Respect Essay for Students and Children

500+ words essay on respect.

Respect is a broad term. Experts interpret it in different ways. Generally speaking, it is a positive feeling or action expressed towards something. Furthermore, it could also refer to something held in high esteem or regard. Showing Respect is a sign of ethical behavior . Unfortunately, in the contemporary era, there has been undermining of the value of Respect. Most noteworthy, there are two essential aspects of Respect. These aspects are self-respect and respect for others.

Self-Respect

Self-Respect refers to loving oneself and behaving with honour and dignity. It reflects Respect for oneself. An individual who has Self-Respect would treat himself with honour. Furthermore, lacking Self-Respect is a matter of disgrace. An individual who does not respect himself, should certainly not expect Respect from others. This is because nobody likes to treat such an individual with Respect.

Self-Respect is the foundation of a healthy relationship . In relationships, it is important to respect your partner. Similarly, it is equally important to Respect yourself. A Self-Respecting person accepts himself with his flaws. This changes the way how others perceive the individual. An individual, who honours himself, would prevent others from disrespecting him. This certainly increases the value of the individual in the eyes of their partner.

Lacking Self-Respect brings negative consequences. An individual who lacks Self-Respect is treated like a doormat by others. Furthermore, such an individual may engage in bad habits . Also, there is a serious lack of self-confidence in such a person. Such a person is likely to suffer verbal or mental abuse. The lifestyle of such an individual also becomes sloppy and untidy.

Self-Respect is a reflection of toughness and confidence. Self-Respect makes a person accept more responsibility. Furthermore, the character of such a person would be strong. Also, such a person always stands for his rights, values, and opinions.

Self-Respect improves the morality of the individual. Such an individual has a good ethical nature. Hence, Self-Respect makes you a better person.

Self-Respect eliminates the need to make comparisons. This means that individuals don’t need to make comparisons with others. Some people certainly compare themselves with others on various attributes. Most noteworthy, they do this to seek validation of others. Gaining Self-Respect ends all that.

Get the huge list of more than 500 Essay Topics and Ideas

Respect of Others

Everyone must Respect fellow human beings. This is an essential requirement of living in a society. We certainly owe a basic level of Respect to others. Furthermore, appropriate Respect must be shown to people who impact our lives. This includes our parents, relatives, teachers, friends, fellow workers, authority figures, etc.

One of the best ways of showing respect to others is listening. Listening to another person’s point of view is an excellent way of Respect. Most noteworthy, we must allow a person to express his views even if we disagree with them.

Another important aspect of respecting others is religious/political views. Religious and cultural beliefs of others should be given a lot of consideration. Respecting other people’s Religions is certainly a sign of showing mature Respect.

Everyone must Respect those who are in authority. Almost everyone deals with people in their lives that hold authority. So, a healthy amount of Respect should be given to such people. People of authority can be of various categories. These are boss, police officer, religious leader, teacher, etc.

In conclusion, Respect is a major aspect of human socialization. It is certainly a precious value that must be preserved. Respectful behaviour is vital for human survival.

Customize your course in 30 seconds

Which class are you in.

tutor

  • Travelling Essay
  • Picnic Essay
  • Our Country Essay
  • My Parents Essay
  • Essay on Favourite Personality
  • Essay on Memorable Day of My Life
  • Essay on Knowledge is Power
  • Essay on Gurpurab
  • Essay on My Favourite Season
  • Essay on Types of Sports

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Download the App

Google Play

respect begets respect meaning essay

25,000+ students realised their study abroad dream with us. Take the first step today

Meet top uk universities from the comfort of your home, here’s your new year gift, one app for all your, study abroad needs, start your journey, track your progress, grow with the community and so much more.

respect begets respect meaning essay

Verification Code

An OTP has been sent to your registered mobile no. Please verify

respect begets respect meaning essay

Thanks for your comment !

Our team will review it before it's shown to our readers.

Leverage Edu

  • Essay Writing /

Essay on Respect: Best Samples Available for Students

respect begets respect meaning essay

  • Updated on  
  • Nov 7, 2023

Essay On Respect

Essay on Respect: Mahatma Gandhi once said, ‘I cannot conceive of a greater loss than the loss of one’s self-respect.’ We all deserve respect from others when they interact with us, regardless of how we are as individuals. Polite, considerate and courteous behaviour are all part of respect. Respect is a larger concept which encompasses treating others the way you would like to be treated, listening to different viewpoints with an open mind, and refraining from causing harm or offence to others. It is considered a fundamental aspect of healthy relationships, effective communication, and a harmonious society. Let’s discuss more through some samples in the essay on respect.

Table of Contents

  • 1 Essay on Respect in 100 Words
  • 2 Essay on Respect in 200 Words
  • 3 Essay on Respect in 300 Words

Also Read: World Sight Day Activities to Plan for Your School

Essay on Respect in 100 Words

Respect is a two-way concept; you receive respect when you show respect to others. Whether you are in a professional or a personal environment, talking respectfully is always appreciated. Respect is not just talking politely but a profound acknowledgement of the dignity of others. 

Respect involves listening to others with an open mind, appreciating the uniqueness of everyone, and refraining from actions that cause harm or undermine the well-being of others. We can consider respect as a timeless virtue. It is necessary for maintaining healthy relationships, communities, and societies. From the way we talk to the way we behave, respect is highlighted in our every move.

Also Read: Essay on Parents

Essay on Respect in 200 Words

‘Respect is what we owe; love, is what we give.’ – Philip James Bailey

How can you expect others to respect you when you cannot serve it to others? We never disrespect people whom we care about. Neither do they. As humans when interacting with others, we expect respectful behaviour from others. It is considered the fundamental aspect of binding human interactions and enabling us to live in harmony with others. 

We can acknowledge and appreciate people, which is one of the most important parts of respectful behaviour. At its essence, respect transcends cultural barriers and fosters empathy, understanding, and kindness among individuals.

Respect is shown via thoughtful actions and considerate behaviour. It involves treating others with courtesy, refraining from causing harm and valuing diverse perspectives. When one respects another person, one listens attentively, seeking to understand rather than to judge. This practice nurtures a culture of open communication and mutual understanding, facilitating the resolution of conflicts and the forging of strong, enduring relationships.

Our respectful attitude and behaviour cultivate a sense of belonging and safety in social settings. In school, respect forms the basis for effective learning and growth. The respectful behaviour of teachers and students fosters an atmosphere of trust and collaboration, nurturing an environment where knowledge is shared, and intellectual curiosity is encouraged.

Essay on Respect in 300 Words

‘Respect your efforts, respect yourself. Self-respect leads to self-discipline. When you have both firmly under your belt, that’s real power.’ – Clint Eastwood

Respect functions as the cornerstone of considerate and empathetic human interaction, forming the basis for a harmonious and equitable society. What we learn is what we say to others. Our respectful behaviour shows our inherent value and dignity. It also fosters empathy, understanding, and compassion, nurturing relationships that are founded on mutual admiration and consideration.

Showing a passive attitude that reflects in one’s behaviour and treatment of others shows who we really are. It entails treating individuals with dignity and kindness, valuing their perspectives, and honouring their rights and boundaries. When one demonstrates respect, they engage in thoughtful communication, listen attentively, and seek to understand differing viewpoints. Such actions lay the groundwork for trust and cooperation, facilitating the resolution of conflicts and the cultivation of strong, enduring bonds.

There are three types of respect: Respect for Personhood; Respect for Authority; and Respect for Honour.

  • Respect for personhood is the recognition and acknowledgement of the inherent dignity, autonomy, and worth of every individual. This concept emphasizes the importance of treating each person as a unique and valuable being, deserving of ethical consideration and moral regard.
  • Respect for authority acknowledges the legitimacy and position of individuals or institutions that hold power or influence in a particular context. It involves recognizing the roles and responsibilities of those in positions of authority and adhering to their directives or decisions within the boundaries of ethical and legal standards.
  • Respect for honour upholding the principles of integrity, dignity, and moral uprightness in both oneself and others

Respect is not confined to personal relationships and educational institutions; it is a fundamental element that shapes the fabric of society.

Ans: Here are some best tips for respecting people: act responsibly, be empathetic, accept mistakes, listen to others, be relentlessly proactive, pay attention to non-verbal communication, keep your promises, etc.

Ans: To write an essay you need to highlight what respect means to you and how it can serve as an effective tool for coexisting with others. The concept of respect goes beyond talking politely and actively listening. It is considered a fundamental aspect of healthy relationships, effective communication, and a harmonious society. 

Ans: Here are three types of respect: Respect for Personhood, Respect for authority and Respect for honour.

Related Articles

For more information on such interesting topics, visit our essay writing page and follow Leverage Edu .

' src=

Shiva Tyagi

With an experience of over a year, I've developed a passion for writing blogs on wide range of topics. I am mostly inspired from topics related to social and environmental fields, where you come up with a positive outcome.

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

Contact no. *

respect begets respect meaning essay

Connect With Us

respect begets respect meaning essay

25,000+ students realised their study abroad dream with us. Take the first step today.

respect begets respect meaning essay

Resend OTP in

respect begets respect meaning essay

Need help with?

Study abroad.

UK, Canada, US & More

IELTS, GRE, GMAT & More

Scholarship, Loans & Forex

Country Preference

New Zealand

Which English test are you planning to take?

Which academic test are you planning to take.

Not Sure yet

When are you planning to take the exam?

Already booked my exam slot

Within 2 Months

Want to learn about the test

Which Degree do you wish to pursue?

When do you want to start studying abroad.

January 2024

September 2024

What is your budget to study abroad?

respect begets respect meaning essay

How would you describe this article ?

Please rate this article

We would like to hear more.

Have something on your mind?

respect begets respect meaning essay

Make your study abroad dream a reality in January 2022 with

respect begets respect meaning essay

India's Biggest Virtual University Fair

respect begets respect meaning essay

Most Popular

Using grammarly placed a student on academic probation.

12 days ago

It’s vs Its

How to cite a report, how to cite a lab manual.

11 days ago

What is One Way to Avoid Plagiarism?

What is respect definition essay example.

freepik.com

Lesley J. Vos

The given prompt: How do personal values, culture, and experiences shape our understanding of respect?

Respect, a seemingly simple seven-letter word, carries profound implications in its fold. At its core, it’s about acknowledging the value and worth of someone or something. But scratch beneath the surface, and you’ll find that respect, like many concepts, is colored and shaped by personal values, cultural backgrounds, and individual experiences.

One’s personal values play an instrumental role in shaping the understanding of respect. If an individual values honesty, they will likely respect transparency in communication. If kindness is held high, compassionate actions will earn esteem. Our personal moral compass, which often develops from lessons learned during upbringing, influences what we regard as worthy of respect. For some, it might be the determination and grit someone displays; for others, it might be the ability to stay humble despite immense success.

Culture, the collective beliefs and behaviors of a group, further molds our concept of respect. In some Eastern cultures, for example, bowing is a traditional gesture of respect, signaling acknowledgment and deference. In contrast, in many Western societies, looking someone in the eye when speaking is an act of respect, denoting attention and sincerity. Even within cultures, nuances exist. An action deemed respectful in one community might be indifferent or even disrespectful in another.

Consider the tradition of addressing elders. In certain cultures, using formal titles or specific terms for elders is paramount, underscoring respect for age and wisdom. On the other hand, in more egalitarian societies, addressing everyone by their first name, irrespective of age or status, might be the norm, reflecting a different kind of respect anchored in equality.

The intricacies of respect become even more pronounced when we fold in personal experiences. Respect isn’t static; it evolves, shifts, and transforms based on our life journeys. Someone who has experienced betrayal might place immense respect on loyalty. An individual who has overcome challenges might deeply respect resilience in others.

Moreover, respect isn’t merely about admiration or esteem; it’s also about boundaries and space. Recognizing and honoring someone’s boundaries, whether emotional, physical, or psychological, is an integral aspect of respect. This understanding often stems from personal experiences. Those who’ve felt their boundaries violated in the past might be even more attuned to this dimension of respect.

But there’s a universal strand to respect that often overarches these individual and cultural nuances: the principle of mutual respect. Regardless of personal values, cultural backgrounds, or individual experiences, respect begets respect. Recognizing the inherent worth and dignity of every individual, irrespective of their background, beliefs, or choices, forms the bedrock of genuine respect.

In weaving through the tapestry of personal values, cultural nuances, and individual experiences, respect emerges as a multifaceted gem. It’s both personal and collective, both inherited and learned. It’s a reflection of what we value, what our culture upholds, and what our life stories have taught us.

Concluding, respect is a dynamic dance of acknowledgment, shaped by myriad influences. In understanding its depth, we not only navigate our interactions more thoughtfully but also contribute to a world where every individual feels valued, understood, and, most importantly, respected.

Follow us on Reddit for more insights and updates.

Comments (0)

Welcome to A*Help comments!

We’re all about debate and discussion at A*Help.

We value the diverse opinions of users, so you may find points of view that you don’t agree with. And that’s cool. However, there are certain things we’re not OK with: attempts to manipulate our data in any way, for example, or the posting of discriminative, offensive, hateful, or disparaging material.

Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

More from Definition Essay Examples and Samples

What Is a Home? Essay Definition Examples

Oct 20 2023

What Is a Home? Essay Definition Examples

What Is Family? Definition Essay Samples

Oct 18 2023

What Is Family? Definition Essay Samples

What Is Integrity? Essay Definition Example

Oct 17 2023

What Is Integrity? Essay Definition Example

Remember Me

What is your profession ? Student Teacher Writer Other

Forgotten Password?

Username or Email

Become a Writer Today

Essays About Respect: Top 5 Examples and 8 Prompts

If you are looking for the next topic for your essay, read our helpful prompts and example essays about respect to get started.

Respect is a fundamental pillar in a harmonious society. At a young age, we are taught that everyone is deserving of respect and should likewise respect others, regardless of diverging beliefs, cultures, and origins. The underlying golden rule is never to do what we don’t want others to do to us.

However, as we grow older, we find it harder to respect people who go against our moral standards and social mores. Nevertheless, acknowledging people and their rights could already be a form of respect. But when people do not care to meet this bare minimum for respect, conflicts and crimes can ensue. 

5 Essay Examples

1. on self-respect by joan didion, 2. respect, trust and partnership: keeping diplomacy on course in troubling times by ted osius, 3. the respect deficit by richard v. reeves, 4. the emotional attachment of national symbols by karina lafayette, 5. filipino hospitality and respect for the aged by kashiwagi shiho, 1. how to show respect to criminals, 2. respect vs. love in relationships, 3. showing respect on social media, 4. respecting indigenous cultures, 5. how to respect data privacy rights, 6. what is respect for parents day, 7. when employees do not feel respected , 8. respect for animals.

“To assign unanswered letters their proper weight, to free us from the expectations of others, to give us back to ourselves—there lies the great, the singular power of self-respect.”

Didion explores misplaced self-respect through her experience of not making it to Phi Beta Kappa and the experience of others. What has been primarily associated with flattering others, self-respect, to Didion, is a virtue that can be developed when we emancipate ourselves from the expectations of others. 

“…[W]hen we show respect it has a big impact. Showing respect means figuring out what is really, truly important to our partners and taking that seriously. It costs America almost nothing and gets us almost everything.”

A former US ambassador to Vietnam shares that respect is a powerful tool to build and strengthen trading partners’ relationships. In the end, he suggests strengthening diplomacy with country partners, such as developing language and regional expertise.

“Here is a much deeper kind of inequality, caused not by a lack of resources, but by a lack of respect. You might be much richer or poorer than I am. But if we treat each other with mutual respect, we are, relationally speaking, equal.”

