexed , trans. Schlomo Pines, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1963.
  • Marx, Karl, “Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right,” Early Writings , Rodney Livingstone and Gregor Benton (trans.), London: Penguin Books, [1975] 1992.
  • –––, “Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts,” Early Writings , Rodney Livingstone and Gregor Benton (trans.), London: Penguin Books, [1975] 1992.
  • Mikalson, J., 1991, Honor Thy Gods , Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press.
  • Mill, J. S., Autobiography , Jack Stillinger (ed.), Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co., 1969.
  • –––, 1874, Three Essays on Religion , London: Henry Holt.
  • Moore, G. E., 1903, Principia Ethica , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Mouw, R., 1990, The God Who Commands , Notre Dame: Notre Dame Press.
  • Murphy, M., 2002, An Essay on Divine Authority , Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 2011, God and Moral Law : On the Theistic Explanation of Morality , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Nietzsche, Friedrich, The Gay Science , Walter Kaufman (trans.), New York: Vintage Books, 1974.
  • –––, On the Genealogy of Morals , Walter Kaufman (trans.), New York: Vintage Books, 1967.
  • Paley, W., 1830, The Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy , Cambridge: Hillard and Brown.
  • Plato, Collected Dialogues , Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns (eds.), Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1963.
  • –––, Republic , Robin Waterfield (trans.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993.
  • Porter, J., 1999, Natural and Divine Law , Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.
  • –––, 2005, Nature as Reason , Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.
  • Quinn, P., 1978, Divine Commands and Moral Requirements , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Rawls, J., 1993, Political Liberalism , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • –––, 1971, A Theory of Justice , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Rousseau, J.-J., The Social Contract and other Later Political Writings , Victor Gourevitch (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
  • Rudolph, Ulrich, Al-Maturidi and Sunni Theology in Samarkand , Leiden: Brill, 2014.
  • Russell, B., 1910, “The Elements of Ethics,” Philosophical Essays , New York: Longmans, Green.
  • Sartre, J.-P., 1957, Existentialism and Human Emotions , Secaucus: Citadel Press.
  • Schneewind, J., 1998, The Invention of Autonomy , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Schopenhauer, A., The World as Will and Representation , E. F. J. Payne (trans.), New York: Dover Publications, 1966.
  • Scotus, D., A Treatise on God as First Principle , Allan B. Wolter (ed. and trans.), Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, 1966.
  • –––, Duns Scotus on the Will and Morality , Allan B. Wolter (ed. and trans.), Washington DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 1986.
  • Sidgwick, H., Methods of Ethics , 7th edn, Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981.
  • Spinoza, B., Ethics , G. H. R. Parkinson (trans.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.
  • Stevenson, C., [1944] 1962, Ethics and Language , New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Suarez, Francisco, De Legibus , in Selections from Three Works of Francisco Suarez, S. J. , 2 vols., Oxford: Clarendon Press; and London: H. Milford, 1944.
  • Vasalou, Sophia, Moral Agents and Their Deserts: The Character of Mu'tazilite Ethics , Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008.
  • Voltaire, Letters of Voltaire and Frederick the Great , Richard Aldington (trans.), New York: Brentano's, 1927.
  • Wainwright, W., 2005, Religion and Morality , Aldershot: Ashgate.
  • Wittgenstein, L., [1953] 1960, Philosophical Investigations , G. E. M. Anscombe (trans.), New York: Macmillan.
  • –––, [1921] 1961, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Wolterstorff, N., 2003, “An Engagement with Rorty,” Journal of Religious Ethics , 31(1): 129–140.
  • Wolterstorff, N., 2008, Justice: Rights and Wrongs , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Zagzebski, L., 2004, Divine Motivation Theory , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

Aquinas, Thomas: moral, political, and legal philosophy | Aristotle, General Topics: ethics | Duns Scotus, John | ethics: natural law tradition | Holbach, Paul-Henri Thiry (Baron) d’ | Kant, Immanuel: and Hume on morality | Moore, George Edward: moral philosophy | morality, definition of | Nietzsche, Friedrich: moral and political philosophy | Plato: ethics | voluntarism, theological

Copyright © 2019 by John Hare

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Last updated 27/06/24: Online ordering is currently unavailable due to technical issues. We apologise for any delays responding to customers while we resolve this. For further updates please visit our website: https://www.cambridge.org/news-and-insights/technical-incident

We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings .

Login Alert

ethics in religion essay

  • < Back to search results
  • Ethics and Religion

Ethics and Religion

ethics in religion essay

  • Get access Buy a print copy Check if you have access via personal or institutional login Log in Register
  • Cited by 11

Crossref logo

This Book has been cited by the following publications. This list is generated based on data provided by Crossref .

  • Google Scholar
  • Harry J. Gensler , Loyola University, Chicago
  • Export citation
  • Buy a print copy

Book description

Many people question whether God is the source of morality. Under divine command theory, God's will creates the moral order, and therefore ethical truths are true because of God's will. Under natural law, on the other hand, some ethical truths do not depend on God's will, and yet perhaps they depend on his reason or creation. Ethics and Religion develops strong, defensible, and original versions of both divine command theory and natural law. The book also discusses ethics and atheism: how atheists object on ethical grounds to belief in God and how they view ethics. The book defends belief in God from criticisms and analyzes related concepts, such as practical reason, the golden rule, ethics and evolution, the problem of evil, and the fine-tuning argument.

'Harry J. Gensler has written an outstanding, critical and yet constructive work on the theological contribution to ethics. The book contains brilliant arguments that are developed with fairness, clarity, and precision. This is a must-read for anyone interested in ethical theory, value theory, or theology.'

Charles Taliaferro - St Olaf College, Minnesota

'Gensler has produced a novel and pragmatic piece of work on religion and ethics. He carefully combs though the various attempts that wed religion and ethics … for those who have commitments to Judeo-Christian ethics, other religious ethics, or to secular ethics, they will find Gensler’s treatment of ethics a much-needed ecumenical primer.'

Bernard Walker - Bethel University

  • Aa Reduce text
  • Aa Enlarge text

Refine List

Actions for selected content:.

  • View selected items
  • Save to my bookmarks
  • Export citations
  • Download PDF (zip)
  • Save to Kindle
  • Save to Dropbox
  • Save to Google Drive

Save content to

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to .

To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle .

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service .

Save Search

You can save your searches here and later view and run them again in "My saved searches".

Frontmatter pp i-iv

  • Get access Check if you have access via personal or institutional login Log in Register

Contents pp v-vi

Preface pp vii-viii, 1 - introduction pp 1-6, part i - ethics as god's commands pp 7-8, 2 - divine command theory pp 9-28, 3 - modified dct pp 29-54, part ii - ethics as natural laws pp 55-56, 4 - natural law and rationality pp 57-83, 5 - natural law and biology pp 84-111, 6 - natural law and spirituality pp 112-132, part iii - ethics and atheism pp 133-134, 7 - ethics without god pp 135-153, 8 - god, evil, and cosmic purpose pp 154-182, bibliography pp 183-190, index pp 191-196, altmetric attention score, full text views.

Full text views reflects the number of PDF downloads, PDFs sent to Google Drive, Dropbox and Kindle and HTML full text views for chapters in this book.

Book summary page views

Book summary views reflect the number of visits to the book and chapter landing pages.

* Views captured on Cambridge Core between #date#. This data will be updated every 24 hours.

Usage data cannot currently be displayed.

Encyclopedia Britannica

  • Games & Quizzes
  • History & Society
  • Science & Tech
  • Biographies
  • Animals & Nature
  • Geography & Travel
  • Arts & Culture
  • On This Day
  • One Good Fact
  • New Articles
  • Lifestyles & Social Issues
  • Philosophy & Religion
  • Politics, Law & Government
  • World History
  • Health & Medicine
  • Browse Biographies
  • Birds, Reptiles & Other Vertebrates
  • Bugs, Mollusks & Other Invertebrates
  • Environment
  • Fossils & Geologic Time
  • Entertainment & Pop Culture
  • Sports & Recreation
  • Visual Arts
  • Demystified
  • Image Galleries
  • Infographics
  • Top Questions
  • Britannica Kids
  • Saving Earth
  • Space Next 50
  • Student Center
  • Introduction & Top Questions

Introduction of moral codes

  • Problems of divine origin
  • Nonhuman behaviour
  • Kinship and reciprocity
  • Anthropology and ethics
  • The Middle East
  • Ancient Greece
  • The Epicureans
  • Ethics in the New Testament
  • St. Augustine
  • St. Thomas Aquinas and the Scholastics
  • Machiavelli
  • The first Protestants
  • Early intuitionists: Cudworth, More, and Clarke
  • Shaftesbury and the moral sense school
  • Butler on self-interest and conscience
  • The climax of moral sense theory: Hutcheson and Hume
  • The intuitionist response: Price and Reid
  • Moore and the naturalistic fallacy
  • Modern intuitionism
  • Existentialism
  • Universal prescriptivism
  • Moral realism
  • Kantian constructivism: a middle ground?
  • Irrealist views: projectivism and expressivism
  • Ethics and reasons for action
  • The debate over consequentialism
  • Varieties of consequentialism
  • Objections to consequentialism
  • An ethics of prima facie duties
  • Rawls’s theory of justice
  • Rights theories
  • Natural law ethics
  • Virtue ethics
  • Feminist ethics
  • Ethical egoism
  • Environmental ethics
  • War and peace
  • Abortion, euthanasia, and the value of human life

Code of Hammurabi

What is ethics?