The essay talks about relational equality and how the lack of it could undermine both the sense of respect for others and the self. It touches on how the world’s meritocratic system has furthered the divide between classes and driven respect away from their reach. The urgent goal is to restore the sense of respect amid the bustle of our daily motions in life.

“National symbols deserve respect not because they are static representations of unchanging ideals, but because they offer a focal point for diverse societies to express and navigate what it is that unites and represents them.”

Respect for national symbols is imperative. But when the approach turns to one that is resistant to prospects of modifying national symbols, then we are missing out on opportunities to re-evaluate and re-invent how we can best represent our collective ideals. Instead of treating national symbols as sacred icons impervious to change, the best way to respect them and what they represent is to brave the thorny road of change. 

“When a Filipino child meets an older family member, the youth customarily greets them with a gesture called ‘mano po,’ taking the older relative’s hand and placing it on his or her own forehead to express profound respect for the elder.”

The essay thoroughly navigates how the Philippine society defends its elders, from the gestures of greeting to how the government, private sector, and non-profit organizations band together to support elders living alone. Other countries can learn from the Philippines’ experience in caring for their elders, especially in the quality care their nurses provide.

8 Thought-Provoking Prompts on Essays About Respect

It is easy to respect those who have worked hard and are deemed as typically well-behaved. But what about criminals who are stereotyped as not showing respect to others, or working hard? Are they deserving of our respect? Answer these questions and determine whether criminals are provided decent facilities and programs that inspire them to change. You can also look into how police officers keep track of their value of life to avoid the abuse of power and putting an end to life with unnecessary force. 

couple, happy, man-1329349.jpg

Take a deep dive into the differences between respect and love and discuss which is more important in a relationship. But first, explain the two and provide narrative examples to demonstrate their contrasts.

For example, with love, one might be inclined to say, “I’m willing to change myself for you.” But with a respect-filled relationship, boundaries are drawn. Hence, people can live comfortably with their true selves without having to worry about losing a partner.

Social media encourages people to say what they wouldn’t otherwise say in the physical world primarily because of the anonymity that social media grants them. In your essay, describe the effects of disrespect on social media. Social experts observe that disrespect propels cancel culture and decreases our tolerance of people with differing views. Do you agree with this? Add in other observations you have about mutual respect, or the lack of it, on social media.

Indigenous groups call for recognition and respect for their land and rich cultures. In this prompt, cite the challenges in promoting respect for the rights of indigenous peoples.

For example, how does the government reconcile the need to preserve their traditions with the need to alter practices that negatively impact the environment? Write down what else the government can do to support indigenous groups. One example is ensuring their participation in deliberating their lands’ use to enable them to give free, prior, and informed consent.

Data privacy is a fundamental human right, but our data can be easily harvested through every transaction and activity we make using our phones. This essay discusses the data privacy law in your country or state.

Write about the obligations the law has set for companies to sufficiently safeguard the personal data of their clients. Suppose you want to look at international data privacy standards. In that case, you can explore the General Data Protection Regulation , dissect its seven principles and find out how they play in the data privacy cycle from collection to disposal. 

Respect for Parents Day is celebrated in the US every August 1 to recognize the importance of parents’ roles in their children’s lives and the larger society. Dedicate this essay to celebrating your parents. Share with readers the hard work they do to raise you while handling a job or a business to build your future. Briefly narrate the origins of Respect Your Parents Day and provide tips on how families can best spend this day.  

In the workplace, some bosses abuse their power, overstep their boundaries and forget the basics of respect. How does disrespect affect the motivation and productivity of workers? Mull over this question and try to enumerate the negative impacts of disrespect in the workplace. Then, with the support of research studies, find out what motivational methods managers can employ to reinforce employees positively and help them receive the respect they deserve.

girl, dog, pet-5623231.jpg

Over the years, the call for respect has extended beyond humankind and to the animal kingdom. First, hear the calls of advocacy groups combating the cruel practice of commoditizing animals or their parts for profit. Track how far their efforts have progressed.

You can also look into the International Convention for the Protection of Animals , a proposed treaty to address all animal issues, and research how it has moved forward to fill in the gap of an international agreement to protect animals.

Make sure your essays are clean and understandable with our list of the best essay checkers .

Tip : If writing an essay sounds like a lot of work, simplify it. Write a simple five-paragraph essay instead.

respect begets respect meaning essay

Yna Lim is a communications specialist currently focused on policy advocacy. In her eight years of writing, she has been exposed to a variety of topics, including cryptocurrency, web hosting, agriculture, marketing, intellectual property, data privacy and international trade. A former journalist in one of the top business papers in the Philippines, Yna is currently pursuing her master's degree in economics and business.

View all posts

May 4, 2023

Essays on Respect: Delving into the Core Values and Implications for Society

Respect is not just a word, it's a powerful force that can change the world. Struggling to write an essay on respect? These examples are here to guide you!

Have you ever noticed how a simple act of respect, like holding the door open for someone or saying 'thank you,' can brighten someone's day and make the world feel a little kinder? Respect is a fundamental value that we all need to thrive, yet it can sometimes feel in short supply in our fast-paced, competitive world. 

That's why in this series of essays, we're diving deep into the topic of respect: what it means, why it matters, and how we can cultivate it in our daily lives. We'll explore the power of reverence, examining how showing respect can be a transformative act that creates connection, understanding, and empathy. We'll also delve into the role of respect in relationships, discussing how treating others with dignity and kindness can be a foundation for healthy connections and flourishing communities. And, of course, we'll discuss the practical applications of respect, including how it can enhance communication and lead to more productive, satisfying interactions. 

By the end of this blog post, we hope you'll come away with a renewed appreciation for the value of respect and a host of tools and strategies for practicing it in your daily life. Join us on Jenni.ai to learn more and gain access to a wealth of resources for essay writing and more. Let's dive in!

Examples of Essays on Respect

The Importance of Respect in Building Healthy Relationships

Respect is an essential ingredient for any healthy relationship to thrive. When two people treat each other with respect, they can build a strong and lasting bond that withstands the test of time. Respect is not just about being polite or courteous to one another, but it's also about acknowledging and appreciating each other's unique qualities and differences. In this article, we'll explore the importance of respect in building healthy relationships and how it can help you maintain a happy and fulfilling connection with your partner.

What is respect?

Respect is a feeling of deep admiration for someone or something elicited by their abilities, qualities, or achievements. In the context of relationships, respect means treating your partner with dignity, recognizing their worth, and valuing their opinions and feelings. It involves listening to them, being considerate of their needs, and acknowledging their boundaries.

Why is respect important in relationships?

Respect is the foundation on which healthy relationships are built. Without respect, a relationship can quickly deteriorate into a toxic and unhealthy dynamic where one partner dominates the other or both partners constantly belittle each other. Respect is what allows two people to trust each other, communicate effectively, and build a strong emotional connection. Here are some reasons why respect is crucial in building healthy relationships:

It fosters trust and intimacy

When two people respect each other, they can trust each other to be honest and transparent. This trust allows them to open up and be vulnerable with each other, leading to a deeper emotional connection and intimacy. Trust and intimacy are essential for any healthy relationship to thrive, and respect is the foundation on which they are built.

It promotes effective communication

Respectful communication involves listening actively, being mindful of each other's feelings, and avoiding hurtful language or behaviors. When two people communicate respectfully, they can resolve conflicts in a constructive and healthy manner, leading to a stronger and more fulfilling relationship.

It builds a sense of safety and security

When two people respect each other, they feel safe and secure in each other's company. They know that they can rely on each other and that their partner will always have their back. This sense of safety and security is essential for building a healthy and long-lasting relationship.

It helps to maintain individuality

Respect is not just about acknowledging your partner's worth, but also about respecting their individuality and unique qualities. When two people respect each other, they can appreciate each other's differences and allow each other to grow and develop as individuals. This helps to maintain a healthy balance between dependence and independence in the relationship.

How to show respect in a relationship?

Showing respect in a relationship involves a combination of behaviors and attitudes. Here are some ways you can show respect to your partner:

Listen actively

One of the most important ways to show respect is to listen actively to your partner. This means paying attention to what they are saying, asking questions, and responding with empathy and understanding.

Be considerate of their feelings

Respect also means being considerate of your partner's feelings. Avoid saying or doing things that might hurt them or make them feel uncomfortable.

Acknowledge their achievements

Respect involves acknowledging and appreciating your partner's achievements and successes. Celebrate their accomplishments and encourage them to pursue their goals and dreams.

Respect their boundaries

Respect also means respecting your partner's boundaries. Avoid pressuring them to do things they are uncomfortable with and always seek their consent before engaging in any intimate activities.

Avoid criticizing or belittling them

Respectful communication also involves avoiding hurtful language or behaviors. Avoid criticizing or belittling your partner, and instead focus on expressing your concerns in a constructive and respectful manner.

Show appreciation and gratitude

Showing appreciation and gratitude is another important way to demonstrate respect in a relationship. Let your partner know that you value and appreciate them, and express your gratitude for the things they do for you.

Be honest and transparent

Honesty and transparency are crucial components of respectful communication. Be truthful with your partner, and avoid hiding things from them or being deceitful in any way.

Take responsibility for your actions

Respect also means taking responsibility for your actions and acknowledging when you make mistakes. Apologize when you've done something wrong, and work together with your partner to find a solution.

How to handle disrespect in a relationship?

Disrespectful behavior can have a significant impact on a relationship and can quickly lead to conflict and tension. Here are some ways to handle disrespect in a relationship:

Communicate your concerns

The first step in addressing disrespect in a relationship is to communicate your concerns to your partner. Let them know how their behavior is making you feel, and work together to find a solution.

Set boundaries

Setting boundaries is an important part of respecting yourself in a relationship. Let your partner know what you will and won't tolerate, and be prepared to enforce these boundaries if necessary.

Seek outside help

If you're struggling to handle disrespect in your relationship, consider seeking outside help from a therapist or counselor. They can provide you with the tools and support you need to navigate the situation.

Respect is an essential ingredient for building healthy and fulfilling relationships. When two people treat each other with respect, they can develop a strong emotional connection based on trust, intimacy, and mutual appreciation. By listening actively, being considerate of each other's feelings, and communicating respectfully, you can show your partner that you value and respect them. Remember that respect is a two-way street, and it's essential to treat your partner the way you would like to be treated.

Cultivating Respect: Strategies for Fostering a Culture of Civility

Respect is a fundamental aspect of human interactions. It is essential to creating a positive and productive workplace culture. Unfortunately, respect is often in short supply in many organizations, leading to negative outcomes such as high turnover rates, low employee engagement, and poor job satisfaction. In this article, we will explore strategies for cultivating respect in the workplace to foster a culture of civility.

Introduction

The workplace is a complex environment that involves the interaction of various individuals with diverse backgrounds and personalities. This diversity often results in conflicts that can negatively impact the work environment. Therefore, fostering a culture of civility is critical to ensuring a healthy and productive workplace. Civility refers to respectful behavior and polite communication, even in situations where there is disagreement or conflict.

The Importance of Respect in the Workplace

Respect is vital to creating a positive and productive work environment. It promotes employee engagement, job satisfaction, and overall well-being. Respectful interactions also encourage collaboration, creativity, and innovation. When employees feel respected, they are more likely to share ideas, provide feedback, and take risks.

Strategies for Fostering a Culture of Civility

Lead by Example: The behavior of leaders sets the tone for the entire organization. Leaders should model respectful behavior and communicate clear expectations for civility in the workplace.

Communication: Encourage open and honest communication by creating a safe and supportive environment. Ensure that all employees have an opportunity to share their thoughts and ideas.

Education: Provide training on conflict resolution, effective communication, and cultural awareness. This will equip employees with the necessary skills to navigate difficult conversations and work collaboratively with diverse individuals.

Policies and Procedures: Establish clear policies and procedures for addressing conflicts and promoting respectful behavior. Ensure that all employees are aware of these policies and understand the consequences of violating them.

Recognition: Recognize and reward employees who demonstrate respectful behavior and contribute to a positive work environment. This will encourage others to follow suit and foster a culture of civility.

Challenges and Solutions

Cultivating respect and promoting civility in the workplace is not always easy. There are several challenges that organizations may face, including resistance to change, lack of resources, and differing perspectives. However, these challenges can be overcome by implementing the following solutions:

Address Resistance: Address resistance to change by communicating the benefits of cultivating respect and promoting civility. Explain how it will benefit the organization, employees, and customers.

Allocate Resources: Allocate the necessary resources to promote respectful behavior, such as training programs, policies and procedures, and recognition programs.

Understand Differences: Encourage employees to understand and respect cultural and individual differences. This will help to foster an environment of inclusivity and respect.

Cultivating respect and promoting civility in the workplace is essential to creating a positive and productive work environment. It requires leadership, communication, education, policies, and recognition. Organizations that prioritize respect and civility will benefit from increased employee engagement, job satisfaction, and overall well-being. By implementing the strategies discussed in this article, organizations can create a culture of civility that fosters respect, collaboration, and innovation.

In conclusion, cultivating respect and promoting civility in the workplace is critical to creating a positive and productive work environment. It requires the commitment and effort of all employees, starting with leadership. By implementing the strategies discussed in this article, organizations can create a culture of civility that fosters respect, collaboration, and innovation. By doing so, they will benefit from increased employee engagement, job satisfaction, and overall well-being, leading to greater success and growth.

Understanding Empathy: The Key to Building Respectful Connections

Empathy is the ability to understand and share the feelings of others. It is a powerful tool that helps us connect with people and build healthy relationships. In this article, we will explore the meaning of empathy, its importance in building respectful connections, and how to cultivate empathy in our daily lives.

What is Empathy?

Empathy is the ability to understand and share the feelings of others. It involves putting yourself in someone else's shoes and seeing the world from their perspective. Empathy helps us connect with people and build healthy relationships by creating a sense of mutual understanding and respect.

The Different Types of Empathy

There are three different types of empathy: cognitive empathy, emotional empathy, and compassionate empathy.

Cognitive Empathy

Cognitive empathy is the ability to understand someone's thoughts and feelings intellectually. It involves seeing the world from their perspective and understanding their needs and concerns.

Emotional Empathy

Emotional empathy is the ability to share someone's feelings and emotions. It involves feeling what they feel and experiencing their emotions alongside them.

Compassionate Empathy

Compassionate empathy is the ability to feel someone's emotions and take action to help them. It involves understanding their needs and concerns and taking steps to address them.

How to Cultivate Empathy

Cultivating empathy requires practice and effort. Here are some strategies you can use to cultivate empathy in your daily life:

Active Listening

Active listening involves fully concentrating on what someone is saying and actively engaging with them. It involves asking questions, providing feedback, and demonstrating that you are fully present and engaged.

Putting Yourself in Someone Else's Shoes

Putting yourself in someone else's shoes involves imagining how they are feeling and seeing the world from their perspective. It involves suspending judgment and taking the time to understand their needs and concerns.

Practicing Self-Reflection

Practicing self-reflection involves taking the time to reflect on your own thoughts and feelings. It involves being honest with yourself about your biases and assumptions and actively working to challenge them.

Practicing Empathy Exercises

Practicing empathy exercises involves actively seeking out opportunities to practice empathy. These exercises may involve volunteering, practicing active listening, or engaging in role-playing activities.

Empathy is a crucial tool for building respectful connections with others. It allows us to understand and share the feelings of others, creating a sense of mutual understanding and respect. By practicing empathy in our daily lives, we can build stronger relationships, enhance our communication skills, and improve our overall well-being.

Respect and Communication: How Listening and Dialogue Can Build Bridges

Communication is the foundation of any relationship, be it personal or professional. However, communication isn't just about talking; it also involves listening actively and with respect. In this article, we will explore how respect and communication can build bridges and help create strong relationships.

Definition of communication

Importance of communication

Communication challenges

Building Bridges through Communication

Communication is a powerful tool that can be used to create and maintain bridges between people. By communicating effectively, we can connect with others on a deeper level and build trust and respect. Here are some ways to build bridges through communication:

Active listening is the key to effective communication. When we listen actively, we give the other person our undivided attention, and we try to understand their perspective without interrupting or judging them.

Empathy is the ability to understand and share the feelings of another person. When we empathize with others, we put ourselves in their shoes, and we try to see things from their perspective. This helps us to communicate more effectively and build stronger relationships.

Respect is essential in any relationship. When we respect others, we treat them with dignity and honor their views and opinions, even if we disagree with them. This creates a safe space for communication and encourages people to share their thoughts and feelings openly.

Open Communication

Open communication is critical for building bridges. When we communicate openly, we share our thoughts and feelings honestly and transparently, and we encourage others to do the same. This helps to build trust and creates a deeper connection between people.

Communication Challenges

Effective communication isn't always easy, and there are many challenges that can arise. Here are some of the most common communication challenges:

Language Barriers

Language barriers can make communication difficult, especially when there are cultural differences. It's essential to be patient and to try to understand the other person's perspective, even if there are language barriers.

Emotional Triggers

Emotions can often get in the way of effective communication. When we feel triggered, we may become defensive or angry, which can create a barrier to communication. 

Power Imbalances

Power imbalances can make communication difficult, especially in a professional setting. When one person has more power or authority than the other, it can be challenging to communicate effectively. 

Effective communication is critical for building bridges and creating strong relationships. By listening actively, empathizing, showing respect, and communicating openly, we can overcome communication challenges and build bridges that last. Remember to be patient, kind, and understanding, and always approach communication with an open mind and heart.

The Power of Reverence: How Respect Can Shape Our Lives

Respect is an essential aspect of our lives that plays a crucial role in shaping our personalities and building meaningful relationships. When we show respect to others, we create a positive environment that allows everyone to thrive. The power of reverence goes beyond basic etiquette; it influences our behavior, decisions, and outlook on life. In this article, we will explore the importance of respect and how it can shape our lives.

Understanding Respect

Respect is defined as a feeling of deep admiration for someone or something elicited by their abilities, qualities, or achievements. It is an attitude that acknowledges the worth of another person or thing. Respect is a fundamental aspect of human interaction that creates a positive environment for everyone. It is essential in building trust, maintaining healthy relationships, and promoting cooperation.

Respect in Personal Relationships

Respect is an essential ingredient in creating meaningful personal relationships. It is the foundation on which all relationships are built. When we show respect to our partners, friends, and family members, we create an environment of trust, empathy, and mutual understanding. Respect allows us to communicate effectively, express our opinions, and solve conflicts in a healthy manner. It is also the key to maintaining healthy boundaries and creating a safe space for everyone involved.

Respect in Professional Relationships

Respect is equally important in professional relationships. It is the key to building trust, fostering collaboration, and creating a positive work environment. When we show respect to our colleagues, supervisors, and subordinates, we promote teamwork, productivity, and job satisfaction. Respectful communication allows for the sharing of ideas, constructive feedback, and the creation of a supportive work culture.

The Benefits of Respect

The power of reverence has numerous benefits that can positively impact our lives. Respect promotes empathy, understanding, and cooperation, allowing us to build healthy relationships with others. It creates a positive environment that fosters personal and professional growth, leading to increased productivity, job satisfaction, and overall well-being. Showing respect also improves our self-esteem, allowing us to feel more confident and empowered.

The Consequences of Disrespect

On the other hand, disrespect can have severe consequences that negatively impact our lives. Disrespectful behavior can damage relationships, erode trust, and create a hostile work environment. It can lead to misunderstandings, conflicts, and even legal issues in extreme cases. Disrespectful behavior can also damage our self-esteem, leading to feelings of inadequacy and insecurity.

Cultivating Respect

Cultivating respect is an ongoing process that requires mindfulness and conscious effort. It involves acknowledging the worth of others, recognizing their contributions, and treating them with dignity and kindness. Cultivating respect also means recognizing our own worth and treating ourselves with kindness and compassion. When we cultivate respect, we create a positive environment that allows everyone to thrive.

In conclusion, the power of reverence is an essential aspect of our lives that can positively impact our personal and professional relationships. Respect allows us to build healthy relationships, promotes empathy and understanding, and fosters personal and professional growth. It is the key to creating a positive environment that allows everyone to thrive. Cultivating respect is an ongoing process that requires mindfulness and conscious effort, but the benefits are worth it.

In conclusion, these essays have explored the multifaceted concept of respect, examining its core values and societal implications. We have seen how respect can foster healthy relationships, promote empathy and understanding, and facilitate productive communication. Through examples from literature, history, and contemporary events, we have gained insights into the power of reverence and the importance of cultivating a culture of civility.

If you are a student looking to improve your essay writing skills, Jenni.ai can help. With our AI-powered tools and resources, you can streamline your writing process, generate new ideas, and refine your work for maximum impact. Sign up for a free trial today to discover the benefits of Jenni.ai and take your writing to the next level.

Try Jenni for free today

Create your first piece of content with Jenni today and never look back

Confucius: 'Without feelings of respect, what is there to distinguish men from beasts?'

Without feelings of respect, what is there to distinguish men from beasts?

The quote by Confucius, 'Without feelings of respect, what is there to distinguish men from beasts?' resonates with a timeless truth about the essence of humanity. It suggests that respect is a fundamental characteristic that separates humans from animals, elevating us to a higher level of existence. At a straightforward level, this quote highlights the importance of respect as a defining quality of human behavior. It implies that without a sense of respect, we risk becoming no different from the creatures that lack the cognitive and moral capacity to exhibit it.Respect, in its simplest form, is the recognition and appreciation for the inherent worth and dignity of all individuals. It encompasses the acknowledgment of their rights, opinions, perspectives, and humanity as a whole. This acknowledgment is essential for the cultivation of harmonious relationships within a society, enabling cooperation, empathy, and understanding among human beings.However, to delve deeper into the significance of this quote, let us introduce the concept of moral consciousness. Moral consciousness refers to an individual's capacity to make ethical judgments, discern right from wrong, and act in accordance with moral principles. It is an integral part of human nature, enabling us to transcend our basic instincts and engage in a higher level of ethical and compassionate behavior.While animals may exhibit certain characteristics that resemble respect, such as protecting their young or displaying hierarchical behavior, they lack the same level of moral consciousness as humans. Animals act primarily on instinct, driven by self-preservation and survival. They are not guided by a deep understanding of moral values or the ability to make deliberate choices that consider the well-being of others.In contrast, humans have the capacity to reason, reflect, and exercise free will. We possess the ability to grasp the concepts of fairness, justice, and compassion. It is through these qualities that we embrace the spirit of respect and elevate ourselves from mere creatures of instinct. This ability to understand and practice respect is what distinguishes us from beasts.Respect serves as a cornerstone for a just and harmonious society. It fosters empathy and inspires individuals to treat others with dignity and kindness. When we respect one another, we embrace diversity, celebrate differences, and foster an environment where all feel valued and accepted. Respect begets respect, creating a positive cycle that promotes cooperation and mutual understanding. Without this fundamental quality, society would invariably descend into chaos, devoid of the harmony and cohesion necessary for progress and growth.Moreover, respect extends beyond human interactions. It encompasses our relationship with the natural world, as well. Respecting the environment, animals, and ecosystems is an essential part of our responsibility as custodians of the planet. By honoring the sanctity of life in all its forms, we honor our own humanity and acknowledge our interconnectedness with the world around us.In conclusion, Confucius' quote encapsulates the profound significance of respect in our lives. It reminds us that respect is not only a matter of social etiquette, but a fundamental quality that distinguishes us as humans. Through respect, we exercise our moral consciousness and showcase our ability to rise above instinctual behavior. It is through respect that we nurture harmonious relationships, build a just society, and foster a world where individuals and nature are valued and protected. Let us continuously strive to cultivate respect within ourselves and extend it to those we encounter, for it is through this virtue that we truly embody our humanity.

Albert Camus: 'I would rather live my life as if there is a God and die to find out there isn't, than live my life as if there isn't and die to find out there is.'

Christopher marlowe: 'accurst be he that first invented war.'.

SEP thinker apres Rodin

Respect has great importance in everyday life. As children we are taught (one hopes) to respect our parents, teachers, and elders, school rules and traffic laws, family and cultural traditions, other people's feelings and rights, our country's flag and leaders, the truth and people's differing opinions. And we come to value respect for such things; when we're older, we may shake our heads (or fists) at people who seem not to have learned to respect them. We develop great respect for people we consider exemplary and lose respect for those we discover to be clay-footed, and so we may try to respect only those who are truly worthy of our respect. We may also come to believe that, at some level, all people are worthy of respect. We may learn that jobs and relationships become unbearable if we receive no respect in them; in certain social milieus we may learn the price of disrespect if we violate the street law: “Diss me, and you die.” Calls to respect this or that are increasingly part of public life: environmentalists exhort us to respect nature, foes of abortion and capital punishment insist on respect for human life, members of racial and ethnic minorities and those discriminated against because of their gender, sexual orientation, age, religious beliefs, or economic status demand respect both as social and moral equals and for their cultural differences. And it is widely acknowledged that public debates about such demands should take place under terms of mutual respect. We may learn both that our lives together go better when we respect the things that deserve to be respected and that we should respect some things independently of considerations of how our lives would go.

We may also learn that how our lives go depends every bit as much on whether we respect ourselves. The value of self-respect may be something we can take for granted, or we may discover how very important it is when our self-respect is threatened, or we lose it and have to work to regain it, or we have to struggle to develop or maintain it in a hostile environment. Some people find that finally being able to respect themselves is what matters most about getting off welfare, kicking a disgusting habit, or defending something they value; others, sadly, discover that life is no longer worth living if self-respect is irretrievably lost. It is part of everyday wisdom that respect and self-respect are deeply connected, that it is difficult if not impossible both to respect others if we don't respect ourselves and to respect ourselves if others don't respect us. It is increasingly part of political wisdom both that unjust social institutions can devastatingly damage self-respect and that robust and resilient self-respect can be a potent force in struggles against injustice.

The ubiquity and significance of respect and self-respect in everyday life largely explains why philosophers, particularly in moral and political philosophy, have been interested in these two concepts. They turn up in a multiplicity of philosophical contexts, including discussions of justice and equality, injustice and oppression, autonomy and agency, moral and political rights and duties, moral motivation and moral development, cultural diversity and toleration, punishment and political violence. The concepts are also invoked in bioethics, environmental ethics, business ethics, workplace ethics, and a host of other applied ethics contexts. Although a wide variety of things are said to deserve respect, contemporary philosophical interest in respect has overwhelmingly been focused on respect for persons, the idea that all persons should be treated with respect simply because they are persons. Respect for persons is a central concept in many ethical theories; some theories treat it as the very essence of morality and the foundation of all other moral duties and obligations. This focus owes much to the 18 th century German philosopher, Immanuel Kant, who argued that all and only persons (i.e., rational autonomous agents) and the moral law they autonomously legislate are appropriate objects of the morally most significant attitude of respect. Although honor, esteem, and prudential regard played important roles in moral and political theories before him, Kant was the first major Western philosopher to put respect for persons, including oneself as a person, at the very center of moral theory, and his insistence that persons are ends in themselves with an absolute dignity who must always be respected has become a core ideal of modern humanism and political liberalism. In recent years many people have argued that moral respect ought also to be extended to things other than persons, such as nonhuman living things and the natural environment.

Despite the widespread acknowledgment of the importance of respect and self-respect in moral and political life and theory, there is no settled agreement in either everyday thinking or philosophical discussion about such issues as how to understand the concepts, what the appropriate objects of respect are, what is involved in respecting various objects, what the conditions are for self-respect, and what the scope is of any moral requirements regarding respect and self-respect. This entry will survey these and related issues.

1.1 Elements of respect

1.2 kinds of respect, 2.1 some important issues, 2.2 kant's account of respect for persons, 2.3 further issues, developments, and applications, 3. respect for nature and other nonpersons, 4.1 the concept of self-respect, 4.2 treatment of self-respect in moral and political philosophy, 5. conclusion, philosophical works chiefly on respect and related concepts, philosophical works chiefly on self-respect and related concepts, other internet resources, related entries, 1. the concept of respect.

Among the main questions about respect that philosophers have addressed are these: (1) How should respect in general be understood? (a) What category of thing is it? Philosophers have variously identified it as a mode of behavior, a form of treatment, a kind of valuing, a type of attention, a motive, an attitude, a feeling, a tribute, a principle, a duty, an entitlement, a moral virtue, an epistemic virtue: are any of these categories more central than others? (b) What are the distinctive elements of respect? (c) To what other attitudes, actions, valuings, duties, etc. is respect similar, and with what does it contrast? (d) What beliefs, attitudes, emotions, motives, and conduct does respect involve, and with what is it incompatible? (2) What are the appropriate objects of respect, i.e., the sorts of things that can be reasonably said to warrant respect? (3) What are the bases or grounds for respect, i.e., the features of or facts about objects in virtue of which it is reasonable and perhaps obligatory to respect them? (4) What ways of acting and forbearing to act express or constitute or are regulated by respect? (5) What moral requirements, if any, are there to respect certain types of objects, and what is the scope and theoretical status of such requirements? (6) Are there different levels or degrees of respect? Can an object come to deserve less or no respect? (7) Why is respect morally important? What, if anything, does it add to morality over and above the conduct, attitudes, and character traits required or encouraged by various moral principles or virtues? (8) What are the implications of respect for problematic moral and sociopolitical issues such as racism and sexism, pornography, privacy, punishment, responses to terrorism, paternalism in health care contexts, cultural diversity, affirmative action, abortion, and so on?

It is widely acknowledged that there are different kinds of respect, which complicates the answering of these questions. For example, answers concerning one kind of respect can diverge significantly from those about another kind. Much philosophical work has gone into explicating differences and links among the various kinds. One general distinction is between respect simply as behavior and respect as an attitude or feeling which may or may not be expressed in or signified by behavior. We might speak of drivers respecting the speed limit, hostile forces as respecting a cease fire agreement, or AIDS as not respecting national borders, and in such cases we can be referring simply to behavior which avoids violation of or interference with some boundary, limit, or rule, without any reference to attitudes, feelings, intentions, or dispositions, and even, as in the case of the AIDS virus, without imputing agency (Bird 2004). In such cases the behavior is regarded as constitutive of respecting. In other cases, we take respect to be or to express or signify an attitude or feeling, as when we speak of having respect for another person or for nature or of certain behaviors as showing respect or disrespect. In what follows, I will focus chiefly on respect as attitude or feeling. There are, again, several different attitudes or feelings to which the term “respect” refers. Before looking at differences, however, it is useful first to note some elements common among varieties.