How is ethics different from morality, why does ethics matter, is ethics a social science.

  • What did Aristotle do?

Aristotle (384-322 BC), Ancient Greek philosopher and scientist. One of the most influential philosophers in the history of Western thought, Aristotle established the foundations for the modern scientific method of enquiry. Statue

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

  • Business LibreTexts - What is Ethics?
  • Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Ethics and Contrastivism
  • Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Empathy and Sympathy in Ethics
  • VIVA Open Publishing - Ethics and Society - Ethical Behavior and Moral Values in Everyday Life
  • Philosophy Basics - Ethics
  • American Medical Association - Journal of Ethics - Triage and Ethics
  • Psychology Today - Ethics and Morality
  • Government of Canada - Treasury Board of Canada Secretariat - What is ethics?
  • Cornell Law School - Legal Information Institute - Ethics
  • ethics and morality - Student Encyclopedia (Ages 11 and up)
  • Table Of Contents

Code of Hammurabi

The term ethics may refer to the philosophical study of the concepts of moral right and wrong and moral good and bad, to any philosophical theory of what is morally right and wrong or morally good and bad, and to any system or code of moral rules, principles, or values. The last may be associated with particular religions , cultures, professions, or virtually any other group that is at least partly characterized by its moral outlook.

Traditionally, ethics referred to the philosophical study of morality, the latter being a more or less systematic set of beliefs, usually held in common by a group, about how people should live. Ethics also referred to particular philosophical theories of morality. Later the term was applied to particular (and narrower) moral codes or value systems. Ethics and morality are now used almost interchangeably in many contexts, but the name of the philosophical study remains ethics .

Ethics matters because (1) it is part of how many groups define themselves and thus part of the identity of their individual members, (2) other-regarding values in most ethical systems both reflect and foster close human relationships and mutual respect and trust, and (3) it could be “rational” for a self-interested person to be moral, because his or her self-interest is arguably best served in the long run by reciprocating the moral behaviour of others.

No. Understood as equivalent to morality, ethics could be studied as a social-psychological or historical phenomenon, but in that case it would be an object of social-scientific study, not a social science in itself. Understood as the philosophical study of moral concepts, ethics is a branch of philosophy , not of social science.

Trusted Britannica articles, summarized using artificial intelligence, to provide a quicker and simpler reading experience. This is a beta feature. Please verify important information in our full article.

This summary was created from our Britannica article using AI. Please verify important information in our full article.

ethics , the discipline concerned with what is morally good and bad and morally right and wrong. The term is also applied to any system or theory of moral values or principles.

(Read Britannica’s biography of this author, Peter Singer.)

How should we live? Shall we aim at happiness or at knowledge, virtue , or the creation of beautiful objects? If we choose happiness, will it be our own or the happiness of all? And what of the more particular questions that face us: is it right to be dishonest in a good cause? Can we justify living in opulence while elsewhere in the world people are starving? Is going to war justified in cases where it is likely that innocent people will be killed? Is it wrong to clone a human being or to destroy human embryos in medical research? What are our obligations, if any, to the generations of humans who will come after us and to the nonhuman animals with whom we share the planet?

Ethics deals with such questions at all levels. Its subject consists of the fundamental issues of practical decision making , and its major concerns include the nature of ultimate value and the standards by which human actions can be judged right or wrong .

The terms ethics and morality are closely related. It is now common to refer to ethical judgments or to ethical principles where it once would have been more accurate to speak of moral judgments or moral principles. These applications are an extension of the meaning of ethics. In earlier usage, the term referred not to morality itself but to the field of study, or branch of inquiry, that has morality as its subject matter. In this sense, ethics is equivalent to moral philosophy .

Although ethics has always been viewed as a branch of philosophy, its all-embracing practical nature links it with many other areas of study, including anthropology , biology , economics , history , politics , sociology , and theology . Yet, ethics remains distinct from such disciplines because it is not a matter of factual knowledge in the way that the sciences and other branches of inquiry are. Rather, it has to do with determining the nature of normative theories and applying these sets of principles to practical moral problems.

This article, then, will deal with ethics as a field of philosophy, especially as it has developed in the West. For coverage of religious conceptions of ethics and the ethical systems associated with world religions, see Buddhism ; Christianity ; Confucianism ; Hinduism ; Jainism ; Judaism ; Sikhism .

The origins of ethics

Mythical accounts.

When did ethics begin and how did it originate? If one has in mind ethics proper—i.e., the systematic study of what is morally right and wrong—it is clear that ethics could have come into existence only when human beings started to reflect on the best way to live. This reflective stage emerged long after human societies had developed some kind of morality, usually in the form of customary standards of right and wrong conduct . The process of reflection tended to arise from such customs, even if in the end it may have found them wanting. Accordingly, ethics began with the introduction of the first moral codes .

Virtually every human society has some form of myth to explain the origin of morality. In the Louvre in Paris there is a black Babylonian column with a relief showing the sun god Shamash presenting the code of laws to Hammurabi (died c. 1750 bce ), known as the Code of Hammurabi . The Hebrew Bible ( Old Testament ) account of God’s giving the Ten Commandments to Moses (flourished 14th–13th century bce ) on Mount Sinai might be considered another example. In the dialogue Protagoras by Plato (428/427–348/347 bce ), there is an avowedly mythical account of how Zeus took pity on the hapless humans, who were physically no match for the other beasts. To make up for these deficiencies, Zeus gave humans a moral sense and the capacity for law and justice , so that they could live in larger communities and cooperate with one another.

That morality should be invested with all the mystery and power of divine origin is not surprising. Nothing else could provide such strong reasons for accepting the moral law. By attributing a divine origin to morality, the priesthood became its interpreter and guardian and thereby secured for itself a power that it would not readily relinquish. This link between morality and religion has been so firmly forged that it is still sometimes asserted that there can be no morality without religion. According to this view, ethics is not an independent field of study but rather a branch of theology ( see moral theology ).

There is some difficulty, already known to Plato, with the view that morality was created by a divine power. In his dialogue Euthyphro , Plato considered the suggestion that it is divine approval that makes an action good . Plato pointed out that, if this were the case, one could not say that the gods approve of such actions because they are good. Why then do they approve of them? Is their approval entirely arbitrary? Plato considered this impossible and so held that there must be some standards of right or wrong that are independent of the likes and dislikes of the gods. Modern philosophers have generally accepted Plato’s argument, because the alternative implies that if, for example, the gods had happened to approve of torturing children and to disapprove of helping one’s neighbours, then torture would have been good and neighbourliness bad.

Relationship Between Ethics and Religion Essay

  • To find inspiration for your paper and overcome writer’s block
  • As a source of information (ensure proper referencing)
  • As a template for you assignment

Introduction

  • Relationship

Reference List

Is there a connection between religion and morality? This essay tries to explore the ongoing debate on this topic. Some argue that the two are inseparable, while others claim that morality (or ethics) can exist without religion. Statistics reveal that these suppositions are based on nothing else but the peoples’ understanding of the concepts.

This shows that the relationship between ethics and religion varies within a society. While a believer will pose that the two function as a couple, a non-believer, on the other hand, will hold that moral behavior is independent of faith. It is, therefore, deducible that what is morally right is not necessarily God’s command. It is sometimes from people, both atheists, and believers.

This page provides a relationship between religion and morality essay and a separate detailed study of the two.

Morality & Ethics

Morality in its simplest terms denotes a form of behaviour that controls peoples’ aims, decisions, as well as their doings. It helps in making a clear cut between what ought to be done, planned, or intended, and what ought not to. Morality varies based on cultural, religious, philosophical matters, among other matters. Each of these areas has its own structure of morals commonly referred to as the moral code. Some commonly abused terms on this subject are immorality and amorality.

While the former is the reverse of morality, the latter denotes scepticism of a particular moral law. Following the variability of morality with people, there exist no clear-cut difference between what is right and what is wrong. All these are people’s creations based on their morals. Therefore, it stands out that what a certain culture terms as good may be the other way round for another.

“Religion is the belief in and worship of a god or gods , or a set of beliefs concerning the origin and purpose of the universe. It is commonly regarded as consisting of a person’s relation to God or to gods or spirits” (Regnerus & Burdette 2006, 175-194). Religions vary in their ciphers and beliefs but all depict their relationship with their deities.