An attitude of respect is, most generally, a relation between a subject and an object in which the subject responds to the object from a certain perspective in some appropriate way. Respect necessarily has an object: respect is always directed toward, paid to, felt about, shown for some object. While a very wide variety of things can be appropriate objects of one kind of respect or another, the subject of respect (the respecter) is always a person, that is, a conscious rational being capable of recognizing and acknowledging things, of self-consciously and intentionally responding to them, of having and expressing values with regard to them, and of being accountable for disrespecting or failing to respect them. Though animals may love or fear us, only persons can respect and disrespect us or anything else. Respect is a responsive relation, and ordinary discourse about respect identifies several key elements of the response, including attention, deference, judgment, acknowledgment, valuing, and behavior. First, as suggested by its derivation from the Latin respicere , which means “to look back at” or “to look again,” respect is a particular mode of apprehending the object: the person who respects something pays attention to it and perceives it differently from someone who does not and responds to it in light of that perception. This perceptual element is common also to synonyms such as regard (from “to watch out for”) and consideration (“examine (the stars) carefully”). The idea of paying heed or giving proper attention to the object which is central to respect often means trying to see the object clearly, as it really is in its own right, and not seeing it solely through the filter of one's own desires and fears or likes and dislikes. Thus, respecting something contrasts with being oblivious or indifferent to it, ignoring or quickly dismissing it, neglecting or disregarding it, or carelessly or intentionally misidentifying it. An object can be perceived by a subject from a variety of perspectives; for example, one might rightly regard another human individual as a rights-bearer, a judge, a superlative singer, a trustworthy person, or a threat to one's security. The respect one accords her in each case will be different, yet all will involve attention to her as she really is as a judge, threat, etc. It is in virtue of this aspect of careful attention that respect is sometimes thought of as an epistemic virtue.

As responsive, respect is object-generated rather than wholly subject-generated, something that is owed to, called for, deserved, elicited, or claimed by the object. We respect something not because we want to but because we recognize that we have to respect it (Wood 1999); respect involves “a deontic experience”—the experience that one must pay attention and respond appropriately (Birch 1993). It thus is motivational: it is the recognition of something “as directly determining our will without reference to what is wanted by our inclinations” (Rawls 2000, 153). In this way respect differs from, for example, liking and fearing, which have their sources in the subject's interests or desires. When we respect something, we heed its call, accord it its due, acknowledge its claim to our attention. Thus, respect involves deference, in the most basic sense of yielding: self-absorption and egocentric concerns give way to consideration of the object, one's motives or feelings submit to the object's reality, one is disposed to act in obedience to the object's demands.

At the same time, respect is also an expression of agency: it is deliberate, a matter of directed rather than grabbed attention, of reflective consideration and judgment. In particular, the subject judges that the object is due, deserves, or rightfully claims a certain response in virtue of some feature of or fact about the object that warrants that response. This feature or fact is the ground or basis in the object, that in virtue of which it calls for respect. The basis gives us a reason to respect the object; it may also indicate more precisely how to respect it. Respect is thus reason-governed: we cannot respect a particular object for just any old reason or for no reason at all. Rather, we respect an object for the reason that it has, in our judgment, some respect-warranting characteristic, that it is, in our view, the kind of object that calls for that kind of response (Cranor 1975; but see Buss 1999 for disagreement). And these reasons are categorical, in the sense that their weight or stringency does not depend on the subject's interests, goals, or desires; hence acting against these reasons, other things equal, is wrong (Raz 2001). Respect is thus both subjective and objective. It is subjective in that the subject's response is constructed from her understanding of the object and its characteristics and her judgments about the legitimacy of its call and how fittingly to address the call. An individual's respect for an object can thus be inappropriate or unwarranted, for the object may not have the features she takes it to have, or the features she takes to be respect-warranting might not be, or her idea of how properly to treat the object might be mistaken. But, as object-generated, the logic of respect is the logic of objectivity and universality, in four ways. First, in respecting an object, we respond to it not as an extension of feelings, desires, and interests we already have, but as something whose significance is independent of us. Second, we experience the object as constraining our attitudes and actions. Third, our reasons for respecting something are, we logically have to assume, reasons for other people to respect it (or at least to endorse our respect for it from a common point of view). Respect is thus, unlike erotic or filial love, an impersonal response to the object. Fourth, respect is universalizing, in the sense that if F is a respect-warranting feature of object O, then respecting O on account of F commits us, other things equal, to respecting other things that also have feature F. In respect, then, subjectivity defers to objectivity.

There are many different kinds of objects that can reasonably be respected and many different reasons why they warrant respect; thus warranted responses can take different forms beyond attention, deference, and judgment. Some things are dangerous or powerful and respect of them can involve fear, awe, self-protection, or submission. Other things have authority over us and the respect they are due includes acknowledgment of their authority and perhaps obedience to their authoritative commands. Other forms of respect are modes of valuing, appreciating the object as having an objective worth or importance that is independent of, perhaps even at variance with, our antecedent desires or commitments. Thus, we can respect things we don't like or agree with, such as our enemies or someone else's opinion. Valuing respect is kin to esteem, admiration, veneration, reverence, and honor, while regarding something as utterly worthless or insignificant or disdaining or having contempt for it is incompatible with respecting it. Respect also aims to value its object appropriately, so it contrasts with degradation and discounting. The kinds of valuing that respect involves also contrast with other forms of valuing such as promoting or using (Anderson 1993, Pettit 1989). Indeed, regarding a person merely as useful (treating her as just a sexual object, an ATM machine, a research subject) is commonly identified as a central form of disrespect for persons, and many people decry the killing of endangered wild animals for their tusks or hides as despicably disrespectful of nature. Respect is sometimes identified as a feeling; it is typically the experiencing of something as valuable that is in focus in these cases.

Finally, respect is generally regarded as having a behavioral component. In respecting an object, we often consider it be making legitimate claims on our conduct as well as our thoughts and feelings and are disposed to behave appropriately. Appropriate behavior includes refraining from certain treatment of the object or acting only in particular ways in connection with it, ways that are regarded as fitting, deserved by, or owed to the object. And there are very many ways to respect things: keeping our distance from them, helping them, praising or emulating them, obeying or abiding by them, not violating or interfering with them, destroying them in some ways rather than letting them be destroyed in others, protecting or being careful with them, talking about them in ways that reflect their worth or status, mourning them, nurturing them. One can behave in respectful ways, however, without having respect for the object, as when a teen who disdains adults behaves respectfully toward her friend's parents in a scheme to get the car, manipulating rather than respecting them. To be a form or expression of respect, behavior has to be motivated by one's acknowledgment of the object as calling for that behavior, and it has to be motivated directly by consideration that the object is what it is, without reference to one's own interests and desires. On the other hand, certain kinds of feelings would not count as respect if they did not find expression in behavior or involved no dispositions to behave in certain ways rather than others, and if they did not spring from the beliefs, perceptions, and judgments that the object is worthy of or calls for such behavior.

The attitudes of respect, then, have cognitive dimensions (beliefs, acknowledgments, judgments, deliberations, commitments), affective dimensions (emotions, feelings, ways of experiencing things), and conative dimensions (motivations, dispositions to act and forbear from acting); some forms also have valuational dimensions. The attitude is typically regarded as central to respect: actions and modes of treatment typically count as respect insofar as they either manifest an attitude of respect or are of a sort through which the attitude of respect is characteristically expressed; a principle of respect is one that, logically, must be adopted by someone with the attitude of respect or that prescribes the attitude or actions that express it (Frankena 1986, Downie and Telfer 1969).

That it is the nature of the object that determines its respect-worthiness, and that there are different kinds of objects calling for correspondingly different responses has led many philosophers to argue that there are different kinds of respect. In what follows, three sets of distinctions will be discussed.

Speculating on the historical development of the idea that all persons as such deserve respect, and using terms found in Kant's writings on Achtung (the German word usually translated as “respect”), Feinberg (1975) identifies three distinct concepts for which “respect” has been the name. (1) Respekt , is the “uneasy and watchful attitude that has 'the element of fear' in it” (1975,1). Its objects are dangerous things or things with power over the subject. It is respekt that woodworkers are encouraged to have for power tools, that a city dweller might have for street gangs, a new sailor might be admonished to have for the sea, a child might have for an abusive parent. Respekt contrasts with contemptuous disregard; it is shown in conduct that is cautious, self-protective, other-placating. (2) The second concept, observantia , is the moralized analogue of respekt. It involves regarding the object as making a rightful claim on our conduct, as deserving moral consideration in its own right, independently of considerations of personal well being. It is observantia , Feinberg maintains, that historically was extended first to classes of non-dangerous but otherwise worthy people and then to all persons as such, regardless of merit or ability. Observantia encompasses both the respect said to be owed to all humans equally and the forms of polite respect and deference that acknowledge different social positions. (3) Reverentia , the third concept, is the special feeling of profound awe and respect we have in the presence of something extraordinary or sublime, a feeling that both humbles and uplifts us. On Kant's account, the moral law and people who exemplify it in morally worthy actions elicit reverentia from us, for we experience the law or its exemplification as “something that always trumps our inclinations in determining our wills” (Feinberg 1975, 2). Feinberg sees different forms of power as underlying the three kinds of respect; in each case, respect is the acknowledgment of the power of something other than ourselves to demand, command, or make claims on our attention, consideration, and deference.

Hudson (1980) draws a four-fold distinction among kinds of respect, according to the bases in the objects. Consider the following sets of examples: (a) respecting a colleague highly as a scholar and having a lot of respect for someone with “guts”; (b) a mountain climber's respect for the elements and a tennis player's respect for her opponent's strong backhand; (c) respecting the terms of an agreement and respecting a person's rights; and (d) showing respect for a judge by rising when she enters the courtroom and respecting a worn-out flag by burning it rather than tossing it in the trash. The respect in (a), evaluative respect , is similar to other favorable attitudes such as esteem and admiration; it is earned or deserved (or not) depending on whether and to the degree that the object is judged to meet certain standards. Obstacle respect , in (b), is a matter of regarding the object as something that, if not taken proper account of in one's decisions about how to act, could prevent one from achieving one's ends. The objects of (c) directive respect are directives: things such as requests, rules, advice, laws, or rights claims that may be taken as guides to action. One respects a directive when one's behaviors intentionally comply with it. The objects of (d) institutional respect are social institutions or practices, the positions or roles defined within an institution or practice, and persons or things that occupy the positions or represent the institution. Institutional respect is shown by behavior that conforms to rules that prescribe certain conduct as respectful. These four forms of respect differ in several ways. Each identifies a quite different kind of feature of objects as the basis of respect. Each is expressed in action in quite different ways, although evaluative respect need not be expressed at all, one can have institutional respect for an institution (e.g., the criminal justice system) without showing it for a particular element of it (the judge in this trial), and directive respect is not an attitude that one might or might not express but a mode of conduct motivated by a recognition of the directive's authority. Evaluative respect centrally involves having a favorable attitude toward the object, while the other forms do not. Directive respect does not admit of degrees (one either obeys the rule or doesn't), but the others do (we can have more evaluative respect for one person than another). Hudson uses this distinction to argue that respect for persons is not a unique kind of respect but should be conceived rather as involving some combination or other of these four.

To Hudson's four-fold classification, Dillon (1992a) adds a fifth form, care respect , which is exemplified in an environmentalist's deep respect for nature. Care respect involves regarding the object as having profound and perhaps unique value and so cherishing it, and perceiving it as fragile or calling for special care and so acting or forbearing to act out of felt benevolent concern for it. This analysis of respect draws explicitly from a feminist ethics of care and has been influential in feminist and non-feminist discussions of respecting persons as unique, particular individuals.

Darwall (1977) distinguishes two kinds of respect: recognition respect and appraisal respect . Recognition respect is the disposition to give appropriate weight or consideration in one's practical deliberations to some fact about the object and to regulate one's conduct by constraints derived from that fact. (Frankena 1986 and Cranor 1982, 1983) refer to this as “consideration respect.”) A wide variety of objects can be objects of recognition respect, including laws, dangerous things, someone's feelings, social institutions, nature, the selves individuals present in different contexts, and persons as such. Appraisal respect, by contrast, is an attitude of positive appraisal of a person or their merits, which are features of persons that manifest excellences of character. Individuals can be the objects of appraisal respect either as persons or as engaged in some pursuit or occupying some role. Evaluation is always done in light of some qualitative standards, and different standards can apply to one and the same individual. Thus, appraisal respect is a matter of degree, depending on the extent to which the object meets the standards (so, we can respect someone more or less highly and respect one person more highly than another), and it can co-exist with (some) negative assessments of an individual or her traits (judged in light of other standards). We can have appraisal respect for someone's honesty even while thinking her lazy, and we can highly respect someone else as altogether a morally fine person; we can respect an individual as an excellent teacher or carpenter yet regard her as far from a moral exemplar. Darwall (1977) distinguishes appraisal respect, which is based on assessment of character traits, from esteem, another attitude of positive assessment whose wider basis include any features in virtue of which one can think well of someone. However, other philosophers treat “esteem” and (appraisal) “respect” as synonyms, and Darwall (2004) calls appraisal respect a form of esteem.

The recognition/appraisal distinction has been quite influential and is widely regarded as the fundamental distinction. If it is, then it should encompass the other distinctions (although some fine-tuning might be necessary). And indeed, evaluative respect and perhaps reverentia for morally good persons are essentially the same as appraisal respect, while respekt , obstacle respect, observantia, directive respect, institutional respect, and care respect can be analyzed as forms of recognition respect. Some philosophers, however, have found the recognition/appraisal distinction to be inadequate. Neither reverentia for the moral law nor the felt experience of reverential respect for the sublimity of persons as such (Buss 1999) are forms of appraisal respect, yet because recognition respect is analyzed, first, as holding only in deliberative contexts, and second, as not essentially involving feeling, reverentia seems also not to be a form of recognition respect. Moreover, while valuing the object is not part of Darwall's analysis of recognition respect—and it is not essential to some forms of recognition respect (e.g., directive respect) and is only indirectly involved in other forms (in obstacle respect, we don't value the obstacle but do value the goal it blocks us from reaching)—valuing is essential to some forms of respect that are not appraisal respect. In particular, valuing persons intrinsically is widely regarded as the heart of the respect that all persons are thought to be owed simply as persons. However, it is not sufficient simply to gloss recognition respect as recognizing the value of the object, for one can recognize the value of something and yet not value it, as an insurance appraiser does, or take the value of something, say, a person's child, into account in deliberating about how best to revenge oneself on that person. Respect for some categories of objects is not just a matter of taking the object's value into consideration but of valuing the object, and valuing it intrinsically. Analyzing appraisal respect as just the positive assessment of someone's character traits as good is similarly problematic, for one can evaluate something highly and yet not value it. For example, one can appraise someone's moral performance as stellar and hate or envy her for precisely that reason. Respect in the appraisal sense is not just evaluating but also valuing the object positively. The recognition/appraisal distinction thus seems to obscure another very important distinction between what we might call valuing respect and non-valuing respect. Appraisal respect is a form of valuing respect, but recognition respect includes both valuing and non-valuing forms. There are, of course, different modes of valuing, and at least three distinctions are relevant to respect: (a) between moral and non-moral valuing (or, valuing from a moral or a nonmoral point of view), (b) between comparative and non-comparative valuing, and (c) between valuing intrinsically (valuing it in itself, apart from valuing anything else) and valuing extrinsically (for example, because of its relation to something else of value) (Anderson 1993). A complete account of respect would need to work out a taxonomy that incorporates these valuing distinctions.

In the rest of this article, I will discuss respect and self-respect using Darwall's term “recognition respect,” Hudson's term “evaluative respect,” and Feinberg's “reverential respect” (the last for the valuing feeling that is motivational without being deliberative), specifying the valuing dimensions as necessary.

In everyday discourse, the valuing sense of respect, especially when used about people, most commonly means thinking highly of someone, i.e., evaluative respect. However, philosophical attention to respect has tended to focus on recognition (or, sometimes, reverential) respect that acknowledges or values the object from a moral point of view. These discussions tend to relate such respect to the concepts of moral standing or moral worth. Moral standing, or moral considerability, is the idea that certain things matter morally in their own right and so are appropriate objects of direct fundamental moral consideration or concern (Kuflik 1998, Birch 1993, P. Taylor 1986). Some form of recognition respect is, on some accounts, a primary mode of such moral consideration. Alternatively, it is argued that certain things have a distinctive kind of intrinsic and incomparable moral worth or value, often called “dignity,” in virtue of which they ought to be accorded some valuing form of moral recognition or reverential respect. Discussions that focus on moral standing or moral worth address questions such as: What things fall within the domain of basic moral consideration or have this distinctive moral worth? What confers moral standing on objects, or what is the basis of their moral worth? Are there different levels of moral standing and, if so, do objects at different levels warrant different modes of moral respect? And what sorts of treatment are constitutive of, express, or are compatible with such moral respect? In modern philosophical discussions, humans are universally regarded as the paradigm objects of moral respect; if anything has moral standing or dignity and so warrants respect, it is the individual human being. Although some theorists argue that nature (or, all living beings, species, ecosystems) or societies (or, cultures, traditions) also warrant the moral consideration and valuing of respect, most philosophical discussion of respect has focused on respect for persons.

2. Respect for Persons

People can be the objects or recipients of different forms of respect. We can (directive) respect a person's legal rights, show (institutional) respect for the president by calling him “Mr. President,” have a healthy (obstacle) respect ( respekt ) for an easily angered person, (care) respect someone by cherishing her in her concrete particularity, (evaluatively) respect an individual for her commitment to a worthy project, and accord one person the same basic moral respect we think any person deserves. Thus the idea of respect for persons is ambiguous. Because both institutional respect and evaluative respect can be for persons in roles or position, the phrase “respecting someone as an R” might mean either having high regard for a person's excellent performance in the role or behaving in ways that express due consideration or deference to an individual qua holder of that position. Similarly, the phrase “respecting someone as a person” might refer to appraising her as overall a morally good person, or to acknowledging her standing as an equal in the moral community, or to attending to her as the particular person she is as opposed to treating her like just another body. In the literature of moral and political philosophy, the notion of respect for persons commonly means a kind of respect that all people are owed morally just because they are persons, regardless of social position, individual characteristics or achievements, or moral merit. The idea is that persons as such have a distinctive moral status in virtue of which we have special categorical obligations to regard and treat them in ways that are constrained by certain inviolable limits. This is sometimes expressed in terms of rights: persons, it is said, have a fundamental moral right to respect simply because they are persons. And it is a commonplace that persons are owed or have a right to equal respect. It is obvious that we could not owe every individual evaluative respect, let alone equal evaluative respect, since not everyone acts morally correctly or has an equally morally good character. So, if it is true that all persons are owed or have a moral right to respect just as persons, then the concept of respect for person has to be analyzed as some form or combination of forms of recognition or reverential respect. For a variety of reasons, however, it is controversial whether we do indeed have a moral obligation to respect all persons, regardless of merit, and if so, why. There are disagreements, for example, about the scope of this claim, the grounds for respect, and the justification for the obligation. There is also a divergence of views about the kinds of treatment that are respectful of persons.

One source of controversy concerns the scope of the concept of a person. Although in everyday discourse the word “person” is synonymous with “human being,” some philosophical discussions treat it as a technical term whose range of application might be wider than the class of human beings (just as, for legal purposes, business corporations are regarded as persons). This is because some of the reasons that have been given for respecting persons have the logical consequence that non-human things warrant the same respect on the very same grounds as humans. Consequently, one question an account of respect for persons has to address is: Who or what are persons that are owed respect? Different answers have been offered, including all human beings; all and only those humans who are themselves capable of respecting persons; all beings capable of rational activity, whether human or not; all beings capable of functioning as moral agents, whether human or not. The second, third and fourth answers would seem to exclude deceased humans and humans who lack sufficient mental capacity, such as the profoundly retarded, the severely mentally ill and senile, those in persistent vegetative states, the pre-born, and perhaps very young children. The third and fourth answers might include artificial beings (androids, sophisticated robots), spiritual beings (gods, angels), extraterrestrial beings, and certain animals (apes, dolphins).

In trying to clarify who or what we are obligated to respect, we are naturally led to a question about the ground or basis of respect: What is it about persons that makes them matter morally and makes them worthy of respect? One common way of answer this question is to look for some morally significant natural quality that is common to all beings that are noncontroversially owed respect (for example, all normal adult humans). Candidate qualities include the ability to be moved by considerations of moral obligation, the ability to value appropriately, the ability to reason, and the ability to engage in reciprocal relationships. Some of these apply only to humans, others to other beings as well. Even regarding humans, there is a question of scope: Are all humans owed respect? If respect is something to which all human beings have an equal claim, then, it has been argued, the ground quality has to be one that all humans possess equally or in virtue of which humans are naturally equal, or a threshold quality that all humans possess, with variations above the threshold ignored. Some philosophers have argued that certain capacities fit the bill; others argue that there is no quality possessed by all humans that could be a plausible ground for a moral obligation of equal respect. Some draw from this the conclusion that respect is owed not to all but only to some human beings; others conclude that the obligation to respect all humans is groundless: rather than being grounded in some fact about humans, respect confers moral standing on them. But the last view still leaves the questions: why should this standing be conferred on humans? And is it conferred on all humans? Yet another question of scope is: Must persons always be respected? One view is that individuals forfeit their claim to respect by, for example, committing heinous crimes of disrespect against other persons, such as murder in the course of terrorism or genocide. Another view is that there are no circumstances under which it is morally justifiable to not respect a person, and that even torturers and child-rapists, though they may deserve the most severe condemnation and punishment and may have forfeited their rights to freedom and perhaps to life, still remain persons to whom we have obligations of respect, since the grounds of respect are independent of moral merit or demerit.

Beyond the question of the ground or basis of respect for persons, there is a further question of justification to be addressed, for it is one thing to say that persons have a certain valuable quality, but quite another thing to say that there is a moral obligation to respect persons. So we must ask: What reasons do we have for believing that the fact that persons possess quality X entails that we are morally obligated to respect persons by treating them in certain ways? (Hill 1997). Another way of asking a justification question seeks not a normative connection between qualities of persons and moral obligation, but an explanation for our belief that humans (and perhaps other beings) are owed respect, for example: What in our experience of other humans or in our evolutionary history explains the development and power of this belief? Our actual felt experiences of reverential respect play a significant role in some of these explanatory accounts; what justifies accepting our experience of respect for humans (or other beings) as grounds for an obligation is its coherence with our other moral beliefs (Buss 1999, Margalit 1996, Gibbard 1990).

Finally, there are questions about how we are supposed to respect persons, such as: What standards for conduct and character give appropriate expression to the attitude of respect? Some philosophers argue that the obligation to respect person functions as a negative constraint: respect involves refraining from regarding or treating persons in certain ways. For example, we ought not to treat them as if they were worthless or had value only insofar as we find them useful or interesting, or as if they were mere objects or specimens, or as if they were vermin or dirt; we ought not to violate their basic moral rights, or interfere with their efforts to make their own decisions and govern their own conduct, or humiliate them, or treat them in ways that flout their nature and worth as persons. Others maintain that we also have positive duties of respect: we ought, for example, to try to see each of them and the world from their own points of view, or help them to promote their morally acceptable ends, or protect them from their own self-harming decisions. And some philosophers note that it may be more respectful to judge someone's actions or character negatively or to punish someone for wrongdoing than to treat them as if they were not responsible for what they did, although requirements of respect would impose limits on how such judgments may be expressed and how persons may be punished. Another question is whether treating people with respect requires treating them equally. One view is that the equality of persons entails equal treatment; another view is that equal treatment would involve failing to respect the important differences among persons. On the latter view, it is respectful to deal with each individual impartially and exclusively on the basis of whatever aspects of the individual or the situation are relevant (Frankfurt 1999).

The most influential position on these issues is found in the moral philosophy of Immanuel Kant (1785, 1788, 1797). Indeed, most contemporary discussions of respect for persons explicitly claim to rely on, develop, or challenge some aspect of Kant's ethics. Central to Kant's ethical theory is the claim that all persons are owed respect just because they are persons, that is, free rational beings. To be a person is to have a status and worth that is unlike that of any other kind of being: it is to be an end in itself with dignity. And the only response that is appropriate to such a being is respect. Respect (that is, moral recognition respect) is the acknowledgment in attitude and conduct of the dignity of persons as ends in themselves. Respect for such beings is not only appropriate but also morally and unconditionally required: the status and worth of person is such that they must always be respected. Because we are all too often inclined not to respect persons, not to value them as they ought to be valued, one formulation of the Categorical Imperative, which is the supreme principle of morality, commands that our actions express due respect for the worth of persons: “Act in such a way that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or the person of any other, never simply as a means but always at the same time as an end” ( Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten ( Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Moral) (1785), 4:429). Our fundamental moral obligation, then, is to respect persons; morally right actions are thus those that express respect for persons as ends in themselves, while morally wrong actions are those that express disrespect or contempt for persons by not valuing them as ends in themselves (Wood 1999). In addition to this general commandment, Kant argues that there are also more specific duties of respect for other persons and self-respect, to which we'll return. For now, we must address the question, What is it to be an end in itself and to possess dignity?

The concept of an end has several meanings for Kant. In one sense, to be an end is to have some kind of value or worth. Most things have value as the objects of our desires, interests, or affections; they are the ends we pursue or produce, our subjective ends. But the worth of an end in itself is worth that is not relative to, conditional on, or derived from being the object of anyone's desires or affections. Rather, its worth is intrinsic to it, unconditional, incomparable, and objective. Kant calls this distinctive worth which only ends in themselves possess “dignity.” In Kant's theory of value dignity is the supreme value; thus ends in themselves are to be valued morally above all other entities. Kant argues that rational beings are the only entities that are ends in themselves and that all rational beings are ends in themselves. The term “person” means a being whose rational nature “already marks them out as ends in themselves...and an object of respect” (Kant 1785, 4: 428). In arguing for respect for the dignity of persons, Kant explicitly rejects two other conceptions of human value: the aristocratic idea of honor that individuals differentially deserve according to their social rank, individual accomplishments, or moral virtue (see Berger 1983 for a discussion of the aristocratic dimensions of honor), and the view, baldly expressed by Hobbes, that “the value or worth of a man is, as of all other things, his price—that is to say, so much as would be given for the use of his power—and therefore is not absolute but a thing dependent on the need and judgment of another” (Hobbes 1958 (1651), 79). In Die Metaphysik der Sitten (The Metaphysics of Morals) (1797) Kant grants that if we think of humans as merely one kind of animal among others “in the system of nature,” we can ascribe a price to them, an extrinsic value that depends on their usefulness; but, he argues, “a human being regarded as a person, that is, as the subject of morally practical reason, is exalted above all price...as an end in himself he possesses a dignity by which he exacts respect for himself from all other beings in the world” (Kant 1797, 6: 434–435). Against the aristocratic view Kant argues that although individuals as members of some social community or other may have or lack meritorious accomplishment or status or may deserve honor (or evaluative respect) to different degrees or not at all, all persons as members of the moral community, the community of all and only ends in themselves, are owed the same (moral recognition) respect, for the dignity that they possesses as rational is unconditional and independent of all other facts about or features of them. Dignity is also absolute and incomparable worth: it can't be compared with, exchanged for, or replaced by any other value, whereas the very purpose of a price is to establish comparative value. And dignity is objective worth, which means that it is a value that everyone has compelling reason to acknowledge, regardless of their antecedent desires, interests, or affections. This brings us to a second sense in which persons are ends in themselves. For “end” can also mean a limit or constraint on action (as the end of the road puts a limit on our our travel). The rational nature of persons “constitutes the supreme limiting condition of the freedom of action of every human being” (Kant 1785, 4: 431); it puts an absolute limit on how we can treat them. In particular, they must never be treated merely as means, as things that we may use however we want in order to advance our interests, and they must always be treated as the supremely valuable beings that they are. Note that it is not wrong to treat persons as means to our ends; indeed we could not get along in life if we could not make use of the talents, abilities, service, and labor of other people. What we must not do is to treat persons as mere means to our ends, to treat them as if the only value they have is what derives from their usefulness to us. We must always treat them “at the same time as an end.” To respect persons is thus to regard them as absolutely, unconditionally, and incomparably valuable, to value them in themselves and not just in comparison to others or insofar as they are valuable to someone or could be useful as a means for furthering some purpose, and to acknowledge in a practical way that their dignity imposes absolute constraints on our treatment of them.

As the Categorical Imperative indicates, it is humanity in persons, strictly speaking, that has dignity; that is, it is in virtue of the humanity in them that people are and so ought to be treated as ends in themselves. Commentators generally identify humanity (that which makes us distinctively human beings and sets us apart from all other animal species) with two closely related aspects of rationality: the capacity to set ends and the capacity to be autonomous, both of which are capacities to be a moral agent (for example, Wood 1999, Korsgaard 1997, Hill 1997). The capacity to set ends, which is the power of rational choice, is the capacity to value things through rational judgment: to determine, under the influence of reason independently of antecedent instincts or desires, that something is valuable or important, that it is worth seeking or valuing. It is also, thereby, the capacity to value ends in themselves, and so it includes the capacity for respect (Velleman 1999). The capacity to be autonomous is the capacity to be self-legislating and self-governing, that is, (a) the capacity to legislate moral laws that are valid for all rational beings through one's rational willing by recognizing, using reason alone, what counts as a moral obligation, and (b) the capacity then to freely resolve to act in accordance with moral laws because they are self-imposed by one's own reason and not because one is compelled to act by any forces external to one's reason and will, including one's own desires and inclinations. The capacity to be autonomous is thus also the capacity to freely direct, shape, and determine the meaning of one's own life, and it is the condition for moral responsibility. But why does the possession of these capacities make persons ends in themselves? Kant argues that moral principles must be categorical imperatives, which is to say that they must be rational requirements to which we are unconditionally subject, regardless of whatever inclinations, interests, goals, or projects we might have. But there could be categorical imperatives only if there is something of absolute worth. Only persons have this kind of worth, and they have it because the capacity to set ends, or to confer value on things, is the source of all objective value (as Korsgaard 1996 and Wood 1999 have argued), and the capacity for autonomy is the source, on the one hand, both of the obligatoriness of moral law and of responsible moral actions, and on the other, of all realized human goodness. As the sources of all value and of morality itself, then, these rational capacities are the basis of the absolute worth or dignity of rational beings. Kant maintains that all rational beings necessarily attribute this value to themselves and that they must, on reflection, acknowledge that every other rational being has the same value and on the same grounds: because of the rational nature that is common to all persons. It is thus not as members of the biological species homo sapiens that we have dignity and so are owed moral recognition respect, but as rational beings who are capable of moral agency.