Each religion has a specific set of code, which is believed to originate from their god or gods. They all act, aim, or intend to, based on what is in the code. They use it as the source of their moral values as well as a basis of the kind of behaviour they ought to portray to the public and which they ought not to.

This signifies a relationship between morality and religion in that morality makes use of religion but not the other way round. This on the other hand does not deprive morality of its ability to stand-alone as the following paragraph clarifies. Since they just draw some and not all the religious codes and couple them with their moral values, which vary per people, it then stands out that what is morally right is not necessarily a command by God.

Relationship Between Religion and Morality

There is a debate on whether morality has anything to do with religion. Does morality rely entirely on religion or religion entirely on morality? The answer depends on how the two relate and will vary with people. Given a scenario where a person steals from another and probably punished as a result, people tend to first enquire about the religious status of the particular person.

This on the other hand signifies that, according to them, if the person is religiously upright, he/she cannot afford such an offence. What comes out of this is a claim that religion and morality are related but this is a common misconception. Morality in itself can or can fail to contain a mixture of both religious and other moral laws.

The culture, philosophy, or religion decides on whether to couple some religious morals with theirs or not. This makes it clear that there is a possibility of morality to stand alone even without religion.

The person’s background people and particularly the parents only determine the relationship between the two. Any parent ought to equip his/her child with a rough picture of what morality is. If he/she has a religious background then he/she will teach the child about religion. This is what virtually all parents do, hence relating morality and religion.

A group of people argues that there is entirely no affiliation between morals and religion. This is a common view of humanists and non-believers.

Muslims, Jews, and Christians on the other hand hold that morality and religion are inseparable. Plato came up with a theory entitled, ‘The Divine Command Theory’. This theory is a follow up of a question that triggers the minds of many. Will something become good because God has said so or is it that God has said so because it is good? Considering the instance of the atheists, they believe but not in the existence of God.

What they term as good or morally upright is not determined by religion. On the other hand, it is worthy noting that what they do is not always against those who believe in God. Most of their moral actions conform to those of the believers. This then drives home the claim that what is morally right is not always from God, picturing morality as independent of religion.

Philosophers, Plato inclusive, argue that religion relies on morality and not the reverse. This follows from the divine command theory. According to Jonathan Berg, “…a way to construe ethics as depending on religion would be on the basis of a ‘Divine Command Theory’ of ethics, identifying the moral good with God’s Will or with what God commands” (1).

Given the scenario of Abraham of the Bible whom God commands to offer his son as a sacrifice, though he is willing, that is not the case for the majority. If people receive this kind of a suggestion, it will not be a surprise that 100% will reject it regardless of its godly origin.

It is a religiously right because God is saying it but it must be related to the already laid down morals before it is declared right or wrong. This then shows how religion depends on morality. In addition, whatever is righteous is approved to people that it is accepted before God. This then implies that morals values remain accepted by God since they are excellent just like God, showing that what is religiously upright has to be morally upright and not the reverse.

The issue of morality and religion is no less than a broad subject. While the two may appear the same thing to some, to others it is the reverse. Following the variations of both morals with people, the relationship between the two is also subject to variations. Some people believe in God while others do not, yet all share virtues. Therefore, Morals do not necessarily come from God and thus it is worthy concluding that what is morally good is not always a command by God.

Jonathan, B. The Divine Command Theory. 2010. Web.

Regnerus, M. D., & Burdette, A. 2006. Religious Change and Adolescent Family Dynamics. The Sociological Quarterly 47 (1): 175–194.

  • Euthyphro Dilemma and Divine Command Theory
  • Convergence of Nursing Care With Spiritual Care
  • Religious Illiteracy and Related Challenges
  • The Basis of a Moral Judgement
  • Core Human Service Values with Reference to Moral Philosophy
  • The Connections between the MEAA Code of Ethics and Three Philosophical Traditions
  • Epictetus and Epicurus
  • Machiavelli and a Notion of Virtue as an Innovation
  • Chicago (A-D)
  • Chicago (N-B)

IvyPanda. (2019, February 7). Relationship Between Ethics and Religion Essay. https://ivypanda.com/essays/relationship-between-morality-and-religion/

"Relationship Between Ethics and Religion Essay." IvyPanda , 7 Feb. 2019, ivypanda.com/essays/relationship-between-morality-and-religion/.

IvyPanda . (2019) 'Relationship Between Ethics and Religion Essay'. 7 February.

IvyPanda . 2019. "Relationship Between Ethics and Religion Essay." February 7, 2019. https://ivypanda.com/essays/relationship-between-morality-and-religion/.

1. IvyPanda . "Relationship Between Ethics and Religion Essay." February 7, 2019. https://ivypanda.com/essays/relationship-between-morality-and-religion/.

Bibliography

IvyPanda . "Relationship Between Ethics and Religion Essay." February 7, 2019. https://ivypanda.com/essays/relationship-between-morality-and-religion/.

Home — Essay Samples — Religion — Religious Pluralism — The Relation of Ethics to Religion

test_template

The Relation of Ethics to Religion

  • Categories: Ethics Religious Beliefs Religious Pluralism

About this sample

close

Words: 990 |

Published: Oct 4, 2018

Words: 990 | Pages: 2 | 5 min read

Works Cited

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958). Modern moral philosophy. Philosophy, 33(124), 1-19.
  • Asbury, H. (2012). The anatomy of Abraham's test: Sacrifice as justice and sacrifice as mercy. Theology Today, 69(3), 231-239.
  • Bennett, D. W. (2017). The man who would be father of nations: Abraham in the political imagination of John Adams. Journal of Church and State, 59(1), 5-24.
  • Greenawalt, K. (2016). Incest and the ethics of sexual relationships. Philosophical Studies, 173(2), 519-542.
  • Harris, M. (2006). The rise of anthropological theory: A history of theories of culture. Rowman Altamira.
  • Hutson, M., Rubin, D. C., & May, J. (2014). Can meditation really slow aging? Cognitive and affective mechanisms mediate the effects of meditation practice on psychological well-being and physical health. Cognitive Therapy and Research, 38(1), 1-12.
  • Spurgeon, C. H. (1859). The preacher's power, and the conditions of obtaining it: A sermon. Passmore and Alabaster.
  • Wierenga, E. R. (1983). Divine command morality and the theological foundations of ethics. Faith and Philosophy, 2(2), 111-130.

Image of Dr. Charlotte Jacobson

Cite this Essay

Let us write you an essay from scratch

  • 450+ experts on 30 subjects ready to help
  • Custom essay delivered in as few as 3 hours

Get high-quality help

author

Dr. Heisenberg

Verified writer

  • Expert in: Philosophy Religion

writer

+ 120 experts online

By clicking “Check Writers’ Offers”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy . We’ll occasionally send you promo and account related email

No need to pay just yet!

Related Essays

5 pages / 2400 words

1 pages / 427 words

1 pages / 624 words

4 pages / 1709 words

Remember! This is just a sample.

You can get your custom paper by one of our expert writers.

121 writers online

The Relation of Ethics to Religion Essay

Still can’t find what you need?

Browse our vast selection of original essay samples, each expertly formatted and styled

Related Essays on Religious Pluralism

It is the duty of every cultured man or woman to respect others’ religions as we would have them respect our own, Christianity and Islam are similar faiths. They have many things in common, both in belief and practice, then they [...]

The principle of separation of church and state is a cornerstone of democratic societies, reflecting the delicate balance between religious freedom and government authority. This essay delves into the concept of separation of [...]

Religion has played a significant role in human society throughout history. The origins of religion date back thousands of years, and it continues to have a profound influence on societies around the world today. This essay will [...]

A Jesuit response to the prevailing climate of divisiveness, hate and intolerance. “Although we hail from different lands, we share one earth and sky and sun, remember friends the world is one.” this is an excerpt from the [...]

Billion years ago, there was an extra-ordinary event without which nothing would exist. It was the beginning of the universe. It was the time when a large amount of energy in an infinitely small space violently expanded and led [...]

“Love need not be a command nor faith a dictum. I am my own god. We are here to unlearn the teachings of the church, state, and our educational system. We are here to drink beer. We are here to kill war. We are here to laugh at [...]

Related Topics

By clicking “Send”, you agree to our Terms of service and Privacy statement . We will occasionally send you account related emails.

Where do you want us to send this sample?

By clicking “Continue”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy.

Be careful. This essay is not unique

This essay was donated by a student and is likely to have been used and submitted before

Download this Sample

Free samples may contain mistakes and not unique parts

Sorry, we could not paraphrase this essay. Our professional writers can rewrite it and get you a unique paper.

Please check your inbox.

We can write you a custom essay that will follow your exact instructions and meet the deadlines. Let's fix your grades together!

Get Your Personalized Essay in 3 Hours or Less!

We use cookies to personalyze your web-site experience. By continuing we’ll assume you board with our cookie policy .

  • Instructions Followed To The Letter
  • Deadlines Met At Every Stage
  • Unique And Plagiarism Free

ethics in religion essay

A Level Philosophy & Religious Studies

Situation Ethics

Introduction.

Situation ethics was created by Joseph Fletcher in the 1960s. It is a product of its time, and deliberately so. The 60s were defined by radical social movements aimed at overthrowing traditional ways of life which were seen as oppressive. Religion faces a dilemma in the face of such modernising forces; whether to adapt and reform itself or attempt to carry on as if nothing had changed. Fletcher is a classic example of adaptation. His approach embodies liberal Christianity in many ways. He rejected the traditional approach to Christian ethics of strict adherence to moral laws. Instead he attempted a reduction of Christian ethics to what many would agree is the overarching theme of Jesus’ ethics: love.

Legalism, situation ethics & antinomianism

Legalism is the view that people require fixed rules to follow. Antinomianism is the view that there are no rules or laws to follow at all. Fletcher claimed that his situation ethics was a middle ground which avoids the problems of each extreme while retaining the benefit of each. The downside of legalism is that it cannot take the situation into account, the downside of antinomianism is that it leads to moral chaos. The upside of legalism is that it has clear guidance for people to follow, the upside of antinomianism is that it takes the situation into account. Situation ethics takes the situation into account, give people clear guidance and avoids moral chaos. It does this by claiming that love is the one single absolute principle which should be applied to all situations. The action that is good is the one which has the most loving consequence in the situation you are in.  

The importance of Agape in Christianity is drawn from Jesus saying that the ‘greatest commandment’ is to ‘love your neighbour as yourself’. Fletcher interprets that as suggesting all other religious rules, principles and commandments only have value insofar as they enable Agape. For example, the 10 commandments clearly state that murder is wrong. However, Fletcher gives the example of a family hiding from bandits when their baby started crying, which would reveal their hiding place. Fletcher said it’s the most loving thing to kill the baby because the situation was that they would otherwise all die anyway, including the baby.

The four working principles

The four working principles are involved in the application of the guiding principle of agape to moral situations.

Pragmatism. An action must be calibrated to the reality of the situation.

Relativism . Fletcher claimed his theory “relativizes the absolute, it does not absolutize the relative”.  Relativizing the absolute means that absolutes like “Do not kill” become relative to love. If it has a loving outcome to kill, such as euthanasia sometimes can, then that absolute is false relative to love. Not absolutizing the relative means that it is not total relativism where any moral claim could be justified. It is always relative to love which means that only moral claims which are valid when relative to love will be justified for Fletcher.

Positivism. Natural law and Kantian ethics are based on reason but Fletcher thought ethics had to begin with faith in love because Fletcher thought no rational answer can be given for why someone should love as it is a matter of faith in Jesus’ command to love your neighbour as yourself.

Personalism. Situation ethics puts people above rules. As Jesus said “The Sabbath was made for man, not man for the Sabbath”. Fletcher claims this shows that Jesus knew rules could be broken if it was for the good of humanity to do so.

The six fundamental principles

The six fundamental principles/propositions are axioms which follow from agape being at the centre of ethics.

Only love is intrinsically good. Everything else has conditional value depending on whether it helps or hurts people, but love is always unconditionally and therefore intrinsically good.

The ruling norm of Christian decision is love; nothing else.

Love and justice are the same, for justice is love distributed, nothing else.  Fletcher think that maximising agape is the only ethical goal. Many think that justiice is an ethical goal, so Fletcher here is explaining that justice actually reduces to love, it is merely the question of how widely and fairly love is distributed.

Love wills the neighbour’s good whether we like him or not. Jesus called on us to love our neighbour no matter who they are, which includes people we don’t like.

Only the end justifies the means; nothing else. The is Fletcher’s consequentialism. If the consequence of an action is the most loving possible then it is good, it doesn’t matter what the action is. The end of maximising agape justifies the means we use to produce it.

Love decides there and then. When we are faced with a moral choice we have to decide there and then in that situation what the right thing to do is.

Fletcher’s views on conscience

Fletcher thought that the conscience was what enabled you to figure out the requirements of agape in your situation. He said conscience was a verb not a noun, indicating he disagreed with the traditional view that conscience is an internal moral compass or mental ability to intuitively know what is right or wrong.

Whether situation ethics grants people too much freedom

Strength of situation ethics:  Situation ethics is designed for modern society. Fletcher and Robinson argue (influenced by Bonhoeffer) that humanity has ‘come of age’, meaning become more mature. In medieval and ancient times, people in general were less educated and less self-controlling. This meant that they needed fixed ridged clear rules to follow, because they could not be trusted to understand and act on the nuances and complexities in how a rule could justifiably be bent or broken if the situation called for it. However, now people are more civilised, to the point that granting them more autonomy will increase love without risking the stability of society.

Weakness: William Barclay disagreed. He argues that situation ethics gives moral agents a dangerous amount of freedom. For freedom to be good, love has to be perfect. If there is no or not enough love then ‘freedom can become selfishness and even cruelty’. If everyone was a saint, then situation ethics would be perfect. Barclay argues mankind has not yet come of age and so ‘still needs the crutch and protection of law’.

Final judgement defending Situation ethics:

Barclay’s argument fails because legalism has worse downsides. It may be true that some would abuse the autonomy situation ethics grants them. However, that is arguably not as bad compared with the dangers of legalistic morality, which is inflexible and outdated. Furthermore, the direction of history involves people becoming more educated and civilised and so it makes sense for Fletcher to develop a morality which reflects the fact that people can be trusted with more freedom.

Final judgement critiquing Situation ethics:

Barclay’s argument is successful because although people might appear improved in modern times, if granted the freedom (and thus power) to do what they want, they won’t choose the loving thing they will choose the selfish or even the cruel thing. This is essentially the classic argument that power corrupts. It also echoes the debate about the extent to which human nature is corrupt, such as by original sin. Also relevant is psychology like the Stanford prison experiment and literature like lord of the flies. It is a well-known feature of human psychology that power is corrupting. The freedom to decide what is good or bad without external supervision of legalistic laws grants humans more power and thereby corrupts them.

Fletcher vs sola scriptura

One of the strengths of situation ethics is that Fletcher founded it on a liberal approach to the Bible. He argued that traditional legalistic approaches to the bible face a dilemma. They could take the Bible literally, but no one ever can or wants to live that way. Fletcher points to the example of ‘do not resist an evil person’. They could interpret the Bible, but it is impossible to know which interpretation is correct, e.g. of the sermon on the mount.

Fletcher concludes that the Bible should not be thought of as a legalistic ‘rules book’. Ethical teachings like the sermon on the mount at most offer us ‘some paradigms or suggestions’. This makes Fletcher’s approach to the Bible an example of the liberal view of inspiration; that the Bible is not the perfect word of God. So, although the Bible states that many things (e.g. killing, homosexuality and adultery) are wrong, Fletcher doesn’t think a Christian should view those as unbreakable rules. Whatever maximises agape is allowed, no matter the action. This is part of Fletcher’s argument against legalism.

Fletcher focuses on the most prevalent ethical theme of the Bible – love. This is the approach of many liberal Christians. When you boil it down, the Bible, especially the teachings of Jesus and ethics of St Paul, are mainly focused on love and things which follow from love like forgiveness.

Weakness: Although love is central, it is not the only element of Biblical Christian ethics. Fletcher faces the criticism that his theory cannot be considered properly Christian, since it seems to only follow the command to love, ignoring most of the teachings in the Bible. Martin Luther’s theory of ‘sola scriptura’ argues that the ‘Bible alone’ is the source of moral authority, not the autonomous individual deciding the demands of agape in their situation. Sola scriptura protestant W. L. Craig argues that the Bible shows that God’s Justice is just as important as his love.

Fletcher has diluted Christian ethics into just loving and wanting the best for others. That is not distinctive from secular morality or just general well-wishing.

Final judgement defending situation ethics:

Craig could be right that God’s justice is equally important to love, or perhaps Fletcher is still right that justice is just love distributed.

This simply further proves Fletcher’s point about the impossibility of figuring out exactly what the Bible meant. So, should not view it as the perfect word of God but only as guidelines. Fletcher thus simply doesn’t regard it as a problem that he ignores, or thinks it justified to overrule with agape, most of the commands in the Bible.

Final judgement critiquing situation ethics:

Fletcher’s liberal approach to the bible is no better off than the approach of trying to interpret it. The themes and paradigms of the bible are also a matter of subjective interpretation.

Fletcher has not solved the problem of how to interpret the Bible, he has merely kicked the can down the road.

Situation ethics therefore fails to provide a convincing approach to Christian ethics and ends up sliding into antinomianism due to being subjective.

Whether situation ethics truly represents the ethics of Jesus

A strength of Fletcher’s situation ethics is that it fits with the approach to ethics taken by Jesus. Jesus overturned rules (like that of Moses’ eye for an eye & life for a life), allowed the breaking of rules (like the sabbath) and said that the greatest commandment was to love your neighbours as yourself.