There are several important consequences of this view regarding the scope of recognition respect for persons. First, while all normally functioning human beings possess the rational capacities that ground recognition respect, there can be humans in whom these capacities are altogether absent and who therefore are not persons and are not owed respect. Second, these capacities may be possessed by beings who are not biologically human, and such beings would also be persons with dignity whom we are morally obligated to respect. Third, because dignity is an absolute worth grounded in the rational capacities for morality, it is in no way conditional on how well or badly those capacities are exercised, on whether a person acts morally or has a morally good character or not. Thus, dignity cannot be diminished or lost through vice or morally bad action, nor can it be increased through virtue or morally correct action. Because personhood and dignity are not matters of degree, neither is the recognition respect owed to persons. Once a person, always a person (barring, say, brain death), and so individuals cannot forfeit dignity or the right to recognition respect no matter what they do. It follows that even the morally worst individuals must still be regarded as ends in themselves and treated with respect. Of course, wrongdoing may call for punishment and may be grounds for forfeiting certain rights, but it is not grounds for losing dignity or for regarding the wrongdoer as worthless scum. Recognition respect is not something individuals have to earn or might fail to earn, but something they are owed simply because they are rational beings. Finally, because dignity is absolute and incomparable, the worth of all rational beings is equal. Thus the morally worst persons have the same dignity as the morally best persons, although the former, we might say, fail to live up to their dignity. What grounds dignity is something that all persons have in common, not something that distinguishes one individual from another. Thus each person is to be respected as an equal among equals, without consideration of their individual achievements or failures, social rank, moral merit or demerit, or any feature other than their common rational nature. However, the equality of all rational beings does not entail that each person must be treated the same as every other persons, nor does it entail that persons cannot also be differentially evaluated and valued in other ways for their particular qualities, accomplishments, merit, or usefulness. But such valuing and treatment must always be constrained by the moral requirement to accord recognition respect to persons as ends in themselves.

In Die Metaphysik der Sitten (The Metaphysics of Morals) (1797) Kant develops the implications of this view of persons as ends in themselves. In his doctrine of justice he argues that persons, by virtue of their rational nature, are bearers of fundamental rights, including the innate right to freedom, which must be respected by other persons and by social institutions. The dignity of persons also imposes limits on permissible reasons for and forms of legal punishment. In his doctrine of virtue, Kant discusses specific moral duties of recognition respect for other persons, as well as duties of self-respect, to which we'll return below. Here, Kant explicitly invokes the notion of respect as observantia . We have no moral duty to feel respect for others, he holds, for we cannot have a moral duty to have any feeling, since feelings are not directly controllable by our will. Rather, the respect we owe others is “to be understood as the maxim of limiting our self-esteem by the dignity of humanity in another person, and so as respect in the practical sense” (Kant 1797, 6:449). This duty of recognition respect owed to others requires two things: first, that we adopt as a regulating policy a commitment to control our own desire to think well of ourselves (this desire being the main cause of disrespect), and, second, that we refrain from treating others in the following ways: treating them merely as means (valuing them as less than ends in themselves), showing contempt for them (denying that they have any worth), treating them arrogantly (demanding that they value us more highly than they value themselves), defaming them by publicly exposing their faults, and ridiculing or mocking them. We also have duties of love to others, and Kant argues that in friendship respect and love, which naturally pull in opposite directions, achieve a perfect balance.

Subsequent work in a Kantian vein on the duty of respect for others has expanded the list of ways that we are morally required by respect to treat persons. In particular, although Kant says that the duties of recognition respect are strictly negative, consisting in not engaging in certain conduct or having certain attitudes, many philosophers have argued that respecting others involves positive actions and attitudes as well. The importance of autonomy and agency in Kant's moral philosophy has led many philosophers to highlight respect for autonomy. Thus, we respect others as persons (negatively) by doing nothing to impair or destroy their capacity for autonomy, by not interfering with their autonomous decisions and their pursuit of (morally acceptable) the ends they value, and by not coercing or deceiving them or treating them paternalistically. We also respect them (positively) by protecting them from threats to their autonomy (which may require intervention when someone's current decisions seem to put their own autonomy at risk) and by promoting autonomy and the conditions for it (for example, by allowing and encouraging individuals to make their own decisions, take responsibility for their actions, and control their own lives). Some philosophers have highlighted Kant's claim that rationality is the ground for recognition respect, arguing that to respect others is to engage with them not as instruments or obstacles but as persons who are to be reasoned with. So, for example, we should employ considerations that are accessible to other persons and provide them with genuine reasons in our dealings with them rather than trying to manipulate them through nonrational techniques such as threat or bribery, act toward them only in ways to which they could give rational consent, and be willing to listen to them and take their reasons seriously. The importance of the capacity to set ends and value things has been taken by some philosophers to entail that respect also involves consideration for the interests of others; so, we should help them to promote and protect what they value and to pursue their ends, provided these are compatible with due respect for other persons, and we should make an effort to appreciate values that are different from our own. Kant's emphasis in the doctrine of justice on the fundamental rights that persons have has led still others to view the duty of recognition respect for persons as the duty to respect the moral rights they have as persons; some have claimed that the duty to respect is nothing more than the duty to refrain from violating these rights (Benn 1980, Feinberg 1970).

One final dimension of Kant's discussions of respect that is worth mentioning is his attention to the feeling of respect (reverentia) . In the Groundwork Kant identifies the object of the feeling of respect as the moral law and says that respect for the moral law is the only moral motive (4:400). Reverential respect is unlike any other feeling humans experience in that it is not dependent on empirical desires or any other contingencies of the individual agent's psychology, situation, or history, but is “self-produced by means of a rational concept,” that is, the moral law which, as rational beings, we impose on ourselves. The unique moral feeling of reverential respect both the experience of the objective worth of the moral law (Wood 1999) and the experience of the supreme and absolute authority that the moral law has over us (Grenberg 1999), the felt consciousness of the immediate “subordination of my will” to it ( Groundwork 4:401n). In Critik der practischen Vernuft (Critique of Practical Reason) (1788) Kant discusses reverential respect in explaining how the moral law, a purely rational principle, is an “incentive” or motivating reason for choice and action in a being who is not wholly and solely rational but whose will is also affected by inclinations and yet is free ( Critique 5:72–76). As a complex experience that is both the cognitive recognition of the moral law and an affective state (McCarty 1994), reverential respect is the way, and the only way, in which are aware of the self-legislated rational principles for action that unconditionally constrain our inclinations (Stratton-Lake 2000). In recognizing the moral law we are conscious of it in a way that involves two contrasting yet simultaneously experienced feelings. First, in being aware of the law as having absolutely authority, we experience the subordination of our will to its commands. This consciousness of subordination involves a painful, humbling feeling insofar as our self-love (our efforts to satisfy our desires and pursue our ends) is constrained and our self-conceit (our attempts to esteem ourselves independently of moral considerations) is struck down by the moral law's claim to supreme authority. At the same time, however, our awareness of the moral law involves a pleasurably uplifting feeling insofar as we recognize our own reason to be its only source. The moral law thus appears to us not merely as constraint but as freely imposed self-constraint; and reverential respect, this complex experience of the law as both unconditionally authoritative and self-imposed and of both the restriction on our inclinations and the “sublimity” of our “higher vocation” to be self-legislating and self-governing ( Critique 5:87–88), is the way in which we are morally motivated by the law to do unconditionally and so freely what it commands. Reverential respect is a unique feeling not only in that it is produced by reason alone but also in that it is the only feeling that we can know a priori , which is to say that we can know that that the moral experience of every human agent is necessarily and inescapably one of reverential respect for the moral law, for we cannot be aware of the moral law except reverentially (Stratton-Lake 2000). It is, of course and unfortunately, also true that many of us, perhaps most of us most of the time, ignore this feeling and so act morally inappropriately. The feeling of respect is unique also, and relatedly, in that the susceptibility to experience it is “hard-wired” into human nature. In Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der bloßen Vernunft (Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason) (1793) Kant calls reverential respect for the moral law as it itself sufficient to motivate action the “predisposition to personality,” which is that “original predisposition” in human nature which makes it possible for us to be moral beings ( Religion 6:21–23).

As the way in which we are motivated to obey the moral law, reverential respect for the law is thus the way in which we are motivated to treat persons with recognition respect as the law commands us to do. However, there is another, deeper connection between respect for the law and respect for persons. For the discussion in the Critique makes it clear that reverential respect for the moral law is at the same time reverential respect for oneself, qua rational being, as the author of the law. Self-conceit, trying to esteem ourselves independently of moral considerations, is also the attempt to make our inclinations “lawgiving and the unconditional practical principle” ( Critique 5:74), i.e., to deny that the moral law is purely rational and unconditionally and supremely authoritative. Both attempts involve “illusion” (5:75), pretending that we do not feel reverence for the absolute worth and authority of the moral law and for our reason as its author and as supreme governor of our inclinations. In the Metaphysics of Morals Kant says that feeling of reverential self-respect, which the law “unavoidably forces from” us (6:403), is part of the subjective basis of morality, the predispositions to feeling that make possible for beings like us to acknowledge that we have binding moral duties (6:399–418), including the duty to treat ourselves as well as others always as ends in ourselves. There is, finally, one further interesting relation between respect for the law and respect for persons. Although Kant says that the moral law is the sole object of respect ( Groundwork 4:400, 401n), he also says that we experience this same humbling and uplifting feeling of respect for morally good people ( Critique 5:77ff). This feeling is both reverential respect for the moral law which such individuals exemplify ( Groundwork 4:401n) and a mode of evaluative respect, a “tribute” to their moral “merit” ( Critique 5:77). Kant holds that reverence for morally good people, like reverential respect for the moral law, is something we necessarily and unavoidably feel, although we might pretend we don't or refuse to acknowledge or show it. Reverential respect for morally good persons contrasts with the duty to give recognition respect to all persons in our attitudes and conduct, for the former is something we can't help feeling for some people, while the latter is a way we are obligated to comport ourselves toward all persons regardless of our feelings and their moral performance. We might, however, regard the two as linked, by regarding our recognition and appreciation of the dignity of others as involving a feeling that we can't help but experience and to which we commit ourselves to living up to in acknowledging the moral duty to respect persons just because they are persons (Hill 1998).

Philosophical discussions of respect since Kant have tended, on the one hand, to develop or apply various aspects of it, or on the other, to take issue with it or develop alternative accounts of respect. Some of the discussions have focused on more theoretical issues. For example, Kant gives the notion of respect for persons a central and vital role in moral theory. One issue that has since concerned philosophers is whether respect for persons is the definitive focus of morality, either in the sense that moral rightness and goodness and hence all specific moral duties, rights, and virtues are explainable in terms of respect or in the sense that the supreme moral principle from which all other principles are derived is a principle of respect for persons. Some philosophers have developed ethical theories in which a principle of respect for persons is identified as the fundamental and comprehensive moral requirement (for example, Donagan 1977, Downie and Telfer 1969). Others (for example, Hill 1993, Frankena 1986, Cranor 1975) argue that while respect for person is surely a very important moral consideration, it cannot be the principle from which the rest of morality is deduced. They maintain that there are moral contexts in which respect for persons is not an issue and that there are other dimensions of our moral relations with others that seem not to reduce to respect. Moreover, they argue, such a principle would seem not to provide moral grounds for believing that we ought to treat mentally incapacitated humans or nonhuman animals decently, or would (as Kant argues) make a duty to respect such beings only an indirect duty—one we have only because it is a way or respecting persons who value such beings or because our duty to respect ourselves requires that we not engage in activities that would dull our ability to treat persons decently—rather than a direct duty to such being (Kant 1787, 6:443).

Some theorists maintain that utilitarianism, a moral theory generally thought to be a rival to Kant's theory, is superior with regard to this last point. A utilitarian might argue that it is sentience rather than the capacity for rational autonomy that is the ground of moral recognition respect, and so would regard mentally incapacitated humans and nonhuman animals as having moral standing and so as worthy of at least some moral respect in themselves. Another issue, then, is whether utilitarianism (or more generally, consequentialism) can indeed accommodate a principle of respect for persons. In opposition to the utilitarian claim, some Kantians argue that Kant's ethics is distinguishable from consequentialist ethics precisely in maintaining that the fundamental demand of morality is not that we promote some value, such as the happiness of sentient beings, but that we respect the worth of humanity regardless of the consequences of doing so (Korsegaard 1996, Wood 1999). Thus, some philosophers argue that utilitarianism is inconsistent with respect for persons, inasmuch as utilitarianism, in requiring that all actions, principles, or motives promote the greatest good, requires treating persons as mere means on those occasions when doing so maximizes utility, whereas the very point of a principle of respect for persons is to rule out such trading of person and their dignity for some other value (Benn 1988, Brody 1982). In opposition, other theorists maintain not only that a consequentialist theory can accommodate the idea of respect for person (Downie and Telfer 1969, Gruzalski 1982, Landesman 1982, Pettit 1989, Cummiskey 1990), but also that utilitarianism is derivable from a principle of respect for persons (Downie and Telfer 1969) and that consequentialist theories provide a better grounding for duties to respect persons (Pettit 1989).

In addition to the debate between Kantian theory and utilitarianism, theoretical work has also been done in developing the role of respect for persons in Habermasian communicative ethics (Young 1997, Benhabib 1991) and in Aristotelian ethics (Jacobs 1995), in exploring similarities and differences between western (Kantian) views of respect for persons and Indian (Gosh-Dastidar 1987), Confucian (Chan 2006, Wawrytko 1982), and Taoist views (Wong 1984), and in developing a distinctively feminist account of respect for persons (Farley 1993, Dillon 1992a).

Other philosophical discussions have been concerned with clarifying the nature of the respect that is owed to persons and of the persons that are owed respect. Some of these discussions aim to refine and develop Kant's account, while others criticize it and offer alternatives. Darwall (2004, 2006) draws on Kant in revising his own understanding of the nature of recognition respect for persons, calling attention to an under-discussed dimension of the dignity of persons on Kant's account. Dignity is not only a worth but a status or standing, a position in the moral community. The standing is that of an equal, for rational beings have the same dignity. But it is also a standing or position from which claims or demands can be made. Dignity is, as Kant says in a passage from the Metaphysics of Morals quoted above, that “by which” rational beings “exact” or demand respect from one another (Kant 1797, 6: 435). As Darwall puts it, dignity is “the second-personal standing of an equal: the authority to make claims and demands on one another as free and rational agents” and to hold each other accountable for complying with these commands (Darwall 2004, 43, 44). Persons are just those beings who have the standing of authority to address demands to one another as persons. Moral recognition respect for the dignity of persons is acknowledging this authority; we respect one another as persons when we hold each other mutually accountable for complying with the demands that we acknowledge each person has the authority to make of each other person as free and rational agents. The reciprocal relations among persons as authoritative claims-makers and mutually accountable claims-responders is, in Darwall's view, one way of understanding the constitution of rational beings into the community of equal persons that Kant calls in the Groundwork a “kingdom of ends.”

Another area of interest has been the connections between respect and other attitudes and emotions, especially love. For example, Kant (1797) argues that we have duties of love to others just as we have duties of respect. However, neither the love nor the respect we owe is a matter of feeling (or, is pathological, as Kant says), but is, rather, a duty to adopt a certain kind of maxim, or policy of action: the duty of love is the duty to make the ends of others my own, the duty of respect is the duty to not degrade others to the status of mere means to my ends (Kant 1779, 6: 449–450). Love and respect, in Kant's view, are intimately united in friendship; nevertheless, they seem to be in tension with one another and respect seems to be the morally more important of the two, in that the duties of respect are stricter and respect constrains and limits love within friendship. Critics object to what they see here as Kant's devaluing of emotions, maintaining that emotions are morally significant dimensions of persons both as subjects and as objects of both respect and love. In response, some philosophers contend that respect and love are more similar and closely connected in Kant's theory than in generally recognized (Velleman 1999, Baron 1997, R. Johnson 1997). Others have developed accounts of respect that is or incorporates a form of love (agape) or care (Dillon 1992a, Downie and Telfer 1969, Maclagan 1960) and some have argued that emotions are included among the bases of dignity and that a complex emotional repertoire is necessary for Kantian respect (Wood 1999, Sherman 1998a, Farley 1993). In a related vein, some philosophers maintain that it is possible to acknowledge that another being is a person, i.e., a rational moral agent, and yet not have or give respect to that being. What is required for respecting a person is not simply recognizing what they are but emotionally experiencing their value as a person (Thomas 2001a, Buss 1999, Dillon 1997).