If one command is greater than another, then it seems like that means it takes priority and thus the lesser rule should be broken if it’s the loving thing to do. Fletcher’s situation ethics is a reasonable interpretation of what Jesus said. It’s hard to see what Jesus could have meant by agape being the greatest commandment except that it was greater than the others which seem to imply taking precedence over them.

Weakness: Richard Mouw points out that it makes no sense to reduce Christian ethics to only one of Jesus’ commands when Jesus made other commands too. It makes no logical sense to follow some of Jesus’ commands but not all of them. We either regard him as a source of moral authority or we don’t.   Pope Pius XII criticised situation ethics on similar grounds. Christ himself frequently spoke of the importance of following all the commandments. (Matthew 19:17 & John 14:15).  Fletcher is therefore unwittingly attacking Christ. Fletcher claims the ends justifies the means, but Romans 3:8 condemns that.

Mouw and Pius XII’s arguments are unsuccessful because they beg the question regarding the validity of taking a legalistic approach.

Certainly if we take all of Jesus’ commands as individually true, it is incoherent to only follow one of them. Fletcher’s point however is that the example of Jesus himself goes against that legalistic method of ethical accounting. Jesus himself was an example of taking a progressive and situationist approach to ethical commands. Reading and following Jesus like an inflexible legalist fails to incorporate that side of his approach. A full appreciation of Jesus’ ethics involves both legalism and situationism. In that case, it cannot be viewed legalistically. Fletcher does not want to disregard rules and commandments, only the insistence on the legalistic approach to their application.

Furthermore, would Jesus have bothered to make any other commandments if agape is the only one that is ultimately matters? If a commandment is only to be followed when it accords with agape, and should be ignored if it conflicts with agape, then agape is the only commandment you actually need.

It seems more logical to think that by calling it the ‘greatest’ commandment Jesus meant something else, such as only that it was the one which would be relevant to the most number of situations.

The subjectivity issue  

Love seems like a strong basis for ethics. Fletcher doesn’t mean simply acting based on the feeling of love. He means doing whatever action actually promotes a loving outcome. Ethical action on his theory has the strength of being orientated towards love but without the weakness of unreliable emotion.   Furthermore, agape is an even stronger basis than love. Agape doesn’t just mean love, it means Christian love, more specifically it means selfless love. It means the kind of love that Jesus recommended when he said we should love our neighbour as ourselves.   Some argue that love is subjective and therefore too unstable a basis for ethics. The Auschwitz guard might think they are doing a loving thing, for example. However, the Nazi does not love their neighbour (jews) the same way as they love themselves. Fletcher’s theory can’t be said to justify their action. A Nazi might think they act out of love, but it is not Christian self-less love of the neighbour.

Weakness: The subjectivity of agape.  Agape is defined as loving your neighbour as yourself. This is less subjective than love, because it requires symmetry in the way you love others and yourself. You can’t just go loving anyone in limitless ways, it has to be the way you love yourself, so it’s less subjective.

However, C. Hitchens pointed out that loving your neighbour as yourself is only as good if the way you love yourself is good. Furthermore, others might not want to be loved in the way you love yourself. The point we can take from Hitchens to critique situation ethics is: the way a person loves themselves is still subjective and therefore so is agape.

Two Nazis might say to each other that they hope the other would kill them if it were discovered they were Jewish, because they would rather be dead than Jewish so that is genuinely what they view as loving themselves. In that case, loving your neighbour as yourself for a Nazi would involve killing your neighbour if they were Jewish. A Viking or spartan warrior might become envious of those they kill in battle, since for them a glorious death is the highest honour. Killing people in battle would in such cases be seen as loving your neighbour as you would want to be loved.

However, this criticism is unsuccessful because it misunderstands agape.

Agape is not merely treating your neighbour as you would like to be treated, it is loving your neighbour as you love yourself.

Nazis and Viking warriors were not really gripped by self-love when creating and accepting their ethical judgements. They may have treated others as they would want to be treated, but they did not love others as they loved themselves. Perhaps they didn’t love themselves at all.

This criticism is successful because it shows that Fletcher’s abandonment of strict laws

Fletcher has diluted Christian ethics into just doing what a person subjectively perceives to be loving, which is not distinctive from secular morality or just general well-wishing. His theory is sliding into antinomianism.   

Whether situation ethics leads to antinomianism

Strength of situation ethics: situation ethics is perpetually relevant due to its flexibility in taking the situation into account.

Fletcher’s approach to conscience also enables this flexibility. It doesn’t reveal strict rules or precepts but is simply the way that an individual figures out what has a loving outcome in their situation.

This allows Christian ethics to adapt to the new ethical situations and issues associated with modern society and technology.

Weakness: Natural law based Catholic argument: relativism leads to antinomianism. Pope Pius XII accepts there is some truth in ethics depending on the situation. However, he argued that Aquinas’ Natural law approach to conscience already sufficiently does that job. Aquinas claimed prudence was a cardinal virtue. The primary precepts are not rules, they are applied to particular situations. It could even be justified to do an action normally considered sinful if the double effect justifies it. However, that is the limit of flexibility. Fletcher goes too far.

Catholics believe in ethical absolutes such as the sanctity of life. No matter what the pragmatic situation is, the value of life cannot be relativized. Fletcher’s working principles of pragmatism and relativism are wrong. The stability of society is threatened by relativistic ethical theories like Fletcher’s. Mother Theresa summed up this kind of argument well during her speech upon receiving the noble peace prize:

“the greatest destroyer of peace today is [abortion]. If a mother can kill her own child in her womb, what is left for you and me to kill each other?” – Mother Theresa.

The social order argument doesn’t seem to be true. Northern Europe has the most atheistic countries where quality of life is acted on instead of sanctity of life. Those countries are nonetheless some of the most stable and happy in the world. So, it just doesn’t look like it’s true that strict ethical principles like the sanctity of life is a requirement for social order. So, Fletcher’s situationism doesn’t lead to antinomianism.

This Catholic argument is successful because it is logical that if a culture devalues life than that could threaten social stability.

God designed us to live a certain way which involves preserving human life. If we go against that then our society will break down because living contrary to God’s design is unnatural and leads to immorality and social disorder. Moralities which focus on individual autonomy at the expense of social norms might seem to make sense in particular situations but are ultimately bad for society which needs clear fixed rules. Fletcher’s overly individualistic situationism thus leads to antinomianism.

Quick links

  • Share full article

Advertisement

Supported by

Pamela Paul

Your Religious Values Are Not American Values

A photo illustration of a religious icon wearing a U.S. flag as a shirt.

By Pamela Paul

Opinion Columnist

Whenever a politician cites “ Judeo-Christian values ,” I find it’s generally followed by something unsettling.

Last month brought two flagrant instances. In both cases, Republican officials introduced state laws that formalize precepts of the Christian nationalist movement — in the words of the National Association of Christian Lawmakers (A.D. 2019), “doing everything we can to restore the Judeo-Christian foundation of our nation.”

On June 19, Gov. Jeff Landry of Louisiana signed legislation requiring public classrooms to display the Ten Commandments, a practice struck down as unconstitutional by the Supreme Court in 1980. A rich endorsement came via Donald Trump, who crowed , “I LOVE THE TEN COMMANDMENTS IN PUBLIC SCHOOLS, PRIVATE SCHOOLS, AND MANY OTHER PLACES, FOR THAT MATTER. READ IT — HOW CAN WE, AS A NATION, GO WRONG???”

One week later, Landry’s fellow Christian soldier Ryan Walters, Oklahoma’s superintendent of public instruction, announced plans to mandate teaching the Bible in public schools. Walters said learning the Bible is necessary to having “an understanding of the basis of our legal system.”

Forgive me for wondering: Is he referring to “ an eye for an eye ” or the stoning of disobedient children ?

Either way, for both Trump and true believers, it hardly matters that the First Amendment was intended to protect religion from the state, not to have the state impose a religion. (So much for originalism.) Their goal is to impose one form of religion , Christianity, and the underlying message is that those who do not share it will have to submit.

We are having trouble retrieving the article content.

Please enable JavaScript in your browser settings.

Thank you for your patience while we verify access. If you are in Reader mode please exit and  log into  your Times account, or  subscribe  for all of The Times.

Thank you for your patience while we verify access.

Already a subscriber?  Log in .

Want all of The Times?  Subscribe .

  • DOI: 10.1145/3656156.3665124
  • Corpus ID: 270846468

Felt Ethics: Reimagining Ethics in Human-Technology Relations

  • Rachael Garrett
  • Published in Conference on Designing… 1 July 2024
  • Philosophy, Computer Science
  • Companion Publication of the 2024 ACM Designing Interactive Systems Conference

40 References

Felt ethics: cultivating ethical sensibility in design practice.

  • Highly Influential

Articulating Mechanical Sympathy for Somaesthetic Human-Machine Relations

How to train your drone: exploring the umwelt as a design metaphor for human-drone interaction, five provocations for a more creative tas, design justice: community-led practices to build the worlds we need, vulnerability as an ethical stance in soma design processes, unpacking non-dualistic design: the soma design case, things we could design: for more than human-centered worlds, counterfactual thinking: what theories do in design, designing drone chi: unpacking the thinking and making of somaesthetic human-drone interaction, related papers.

Showing 1 through 3 of 0 Related Papers

Jump to navigation


Religious Encounters: Tradition, Text, and Travel (Edited Volume, proposed to be published by Bloomsbury)

Title: Religious Encounters: Text, Travel, and Tradition

As Michael Pasquier rightly suggests, the concept of 'religion' is relatively modern, emerging predominantly through political and scientific innovations. However, this does not imply that notions of the 'sacred' or 'spiritual' were absent in earlier times. From the dawn of human existence, individuals have sought to create meaning around themselves and their place in the world. This quest to explain the origin of life and the universe has led to the creation of sacred histories, narratives, oral mythological traditions, texts, symbols, and sites.

Travel—whether physical, astral, or spiritual—has often been a central theme in human religious and spiritual encounters. Astral and spiritual travel have found expression in various forms and genres of literature. Meanwhile, physical journeys undertaken by significant figures, such as the Exodus in Judaism, the Hijra in Islam, the Udasian journeys in Sikhism, and the travels of Buddha, have established sacred and religious sites. The journeys to these sites have given rise to a vast literature of pilgrimage. While pilgrimage has been extensively analysed as travel writing, the value of interactions and intersections that occur due to the  other forms of travel, such as sightseeing, cultural tourism, secular pilgrimage and grey tourism, to religious sites remains understudied.

This edited volume, titled "Religious Encounters: Text, Travel, and Tradition," seeks to provide a comprehensive and multidisciplinary examination of how religious encounters shape, and are shaped by, textual narratives, travel experiences, and traditions. It focuses on the dynamic interaction between sacred texts, transformative travel experiences, and the preservation of cultural traditions. The volume aims to provide a nuanced understanding of the complex relationships that unfold in the realm of religious diversity. It intends to explore religious journeys as sites of encounters where identities are constructed, deconstructed, and reconstructed. The objective is to examine not only pilgrimages but also various other settings where religious interactions occur, such as places of worship, community gatherings, personal reflections, and ethnographic studies.

Call for Papers: We invite scholars to contribute to this volume, which will be proposed to Bloomsbury Publishing, by submitting papers that explore the following themes:

  • Sacred Texts and Travel:
  • How do sacred texts influence religious journeys?
  • The role of pilgrimage in the interpretation and dissemination of sacred texts.
  • Transformative Travel Experiences:
  • Personal narratives of religious journeys.
  • The impact of travel on individual and collective religious identities.
  • Preservation and Transformation of Traditions:
  • The role of travel in preserving and transforming religious traditions.
  • Case studies of religious sites as cultural heritage.
  • Religious Encounters Beyond Pilgrimage:
  • Interactions in places of worship and community gatherings.
  • Personal reflections and ethnographic studies on religious experiences.
  • Diverse Motivations for Religious Travel:
  • Revisiting historical and cultural sites.
  • Religious journalism and its impact on public perception of religious sites.
  • Verification of cultural beliefs and identities through travel.

If you are interested in contributing, please submit an abstract of 300 words and a 200-word biographical note addressed to Kiranpreet Kaur Baath ( [email protected] ).

Call for abstracts (deadline): 31 July 2024 

Notification of acceptance : 30 August 2024

The final submission will be in the form of a chapter of 6,000 to 8,000 words, including references.

Trinity College Dublin, the University of Dublin

School of Religion, Theology, and Peace Studies

View the contact page for more contact and location information

  • News and Events

Fully funded PhD opportunity in the ethics of palliative care

 height=

  • How are patients’ preferences for and choices about care influenced by their family caregiver(s)?
  • How do healthcare professionals decide about the management of patient symptoms including patient distress?
  • How does the legislative framework ‘Assisted Decision-Making (Capacity) Act’ in Ireland impact on patient autonomy and shared decision-making?
  • What are key ethical considerations for patients, their family caregivers, and healthcare professionals in shared decision-making for patient treatment and care?

PhD in the Ethics of Palliative Care: This PhD project is focused on ethical dimensions of shared decision-making for patients with advanced illness, family caregivers, and healthcare professionals in palliative care. The study will compare the patient, family caregiver, and healthcare professional perspective and decipher how their perspectives impact on how they approach decision-making about treatment and care. This PhD study aligns best with applicants from one or more of the following backgrounds: medical ethics; ethics; social sciences; health research; or cognate fields. This PhD will involve primarily qualitative methods. 

For direct inquiries about the specifics of this study, please contact Professor Linda Hogan, email: [email protected] and Dr Geraldine Foley, email: [email protected]. Further details can be found here .

A man with red hair raises his hand as racialized people are photographed from behind raising their hands.

Canada at a crossroads: Understanding the shifting sands of immigration attitudes

ethics in religion essay

Associate Professor of Economics, School of Public Policy and Urban Studies Program, Simon Fraser University

Disclosure statement

Mohsen Javdani does not work for, consult, own shares in or receive funding from any company or organisation that would benefit from this article, and has disclosed no relevant affiliations beyond their academic appointment.

Simon Fraser University provides funding as a member of The Conversation CA.

Simon Fraser University provides funding as a member of The Conversation CA-FR.

View all partners

Canada stands at a crossroads as its 157th birthday approaches. It’s navigating shifting immigration attitudes amid global and domestic challenges.

The ongoing politicization and polarization around immigration in Canada underscores a critical juncture for a country celebrated for its diversity . As Canadians grapple with economic insecurity, housing crises, health-care shortages and social tensions, the immigration debate tests the nation’s values and future direction.

Recent research I conducted with two colleagues , drawing from more than three decades of data, sheds light on evolving Canadian attitudes toward immigration. Between 1988 and 2008, there was a notable 41 per cent decline in Canadians who favoured reducing immigration numbers. Yet, post-2008, this trend shifted, with Canadians who wanted reduced immigration levels rising to 40 per cent by 2019.

Changes in attitudes toward immigration in Canada, 1988 to 2019

This development signals more than just changing preferences; there are deeper socio-psychological and political dynamics shaping views on immigration.

Judgments on who merits inclusion

But let’s simplify that socio-psychological jargon. Imagine society as a bustling potluck gathering. You arrive with your dish — packed with your beliefs, values and biases. Looking around, you’re judging everyone’s contributions and figuring out where you fit in.

Social identity theory suggests it’s natural to categorize ourselves into “us” versus “them” using familiar facets of our identity, such as religion and ethnicity. Driven by our need for a positive self-image and convinced that what we have to offer is the best, we sometimes snub outsiders.

This dynamic suggests the immigration debate delves into deeper territories of social identity. It’s about who we believe merits inclusion in our society, not just as an economic question.

Our findings suggest that economic concerns often cited in the immigration debate are just the tip of the iceberg. Beneath the surface, Canadians’ opinions on immigration are deeply influenced by aspects like religion, ethnicity, personal and familial immigration history and political leanings.

Our research finds, for example, that Christians show the least support for immigration. In contrast, Muslims — the second-largest religious group in Canada after Christians — are the most supportive of immigration. Jewish Canadians, atheists and agnostics also show strong support.

Ethnicity and immigration history also play pivotal roles in shaping our social identity. Our research indicates white people born in Canada exhibit a significantly stronger preference towards decreased immigration compared to white immigrants and ethnic minorities.

In terms of geography, it found that Nova Scotians have the most favourable sentiments about immigration, whereas Alberta and Ontario exhibit the most negative sentiments in Canada.

This suggests a varying landscape of belonging and acceptance. Immigrants and ethnic minorities show greater openness to new immigration, likely mirroring their journeys of settling and integrating into Canadian society.

Women wearing hijabs walk together in a city setting.

The politics of immigration

One of our most striking findings is the increasing political polarization over immigration. Our research has found that since 2006, political party identification has emerged as the foremost factor in explaining Canadians’ differing views on immigration.

This polarization highlights that immigration is not just a social issue, but also a political tool. It is often framed and politicized seemingly to galvanize party bases rather than address the complexities of immigration and integration.

Political parties link immigration to pressures on public finances or housing shortages during difficult periods. This amplifies anti-immigration sentiments, even if there’s no direct causation. This tactic also elevates immigration as a focal issue, intertwining it with prevailing concerns and magnifying its perceived negative impact on society.

Read more: International students are not to blame for Canada's housing crisis

Our study underscores the complexity of the debate. It’s not just about numbers or economics, but about deeper socio-psychological currents and political strategies.

So, what’s the takeaway for Canada? Firstly, our findings are a wakeup call for political leaders, policymakers and the wider community. The rise in negative sentiments about immigration, especially amid challenging conditions, could have far-reaching consequences for Canada’s social harmony and economic prosperity.

Addressing anti-immigration sentiments requires engaging deeply with the socio-psychological factors that mounting evidence suggests are critical. Education is key, as studies consistently show.