Another source of dissatisfaction with Kant's account has been with his characterization of persons and the quality in virtue of which they must be respected. In particular, Kant's view that the rational will which is common to all persons is the ground of respect is thought to ignore the moral importance of the concrete particularity of each individual, and his emphasis on autonomy, which is often understood to involve the independence of one person from all others, is thought to ignore the essential relationality of human beings person (for example, Noggle 1999, Farley 1993, Dillon 1992a, E. Johnson 1982). Rather than ignoring what distinguishes one person from another, it is argued, respect should involve attending to each person as a distinctive individual and to the concrete realities of human lives, and it should involve valuing difference as well as sameness and interdependence as well as independence. Other critics respond that respecting differences and particular identities inevitably reintroduces hierarchical discrimination that is antithetical to the equality among persons that the idea of respect for person is supposed to express (for example, Bird 2004). Identity and difference may, however, be appropriate objects of other forms of consideration and appreciation.

The idea of respect for particularity and relationality has also become an important topic recently in political philosophy. One issue is how persons ought to be respected in multicultural liberal democratic societies (for example, Balint 2006, Tomasi 1995, C. Taylor 1992, Kymlicka 1989). Respect for persons is one of the basic tenets of liberal democratic societies, which are founded on the ideal of the equal dignity of all citizens and which realize this ideal in the equalization of rights and entitlements among all citizens and so the rejection of discrimination and differential treatment. Some writers argue that respecting persons requires respecting the traditions and cultures that permeate and shape their individual identities (Addis 1997). But as the citizenry of such societies becomes increasingly more diverse and as many groups come to regard their identities or very existence as threatened by a homogenizing equality, liberal societies face the question of whether they should or could respond to demands to respect the unique identity of individuals or groups by differential treatment, such as extending political rights or opportunities to some cultural groups (for example, Native Americans, French Canadians, African-Americans) and not others .

The idea that all persons are owed respect has been applied in a wide variety of contexts. For instance, some philosophers employ it to justify various positions in normative ethics, such as the claim that persons have moral rights (Benn 1971, Feinberg 1970, Downie and Telfer 1969) or duties (Fried 1978, Rawls 1971), or to argue for principles of equality (Williams 1962), justice (Narveson 2002, Nussbaum 1999), and education (Andrews 1976). Others appeal to respect for persons in addressing a wide variety of practical issues such as abortion, racism and sexism, rape, punishment, physician-assisted suicide, pornography, affirmative action, forgiveness, terrorism, sexual harassment, cooperation with injustice, treatment of gays and lesbians, sexual ethics, and many others. One very important application context is biomedical ethics, where the principle of respect for autonomy is one of four basic principles that have become “the backbone of contemporary Western health care ethics” (Brannigan and Boss 2001, 39; see also Beauchamp and Childress 1979/2001 and, for example, Munson 2000, Beauchamp and Walters 1999). The idea of respect for patient autonomy has transformed health care practice, which had traditionally worked on physician-based paternalism, and the principle enters into issues such as informed consent, truthtelling, confidentiality, respecting refusals of life-saving treatment, the use of patients as subjects in medical experimentation, and so on.

Although persons are the paradigm objects of moral recognition respect, it is a matter of some debate whether they are the only things that we ought morally to respect. One serious objection raised against Kant's ethical theory is that in claiming that only rational beings are ends in themselves deserving of respect, it licenses treating all things which aren't persons as mere means to the ends of rational beings, and so it supports morally abhorrent attitudes of domination and exploitation toward all nonpersons and toward our natural environment. Taking issue with the Kantian position that only persons are respectworthy, many philosophers have argued that such nonpersons as humans who are not agents or not yet agents, human embryos, nonhuman animals, sentient creatures, plants, species, all living things, biotic communities, the natural ecosystem of our planet, and even mountains, rocks, and the AIDS virus have moral standing or worth and so are appropriate objects of or are owed moral recognition respect. Of course, it is possible to value such things instrumentally insofar as they serve human interests, but the idea is that such things matter morally and have a claim to respect in their own right, independently of their usefulness to humans. A variety of different strategies have been employed in arguing for such respect claims. For example, the concept of moral respect is sometimes stripped down to its bare essentials, omitting much of the content of the concept as it appears in respect for persons contexts. The respect that is owed to all things, it can be argued, is a very basic form of attentive contemplation of the object combined with a prima facie assumption that the object might have intrinsic value. This does not involve the valuing commitments that respect for persons does, since respectful consideration might reveal that the object does not have any positive value. What we owe everything is an opportunity to reveal any value it might have, rather than assuming that only persons have the kind of value that morally warrants attention (Birch 1993). Another strategy is to argue that the true grounds for moral worth and respect are other than or wider than rationality. One version of this strategy (employed by P. Taylor 1986) is to argue that all living things, persons and nonpersons, have equal inherent worth and so equally deserve the same kind of moral respect, because the ground of the worth of living things that are nonpersons is continuous with the ground of the worth for persons. For example, we regard persons as respect-worthy inasmuch as they are agents, centers of autonomous choice and valuation, and we can similarly regard all living things as respect-worthy in virtue of being quasi-agents, centers of organized activity that pursue their own good in their own unique way. It follows from this view that humans must not be regarded as having a moral status superior to other living beings and so human interests may not be regarded as always trumping claims of nonhumans. Respect for all living things would require settling conflicts between persons and nonpersons in ways that are fair to both. A third strategy, which is employed within Kantian ethics, is to argue that respect for persons logically entails respect for nonpersons. For example, one can argue that rational nature is to be respected not only by respecting humanity in someone's person but also by respecting things that bear certain relations to rational nature, for example, by being fragments of it or necessary conditions of it. Respect would thus be owed to humans who are not persons and to animals and other sentient beings (Wood 1998). Alternatively, one can argue that respect for persons requires respecting their values, and since many people value nature or other categories of nonpersons intrinsically and not just instrumentally, respect for persons requires (under certain conditions) also respecting what they respect (Gaus 1998). Yet another strategy is to reject the Kantian notion that there is but one kind or level of moral status or worth that warrants but one kind or level of respect. Instead, one might argue, we can acknowledge that rational moral agents have the highest moral standing and worth and are owed maximal respect, and also maintain that other beings have lesser but still morally significant standing or worth and so deserve less but still some respect. So, although it is always wrong to use moral agents merely as means, it may be justifiable to use nonpersons as means (for example, to do research on human embryos or human cadavers, destroying them in the process, or to kill animals for food) provided their moral worth is also respectfully acknowledged (for example, by not using them for trivial purposes, by destroying them only in certain ways, or by having an attitude of regret or loss because something of genuine moral value is sacrificed) (Meyer and Nelson, 2001). Much philosophical work has been done, particularly in environmental ethics, to determine the practical implications of the claim that things other than persons are owed respect. Certainly a wide variety of human practices, ranging from agriculture and urban development to recreation and energy use to technological and biomedical research, might have to be profoundly altered by a recognition of moral duties of respect to nonpersons.

4. Self-Respect

While there is much controversy about respect for persons and other things, there is surprising agreement among moral and political philosophers about at least this much concerning respect for oneself: self-respect is something of great importance in everyday life. Indeed, it is regarded both as morally required and as essential to the ability to live a satisfying, meaningful, flourishing life—a life worth living—and just as vital to the quality of our lives together. Saying that a person has no self-respect or acts in a way no self-respecting person would act, or that a social institution undermines the self-respect of some people, is generally a strong moral criticism. Nevertheless, as with respect itself, there is philosophical disagreement, both real and merely apparent, about the nature, scope, grounds, and requirements of self-respect. Self-respect is often defined as a sense of worth or as due respect for oneself; it is frequently (but not always correctly) identified with or compared to self-esteem, self-confidence, dignity, self-love, a sense of honor, self-reliance, pride, and it is contrasted (but not always correctly) with servility, shame, humility, self-abnegation, arrogance, self-importance. In addition to the questions philosophers have addressed about respect in general, a number of other questions have been of particular concern to those interested in self-respect, such as: (1) What is self-respect, and how is it different from related notions such as self-esteem, self-confidence, pride, and so on? (2) Are there objective conditions—for example, moral standards or correct judgments—that a person must meet in order to have self-respect, or is self-respect a subjective phenomenon that gains support from any sort of self-valuing without regard to correctness or moral acceptability? (3) Does respecting oneself conceptually or causally require or lead to respecting other persons (or anything else)? And how are respect for other persons and respect for oneself alike and unalike? (4) How is self-respect related to such things as moral rights, virtue, autonomy, integrity, and identity? (5) Is there a moral duty to respect ourselves as there is a duty to respect others? (6) What features of an individual's psychology and experience, what aspects of the social context, and what modes of interactions with others support or undermine self-respect? (7) Are social institutions and practices to be judged just or unjust (at least in part) by how they affect self-respect? Can considerations of self-respect help us to better understand the nature and wrongness of injustices such as oppression and to determine effective and morally appropriate ways to resist or end them?

Most generally, self-respect is a moral relation of persons (and only persons) to themselves that concerns their own intrinsic worth. Self-respect is thus essentially a valuing form of respect. Like respect for others, self-respect is a complex of multilayered and interpenetrating phenomena; it involves all those aspects of cognition, valuation, affect, expectation, motivation, action, and reaction that compose a mode of being in the world at the heart of which is an appreciation of oneself as having morally significant worth. Unlike some forms of respect, self-respect is not something one has only now and again or that might have no effect on its object. Rather, self-respect has to do with the structure and attunement of an individual's identity and of her life, and it reverberates throughout the self, affecting the configuration and constitution of the person's thoughts, desires, values, emotions, commitments, dispositions, and actions. As expressing or constituting one's sense of worth, it includes an engaged understanding of one's worth, as well as a desire and disposition to protect and preserve it. Accounts of self-respect differ in their characterizations of the beliefs, desires, affects, and behaviors that are constitutive of it, chiefly because of differences concerning the aspects or conception of the self insofar as it is the object of one's respect and the nature and grounds of the worth of the self or aspects of the self.

Most theorists agree that there as there are different kinds of respect, so there are different kinds of self-respect. However, we clearly cannot apply all kinds of respect to ourselves: it makes no sense to talk of directive respect for oneself, for instance, and although one might regard oneself or some of one's characteristics as obstacles (“I'm my own worst enemy”), this would not generally be considered a form of self-respect. Because the notion of self-worth is the organizing motif for self-respect, and because in the dominant Western tradition two kinds of worth are ascribed to persons, two kinds of self-respect can be distinguished. The first, recognition self-respect, centers on what we can call status worth, which is unearned worth that derives from such things as one's essential nature as a person, membership in a certain class, group, or people, social role, or place in a social hierarchy. Kantian dignity is one form, but not the only form, of status worth. Evaluative self-respect, in contrast, has to do with merit that is based on the quality of one's character and conduct. We earn or lose moral merit, and so deserve or don't deserve evaluative self-respect, through what we do or become. Different sources of status worth yield different configurations of recognition self-respect, but most contemporary discussions, heavily influenced by Kant, focus on dignity-based recognition self-respect. Recognition respect for oneself as a person, then, involves living in light of an understanding and appreciation of oneself as having dignity and moral status just in virtue of being a person, and of the moral constraints that arise from that dignity and status. All persons are morally obligated or entitled to have this kind of self-respect. Because the dominant Kantian conception of persons grounds dignity in three things—equality, agency, and individuality—we can further distinguish three kinds of recognition self-respect. The first is respect for oneself as a person among persons, as a member of the moral community with a status and dignity equal to every other person (see, for example, Thomas 1983a, Boxill 1976, Hill 1973). This involves having some conception the kinds of treatment from others that would count as one's due as a person and treatment that would be degrading or beneath one's dignity, desiring to be regarded and treated appropriately, and resenting and being disposed to protest disregard and disrespectful treatment. Thinking of oneself as having certain moral rights that others ought not to violate is part of this kind of self-respect; servility (regarding oneself as the inferior of others) and arrogance (thinking oneself superior to others) are among its opposites. The second kind of recognition self-respect involves an appreciation of oneself as an agent, a being with the ability and responsibility to act autonomously and value appropriately (see, for example, G. Taylor 1985, Telfer 1968). Persons who respect themselves as agents take their responsibilities seriously, especially their responsibilities to live in accord with their dignity as persons, to govern themselves fittingly, and to make of themselves and their lives something they believe to be good. So, self-respecting persons regard certain forms of acting, thinking, desiring, and feeling as befitting them as persons and other forms as self-debasing or shameful, and they expect themselves to adhere to the former and avoid the latter. They take care of themselves and seek to develop and use their talents and abilities in pursuit of their plans, projects, and goals. Those who are shameless, uncontrolled, weak-willed, self-consciously sycophantic, chronically irresponsible, slothfully dependent, self-destructive, or unconcerned with the shape and direction of their lives may be said to not respect themselves as agents. A third kind of recognition self-respect involves the appreciation of the importance of being autonomously self-defining, of having and living by a conception of a life that gives expression to the ideals and commitments and is expressed in the pursuits and projects that contribute to an individual's identity. Self-respecting people hold themselves to personal expectations and standards the disappointment of which they would regard as unworthy of them, shameful, even contemptible (although they may not apply these standards to others) (Hill 1982). People who sell out, betray their own values, live inauthentic lives, let themselves be defined by others, or are complacently self-accepting lack this kind of recognition self-respect.

Evaluative self-respect, which expresses confidence in one's merit as a person, rests on an appraisal of oneself in light of the normative self-conception that structures recognition self-respect. Recognition self-respecting persons are concerned to be the kind of person they think it is good and appropriate for them to be and they try to live the kind of life such a person should live. Thus they have and try to live by certain standards of worthiness by which they are committed to judge themselves. Indeed, they stake themselves, their value and their identities, on living in accord with these standards. Because they want to know where they stand, morally, they are disposed to reflectively examine and evaluate their character and conduct in light of their normative vision of themselves. And it matters to them that they are able to “bear their own survey,” as Hume says (1739 (1971), 620). Evaluative self-respect contains the judgment that one is or is becoming the worthy kind of person one seeks to be, and, more significantly, that one is not in danger of becoming an unworthy kind of person. Evaluative self-respect holds, at the least, the judgment that one “comes up to scratch,” as Telfer (1968) puts it. Those whose conduct is unworthy or whose character is shameful by their own standards do not deserve their own evaluative respect. However, people can be poor self-appraisers and their standards can be quite inappropriate to them or to any person, and so their evaluative self-respect, though still subjectively satisfying, can be unwarranted, as can the loss or lack of it. Interestingly, although philosophers have paid scant attention to evaluative respect for others, significant work has been done on evaluative self-respect. This may reflect an asymmetry between the two: although our evaluative respect for others may have no effect on them, perhaps because we don't express it or they don't value our appraisal, our own self-evaluation matters intensely to us and can powerfully affect our self-identity and the shape and structure of our lives. Indeed, an individual's inability to stomach herself can profoundly diminish the quality of her life, even her desire to continue living.

Some philosophers have contended that a third kind of self-valuing underlies both recognition and evaluative self-respect. It is a more basic sense of worth that enables an individual to develop the intellectually more sophisticated forms, a precondition for being able to take one's qualities or the fact that one is a person as grounds of positive self-worth. It has been called “basic psychological security” (Thomas 1989), “self-love” (Buss 1999), and “basal self-respect” (Dillon 1997). Basal self-valuing is our most fundamental sense of ourselves as mattering and our primordial interpretation of self and self-worth. Strong and secure basal self-respect can immunize an individual against personal failing or social denigration, but damage to basal self-respect, which can occur when people grow up in social, political, or cultural environments that devalue them or “their kind,” can make it impossible for people to properly interpret themselves and their self-worth, because it affects the way in which they assess reality and weigh reasons. Basal self-respect is thus the ground of the possibility of recognition and evaluative self-respect.