People carry a banner that reads Reject Migration with the Peace Tower behind them.

Effective response

Our vision of education, however, extends beyond traditional classrooms and involves the gradual development of an appreciation for diverse perspectives, openness and tolerance for change and diversity.

The significance of media and political parties in shaping public opinions cannot be overlooked. The way immigration is politicized through narratives of national security, economic risks and cultural identity influences both policy decisions and the public’s understanding of these policies. That means this conversation is as much a political issue as a policy challenge.

An effective response requires a holistic strategy that integrates policy initiatives with efforts to shift political and societal narratives toward more inclusive and accurate representations of immigration and its myriad contributions to society.

Our reaction to immigration should elevate above the narrow, self-serving question of “what’s in it for us?” This perspective narrowly views immigrants as mere economic assets, neglecting their wide-ranging contributions to society.

This viewpoint becomes particularly problematic when acknowledging that the lands currently known as Canada were first inhabited by Indigenous Peoples. As non-Indigenous people living in Canada, we all share the status of settlers, inheriting a responsibility from our colonial past. This history obliges us to extend a welcome embodying generosity and respect while looking toward our collective future.

  • Immigration
  • Housing crisis
  • Political polarization
  • Anti-immigration attitudes
  • Canadian immigration

ethics in religion essay

Sydney Horizon Educators – Faculty of Engineering (Targeted)

ethics in religion essay

Dean, Faculty of Education

ethics in religion essay

Lecturer in Indigenous Health (Identified)

ethics in religion essay

Social Media Producer

ethics in religion essay

PhD Scholarship

Faced with the threat of a second Trump presidency, America must have a better alternative than Biden

Brendon O’Connor

ethics in religion essay

  • X (formerly Twitter)

One of the greatest threats to the health of liberal democracies at present is the rampant spread of lies and disinformation by powerful and influential people and organisations. We live in a world where lies about global warming, election results, refugees, vaccines, and many other issues of public importance circulate with alarming ease. As a result, the most urgent challenges we face are not being seriously addressed, and vital public institutions — like our electoral systems — are being undermined.

Conversations in which accurate information is discussed and debated are the lifeblood of healthy democracies, whereas the dominance of disinformation is a sign of a slide into authoritarianism — perhaps even fascism.

Donald Trump is among the worst offenders in the war on truth. Much of what the former president says is either false or altogether fanciful. The lies he tells are often so blatant that it hardly takes a great thinker or skilful debater to expose them. But exposed they must be, not blithely accepted as the price of doing democratic business with a character like Trump. Unless self-serving propaganda and claims of  “alternative facts” are confronted with vigilance and seriousness, democracy’s very future is imperilled.

Democracy on the ballot … and in the balance

The inability of President Joe Biden to call out and confront Trump’s lies during  last week’s presidential debate was perhaps the most egregious aspect of what was already an historically bad performance. This failure was unforgivable in the context of an election that Biden himself has billed as likely to determine the future of democracy in the United States. As he put it in a speech to mark  the third anniversary of the attack on the Capitol : “as we begin this election year, we must be clear: Democracy is on the ballot.”

But rather than calling out Trump’s brazen falsehoods, Biden struggled to complete his own thoughts and fashion them into something that resembled a coherent sentence. He seemed to possess neither the confidence nor the mental agility to rebut Trump and mount a persuasive alternative.

There are two moments during the debate that stood out. The first came when Biden tried to answer to a question on how he would address national deficit:

We’d be able to right — wipe out his debt. We’d be able to help make sure that — all those things we need to do, childcare, elder care, making sure that we continue to strengthen our healthcare system, making sure that we’re able to make every single solitary person eligible for what I’ve been able to do with the COVID – excuse me, with dealing with everything we have to do with — uh — look — if — we finally beat Medicare.

Then, when Trump claimed that Democrats support taking “the life of a child in the eighth month, the ninth month, and even after birth”, Biden could only manage this garbled response:

Look, there’s so many young women who have been — including a young woman who just was murdered and he went to the funeral. The idea that she was murdered by — by — by an immigrant coming in and [inaudible] talk about that. But here’s the deal, there’s a lot of young women who are being raped by their — by their in-laws, by their — by their spouses, brothers and sisters, by — just — it’s just — it’s just ridiculous. And they can do nothing about it.

Given both the gravity of the situation involving women’s reproductive rights after the Supreme Court overturned Roe v. Wade , and Trump’s campaign speeches promising there will be  mass deportations of illegal immigrants and the establishment of detention camps , Biden needed to do a lot better.

At another of the debate’s low points — one which has not received anywhere near enough attention in the media coverage — Trump asserted that Biden should let the Israeli government go and “finish the job” in Gaza. How can this be construed other than as a brazen endorsement of even greater destruction and loss of civilian life? But again, Biden could give no credible account of himself, his policy, or the United States’ position on the future of the conflict. What was left to linger in the air was Trump’s bellicose disregard for the lives of Palestinians.

There were, to be sure, failings that cannot be blamed on Biden: the lack of fact checking by the host station CNN during the debate, for example, and the total absence of questions from the moderators directed at Trump about his claim that the 2020 presidential election was stolen from him. These point to tendency not to hold Trump accountable for his actions or lies. The next day, CNN reported that Trump made  30 false claims in the debate .

Above the law?

The inability to hold Trump to account has emboldened the already shameless showman to further defy democratic procedures and the rule of law. The recent decision of the Supreme Court and the heretofore successful strategy on the part of Trump’s legal teams to  “delay, delay, delay” the remaining three cases brought against him, almost guarantee that Trump will not be prosecuted for his role in attempting to interfere with the results of the last presidential election and disrupt the transfer of power on 6 January 2021. This would be a travesty of might over right, and would signal to the world that the US justice system is subject to the authoritarian dictates of a would-be despot.

America is on the precipice of becoming a post-democracy, if not pariah state among the international community. The stakes of the 2024 presidential election could hardly be higher. The outcome of this election is more important than the reputation or legacy of any one person. The reputation of the United States as a functioning liberal democracy hangs in the balance.

Want the best of Religion & Ethics delivered to your mailbox?

Sign up for our weekly newsletter.

Elected Democrats, party leaders, and major Democratic donors are currently putting significant pressure on Biden to step down . The pronouncements from the White House and Biden’s closest allies that the current president is not going to announce his retirement are signs of desperation rather than strength. In modern American politics, there has been no situation like this; Reagan’s poor first debate performance was positively cogent compared to Biden’s, and there were not editorials from major newspapers saying Reagan would lose the election for his party unless he stepped aside. The New York Times editorial board rightly called for  Biden to leave the race after the debate.

The most recent  New York Times /Siena College poll  showing Trump  six percentage points ahead among likely voters and nine points ahead among registered voters nationwide should be the final confirmation that Biden is not the right candidate to prevent the worrying prospect of a second Trump presidency. President Biden needs to do the right thing for his country, and the world, and step aside to allow the process formally to begin of deciding which Democrat will face Trump this November.

Brendon O'Connor is Professor of US Politics and US Foreign Relations, and is jointly appointed between the United States Studies Centre and the Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences at the University of Sydney. His most recent book is Anti-Americanism and American Exceptionalism Prejudice and Pride about the USA .

Bumble and bluster: Key takeaways from Biden and Trump's first 2024 presidential debate

A side by side image of Trump in a suit raising a thumb and Biden in a suit.

Insiders say two dozen high profile Democrats are ready to ask Biden to step aside. Has 'the dam broken'?

Joe Biden in black and white against a red blue gradient speaking at a podiumj

Democracy is precariously poised between what has been and what has yet to be

ethics in religion essay

The war in Gaza has revealed the limits of our political narratives, and the role of universities

ethics in religion essay

Is it worth risking your life for a lost cause? On the moral courage of Alexei Navalny

ethics in religion essay

Anti-social media: What can be done to stop platforms from driving democracies apart?

ethics in religion essay

Best of 2023: How woke thinking plays into the hands of anti-democratic forces

ethics in religion essay

IMAGES

  1. OCR RELIGIOUS STUDIES- Situation Ethics ESSAY PLAN

    ethics in religion essay

  2. The way religion impacts business ethics Essay Example

    ethics in religion essay

  3. Write an essay what is religion ? || Essay writing on what is religion ? in english

    ethics in religion essay

  4. Ethics From Islamic Perspective Theology Religion Essay Example

    ethics in religion essay

  5. The role of religion in human ethicality

    ethics in religion essay

  6. Lesson One

    ethics in religion essay

VIDEO

  1. WHAT IS CHRISTIAN ETHICS?

  2. Religion ।। write an essay on religion in english ।। paragraph on religion ।। essay writing

  3. Ethics and religion

  4. Ethics & Religion (Discussion)

  5. The Power of Ethics and Religion: Unveiling the Importance in our Lives #shorts #ethics

  6. Ethics: Problems for DCT

COMMENTS

  1. Does Ethics Require Religion?

    The relationship between religion and ethics is about the relationship between revelation and reason. Religion is based in some measure on the idea that God (or some deity) reveals insights about life and its true meaning. These insights are collected in texts (the Bible, the Torah, the Koran, etc.) and presented as "revelation.". Ethics ...

  2. The Ethics and Politics of Religious Ethics, 1973-2023

    June O'Connor's essay, "On Doing Religious Ethics," expands the metadisciplinary frame of reference by raising questions about "the task of religious ethics as a whole," which she tackles by describing the nature of the ethical task and then identifying what characteristics render that task a form of religious ethics (1979, 81-82 ...

  3. The Role of Religion in Ethics: A Comprehensive Examination

    The relationship between religion and ethics has been a topic of profound philosophical, theological, and societal interest for centuries. Throughout human history, various religions have played a significant role in shaping moral values, guiding ethical conduct, and influencing the moral decision-making of individuals and communities.

  4. Religion and Morality

    Religion and Morality. First published Wed Sep 27, 2006; substantive revision Thu Aug 8, 2019. From the beginning of the Abrahamic faiths and of Greek philosophy, religion and morality have been closely intertwined. This is true whether we go back within Greek philosophy or within Christianity and Judaism and Islam.

  5. The Relation of Ethics to Religion

    As religion can not be merged in ethics, so ethics must not be lost in religion. As an historical fact they have sometimes existed independently of each other, and do so still, though their normal and legitimate relation to one another is that of interaction. Religion may be non-ethical and ethics non-relig- ious.

  6. Introduction (Chapter 1)

    Practically all thinkers answer yes to this. Our issue, rather, is whether morality makes sense without God. Religious philosophers tend, roughly, to be of two camps. Some see ethics as God's commands (Part I, Chapters 2 and 3), while others see ethics as natural laws that have some independence from God's will (Part II, Chapters 4-6).

  7. PDF Ethics and Religion

    Contents Preface page vii 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Philosophy 1 1.2 Ethics 2 1.3 Religion 3 part i: ethics as god's commands 2 Divine Command Theory 9 2.1 C. S. Lewis 9 2.2 DCT 14 2.3 Euthyphro and Evil Actions 14 2.4 Sovereignty and the Bible 17 2.5 Meaning of "Good" 18 2.6 Knowing God's Will 21 2.7 Further DCT Issues 24 3 Modified DCT 29

  8. Ethics in religion

    Ethics involves systematizing, defending, and recommending concepts of right and wrong behavior. A central aspect of ethics is "the good life", the life worth living or life that is simply satisfying, which is held by many philosophers to be more important than traditional moral conduct.. Most religions have an ethical component, often derived from purported supernatural revelation or guidance.

  9. Ethics and Religion

    Abstract This essay surveys the relations between ethics and religion in a variety of comparative contexts. It suggests replacing the older paradigms of moral theory, for example, deontology/teleol...

  10. Religious Ethics as a Social Practice

    The Journal of Religious Ethics (JRE) was established at a particular moment in the United States in the early 1970s. This article investigates how that moment—in the institutional milieu of academic theology and religious studies in which the (JRE) emerged—influenced its founding. ... That lesson will have shaped the framing of this essay ...

  11. Ethics and Religion

    The book also discusses ethics and atheism: how atheists object on ethical grounds to belief in God and how they view ethics. The book defends belief in God from criticisms and analyzes related concepts, such as practical reason, the golden rule, ethics and evolution, the problem of evil, and the fine-tuning argument.

  12. Ethics and Religion: Making a Healthy Decision Essay

    Introductory Summary. Ethics and religion are two inseparable aspects of humanity that play a vital role in determining the credibility of people's actions ("Ethics for a Whole World," 2010). In essence, for a religion to become credible, it must be founded on the basis of strong ethical frameworks that uphold human dignity and self respect.

  13. The Role of Ethics in Religion

    A longstanding debate has been whether ethics plays a role in religion. Most religions have an ethical component. Ethics, which is a major branch of philosophy, encompasses right conduct and good life. It is significantly broader than the common conception of analyzing right and wrong. Ethics deals with ideas such as Right, Good and Duty and ...

  14. Ethics

    The term ethics may refer to the philosophical study of the concepts of moral right and wrong and moral good and bad, to any philosophical theory of what is morally right and wrong or morally good and bad, and to any system or code of moral rules, principles, or values. The last may be associated with particular religions, cultures, professions, or virtually any other group that is at least ...

  15. Faith and Ethics Role in Religion

    Faith and Ethics Role in Religion Essay. Faith and ethics as they are portrayed in the life of Jesus Christ are important to a person wishing to behave in a moral fashion and have deep respect for people. Faith and ethical characteristics of Jesus Christ are worthy to be emulated in our ethical decision making.

  16. Faith still shapes morals and values even after people are 'done' with

    Religion forms a moral foundation for billions of people throughout the world. In a 2019 survey, 44% of Americans - along with 45% of people across 34 nations - said that belief in God is ...

  17. Role of Religion in Society: Exploring its Significance and

    The record is mixed, but potential remains to harness religious ethics for social good. The Debate Surrounding the Role of Religion in Society ... The Relation of Ethics to Religion Essay. In the 21st-century ethics as far as religious doctrines are concerned has taken a modernity turn. In the classical period religion was solely relied on to ...

  18. Relationship Between Religion and Morality Essay

    This shows that the relationship between ethics and religion varies within a society. While a believer will pose that the two function as a couple, a non-believer, on the other hand, will hold that moral behavior is independent of faith. It is, therefore, deducible that what is morally right is not necessarily God's command.

  19. The Relation of Ethics to Religion: [Essay Example], 990 words

    The Relation of Ethics to Religion. In the 21st-century ethics as far as religious doctrines are concerned has taken a modernity turn. In the classical period religion was solely relied on to dictate morality but due to contemporariness catalyzed by education beliefs can no longer prescribe social principles. Issues are assessed and determined ...

  20. Situation Ethics

    Introduction. Situation ethics was created by Joseph Fletcher in the 1960s. It is a product of its time, and deliberately so. The 60s were defined by radical social movements aimed at overthrowing traditional ways of life which were seen as oppressive. Religion faces a dilemma in the face of such modernising forces; whether to adapt and reform ...

  21. The Religious Response

    Anceschi, et., (2011) point out the moral and ethical impact of religious discourses. As the religious domain remains to be multi-dimensional, encompassing attitudes, beliefs, emotions, experiences, rituals, the ties that bind the community of believers, and a deep sense of belonging, it is by no means that the power of religion can be deprecated.

  22. Religion and Ethics Essay ..... .....

    Religion and Ethics Lane Carpenter. Chamberlain University College of Nursing. ETHC445N- Professor Page May 16th, 2021. Religion and Ethics Combining ethics and religion can be both challenging and interesting. According to Hayden Ramsey, he says that we all must have some sort of common ground and principle for moral judgement (2011).

  23. The Role of Religions in Ethics

    Religion and Ethics. Ethics studies human behavior and ideal ways of being. As a philosophical discipline, it is a systematic approach to understanding, analyzing, and distinguishing matters of right and wrong, good and bad, and admirable and deplorable as they relate to the well-being of and the relationships among human beings. ...

  24. Opinion

    In a suit challenging the Louisiana law, Americans United for Separation of Church and State noted that among the state's approximately 680,000 students, many do not practice any religion at all ...

  25. Felt Ethics: Reimagining Ethics in Human-Technology Relations

    This paper discusses two ongoing project involving autonomous systems, using choreographic methods to explore ethical assumptions embedded in industrial robots and then reimagining such ethics using research through design, and develops felt ethics. Ethical sensibilities are constantly enacted in design practice. As we move towards pluralistic ways of designing, different ethical sensibilities ...

  26. What can be done to challenge the rent-seeking behaviour of the

    The ABC's Religion and Ethics portal is home to religious reporting & analysis, ethical discussion & philosophical discovery, and inspiring stories of faith and belief. More from ABC.

  27. cfp

    Religious journalism and its impact on public perception of religious sites. Verification of cultural beliefs and identities through travel. If you are interested in contributing, please submit an abstract of 300 words and a 200-word biographical note addressed to Kiranpreet Kaur Baath ( [email protected] ).

  28. Fully funded PhD opportunity in the ethics of palliative care

    Professor Linda Hogan is recruiting a fully-funded PhD student to work in the area of the ethics of palliative care. This PhD is one of four funded by an interdisciplinary Trinity Research Doctorate Group-based Award. The four successful applicants will be recruited on four distinct projects within a programme focused on Decision-Making for People with Advanced Illness in Palliative Care.

  29. Canada at a crossroads: Understanding the shifting sands of immigration

    In contrast, Muslims — the second-largest religious group in Canada after Christians — are the most supportive of immigration. Jewish Canadians, atheists and agnostics also show strong support.

  30. Faced with the threat of a second Trump presidency, America needs a

    The ABC's Religion and Ethics portal is home to religious reporting & analysis, ethical discussion & philosophical discovery, and inspiring stories of faith and belief. More from ABC.