It is common in everyday discourse and philosophical discussion to treat self-respect and self-esteem as synonyms. It is true that evaluative self-respect and self-esteem both involve appraising oneself favorably in virtue of one's behavior and personal traits, and that a person can have or lack either one undeservedly. However, many philosophers have argued that the two attitudes are importantly different (for example, Darwall 1977, Sachs 1981, Chazen 1998, Harris, 2001, Dillon 2004). One way of distinguishing them is by their grounds and the points of view from which they are appraised. Evaluative self-respect involves an assessment from a moral point of view of one's character and conduct, while self-esteem can be based on personal features that are unrelated to character, and the assessment it involves need not be from a moral point of view: one can have a good opinion of oneself in virtue of being a good joke-teller or having won an important sports competition and yet not think one is a good person because of it (Darwall 1977). Another way of distinguishing them focuses on what it is to lose them: one would lose evaluative respect for oneself if one judged oneself to be shameful, contemptible, or intolerable, but self-esteem can be diminished by the belief that one lacks highly prized qualities that would add to one's merit (Harris 2001). Self-respect is also often identified with pride. In one sense, pride is the pleasure or satisfaction taken in one's achievements, possessions, or associations, and in this sense pride can be an affective element of either evaluative self-respect or self-esteem. In another sense, pride is inordinate self-esteem or vanity, an excessively high opinion of one's qualities, accomplishments, or status that can make one arrogant and contemptuous of others. In this sense, pride contrast with both well-grounded evaluative self-respect and the interpersonal kind of recognition self-respect. But pride can also be a claim to and celebration of a status worth or to equality with others, especially other groups (for example, Black Pride), which is interpersonal recognition self-respect; and pride can be “proper pride,” a sense of one's dignity that prevents one from doing what is unworthy, and in this sense it is the agentic dimension of recognition self-respect. Pride's opposites, shame and humility, are also closely related to self-respect. A loss of evaluative self-respect may be expressed in shame, but shameless people manifest a lack of recognition self-respect; and although humiliation can diminish or undermine recognition self-respect, humility is an appropriate dimension of the evaluative respect of any imperfect person.

One issue with which contemporary philosophers have been concerned is whether self-respect is an objective concept or a subjective one. If it is the former, then there are certain beliefs, attitudes, and dispositions a person must have to be self-respecting. A person who thought of herself as a lesser sort of being whose interests and well-being are less important than those of others would not count as having recognition self-respect, no matter how appropriate she regards her stance. If self-respect is a subjective concept, then a person counts as having self-respect so long as she believes she is not tolerating treatment she regards as unworthy or behaving in ways she thinks is beneath her, regardless of whether her judgments about herself are accurate or her standards or sense of what she is due are judged by others to be reasonable or worthy (Massey 1983a). Psychologists, for whom “self-esteem” is the term of practice, tend to regard the various dimensions of a person's sense of worth as subjective. Many philosophers treat the interpersonal dimension of recognition self-respect objectively, and it is generally thought that having manifestly inaccurate beliefs about oneself is good grounds for at least calling an individual's sense of worth unjustified or compromised (Meyers 1989). But there is no consensus regarding the standards to which individuals hold themselves and by which they judge themselves, and certainly the standards of the self-defining dimension of recognition self-respect are inescapably, though perhaps not exclusively, subjective. Complicating the objective/subjective distinction, however, is the fact of the social construction of self-respect. What it is to be a person or to have a status worthy of respect, what treatment and conduct are appropriate to a person or one with such a status, what forms of life and character have merit—all of these are given different content in different sociocultural contexts. Individuals necessarily, though perhaps not inalterably, learn to engage with themselves and with issues of self-worth in the terms and modes of the sociocultural conceptions in which they have been immersed. And different kinds of individuals may be given different opportunities in different sociocultural contexts to acquire or develop the grounds of the different kinds of self-respect (Dillon 1997, Moody-Adams 1992–93, Meyers 1989, Thomas 1983b). Even fully justified self-respect may thus be less than strongly objective and more than simply subjective.

Self-respect is frequently appealed to as a means of justifying a wide variety of philosophical claims or positions, generally in arguments of the form: x promotes (or undermines) self-respect; therefore, x is to that extent to be morally approved (or objected to). For example, appeals to self-respect have been used to argue for, among many other things, the value of moral rights (Feinberg 1970), moral requirements or limits regarding forgiving others or oneself (Dillon 2001; Holmgren 1998, 1993; Novitz 1998; Haber 1991; Murphy 1982), and both the rightness and wrongness of practices such as affirmative action. Such arguments rely on rather than establish the moral importance of self-respect. Most philosophers who attend to self-respect tend to treat it as important in one of two ways, which are exemplified in the very influential work of Kant and John Rawls. Kant argues that, just as we have a moral duty to respect others as persons, so we have a moral duty to respect ourselves as persons, a duty that derives from our dignity as rational beings. This duty requires us to act always in an awareness of our dignity and so to act only in ways that are consistent with our status as end in ourselves and to refrain from acting in ways that abase, degrade, defile, or disavow our rational nature. That is, we have a duty of recognition self-respect. In Die Metaphysik der Sitten (The Metaphysics of Morals) (1797) Kant argues for specific duties to oneself generated by the general duty to respect humanity in our persons, including duties to not engage in suicide, misuse of our sexual powers, drunkenness and other unrestrained indulgence of inclination, lying, self-deception, avarice, and servility. Kant also maintains that the duty of self-respect is the most important moral duty, for unless there were duties to respect oneself, there could be no moral duties at all. Moreover, fulfilling our duty to respect ourselves is a necessary condition of fulfilling our duties to respect other persons. Kant maintains that we are always aware of our dignity as persons and so of our moral obligation to respect ourselves, and he identifies this awareness as a feeling of reverential respect for ourselves. This is one of the natural capacities of feeling which we could have no duty to acquire but that make it possible for us to be motivated by the thought of duty. Reverence for self is, along with “moral feeling,” conscience, and love of others, a subjective source of morality, and it is the motivational ground of the duty of self-respect. Kant also discusses evaluative self-respect, especially in Critik der practischen Vernuft (Critique of Practical Reason) (1788) and his Lectures on Ethics (1779), as a combination of noble pride, the awareness that we have honored and preserved our dignity by acting in morally worthy ways, and a healthy dose of humility, the awareness that we inevitably fall short of the lofty requirements of the moral law. Kant regards well-grounded evaluative self-respect as a subjective motivation to continue striving to do right and be good.

Rawls, by contrast, views self-respect neither as something we are morally required to have and maintain nor as a feeling we necessarily have, but as an entitlement that social institutions are required by justice to support and not undermine. In A Theory of Justice (1971) he argues that self-respect is a “primary good,” something that rational beings want whatever else they want, because it is vital to the experienced quality of individual lives and to the ability to carry out or achieve whatever projects or aims an individual might have. It is, moreover, a social good, one that individuals are able to acquire only under certain social and political conditions. Rawls defines self-respect as including “a person's sense of his own value, his secure conviction that his conception of the good, his plan of life, is worth carrying out,” and it implies “a confidence in one's ability, so far as it is within one's power, to fulfill one's intentions” (1971, 440). He argues that individuals' access to self-respect is to a large degree a function of how the basic institutional structure of a society defines and distributes the social bases of self-respect, which include the messages about the relative worth of citizens that are conveyed in the structure and functioning of institutions, the distribution of fundamental political rights and civil liberties, access to the resources individuals need to pursue their plans of life, the availability of diverse associations and communities within which individuals can seek affirmation of their worth and their plans of life from others, and the norms governing public interaction among citizens. Since self-respect is vital to individual well-being, Rawls argues that justice requires that social institutions and policies be designed to support and not undermine self-respect. Rawls argues that the principles of justice as fairness are superior to utilitarian principles insofar as they better affirm and promote self-respect for all citizens.

Rawls's view that the ability of individuals to respect themselves is heavily dependent on their social and political circumstances has been echoed by a number of theorists working in moral, social, and political philosophy. For example, Margalit (1996) argues that a decent society is one whose institutions do not humiliate people, that is, give people good reason to consider their self-respect to be injured. Honneth's theory of social criticism (1995) focuses on the way people's self-respect and self-identity necessarily depend on the recognition of others and so are vulnerable to being misrecognized or ignored both by social institutions and in interpersonal interactions. A number of theorists have used the concept of self-respect to examine the oppression of women, people of color, gays and lesbians, and other groups that are marginalized, stigmatized, or exploited by the dominant culture, identifying the plethora of ways in which oppressive institutions, images, and actions can damage to the self-respect of members of these groups. Other writers discuss ways that individuals and groups might to preserve or restore self-respect in the face of injustice or oppression, and the ways in which the development of self-respect in individuals living under oppression or injustice empowers them to participate in the monumental struggles for justice and liberation (for example, Babbitt 2000, 1993; Bartky 1990a, 1990b, 1990c; Boxill 1992, 1977; Collins 1990; Dillon 1997, 1995; Meyers 1989, 1986; Mohr 1992, 1988; Moody-Adams 1992–93; Statman 2002; Thomas 2001b, 1983, 1978–79). Some theorists, especially those working within a feminist framework, have argued that the prevailing conceptions of self-respect in contemporary liberal societies themselves contain features that reflect objectionable aspects of the dominating culture, and they have attempted to reconceive self-respect in ways that are more conducive to empowerment and emancipation (for example, Dillon 1992c).

Everyday discourse and practices insist that respect and self-respect are personally, socially, politically, and morally important, and philosophical discussions of the concepts bear this out. Their roles in our lives as individuals, as people living in complex relations with other people and surrounded by a plethora of other beings and things on which our attitudes and actions have tremendous effects, cannot, as these discussions reveal, be taken lightly. The discussions thus far shed light on the nature and significance of the various forms of respect and self-respect and their positions in a nexus of profoundly important but philosophically challenging and contestable concepts. These discussions also reveal that much more work remains to be done in clarifying these attitudes and their places among and implications for our concepts and our lives.

Bibliography

  • Addis, A., 1997, “On Human Diversity and the Limits of Toleration,” in Ethnicity and Group Rights , Nomos 39, I. Shapiro and W. Kymlicka (eds.), New York: New York University Press.
  • Anderson, E., 1999, “What is the Point of Equality?” Ethics 109: 287–337.
  • –––, 1993, Value in Ethics and Economics , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Andrews, J.N., 1976, “Social Education and Respect for Others,” Journal of Moral Education 5: 139–143.
  • Armitage, F., 2006, “Respect and Types of Injustice,” Res Publica 12: 9–34.
  • Arnold, D.G. and Bowie, N.E., 2005, “Sweatshops and Respect,” in Ethical Issues for the Twenty-First Century , F. Adams (ed.), Charlottesville: Philosophy Documentation Center.
  • Arrington, R. L., 1978, “On Respect,” Journal of Value Inquiry 12: 1–12.
  • Atwell, J.E., 1982, “Kant's Notion of Respect for Persons,” in Respect for Persons , O.H. Green (ed.), Tulane Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 31, New Orleans: Tulane University Press.
  • Bagnoli, C., 2007, “Respect and Membership in the Moral Community,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10: 113–128.
  • –––, 2003, “Respect and Loving Attention,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33: 483–516.
  • Baldner, K., 1990, “Realism and Respect,” Between the Species 6: 1–8.
  • Balint, P., 2006, “Respect Relations in Diverse Societies,” Res Publica 12: 35–57.
  • Barilan, M.Y. and Weintraub, M., 2001, “Persuasion as Respect for Persons: An Alternative View of Autonomy and the Limits of Discourse,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 26: 13–33.
  • Barnes, A., 1990, “Some Remarks on Respect and Human Rights,” Philosophical Studies , (Ireland): 263–273.
  • Baron, M.W., 1997, “Love and Respect in the Doctrine of Virtue ,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy 36 (Supplement): 29–44.
  • Beauchamp, T.L. and Childress, J.F., 1979/2001, Principles of Biomedical Ethics , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– and Walters, L., 1999, Contemporary Issues in Bioethics , 5 th edition, Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
  • Benditt, T., 2008, “Why Respect Matters,” Journal of Value Inquiry 42:487–496.
  • Benhabib, S., 1991, Situating the Self , New York: Routledge.
  • Benn, S.I., 1971, “Privacy, Freedom, and Respect for Persons,” in Privacy , Nomos 13, J. R. Pennock and J. W. Chapman (eds.), New York: Atherton Press.
  • –––, 1988, A Theory of Freedom , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Berger, P., 1970, “On the Obsolescence of the Concept of Honor,” European Journal of Sociology 11: 339–347. Reprinted in Revisions: Changing Perspectives in Moral Philosophy , S. Hauerwas and A. MacIntyre (eds.), Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983.
  • Birch, T.H., 1993, “Moral Considerability and Universal Consideration,” Environmental Ethics 15: 313–332.
  • Bird, Colin, 2004, “Status, Identity, and Respect,” Political Theory 32: 207–232.
  • Blum, A., 1988, “On Respect,” Philosophical Inquiry 10: 58–63.
  • Boettcher, J., 2007, “Respect, Recognition, and Public Reason,” Social Theory and Practice 33: 223–249.
  • Brannigan, M.C. and Boss, J.A., 2001, Health Care Ethics in a Diverse Society , Mountain View, CA: Mayfield.
  • Broadie, A. and Pybus, E.M., 1975, “Kant's Concept of 'Respect',” Kant-Studien 66: 58–64.
  • Brody, B.A., 1982, “Towards a Theory of Respect for Persons,” in Respect for Persons , O.H. Green (ed.), Tulane Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 31, New Orleans: Tulane University Press.
  • Buss, S., 1999, “Respect for Persons,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29: 517–550.
  • Cary, P., 1996, “Believing the Word: A Proposal about Knowing Other Persons,” Faith and Philosophy 13: 78–90.
  • Chan, S., 2006, “The Confucian Notion of Jing (Respect),” Philosophy East and West 56: 229–252.
  • Code, L., 1987, “Persons and Others,” in Power, Gender, Values , J. Genova (ed), Edmonton, Alberta: Academic Printing and Publishing.
  • Cohen, S., 2008, “Fundamental Equality and the Phenomenology of Respect,” Iyyun 57: 25–53.
  • Connelly, J., 2006, “Respecting Nature?” Res Publica 12: 97–105.
  • Cooke, M., 1995, “Selfhood and Solidarity,” Constellations 1: 337–357.
  • Cooper, D.E., 2000, “The Virtue of Practical Reason and Moral Respect Across Cultures,” Contemporary Philosophy , 22: 20-28.
  • Cottingham, J., 1983, “Punishment and Respect for Persons,” in Law, Morality, and Rights , M.A. Stewart (ed.), Dordrecht: Reidel.
  • Cranor, C.F., 1983, “On Respecting Human Beings as Persons,” Journal of Value Inquiry 17: 103–117.
  • –––, 1982, “Limitations on Respect-for-Persons Theories,” in Respect for Persons , O.H. Green (ed.), Tulane Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 31, New Orleans: Tulane University Press.
  • –––, 1980, “Kant's Respect-for-Persons Principle,” International Studies in Philosophy : 19–40.
  • –––, 1975, “Toward a Theory of Respect for Persons,” American Philosophical Quarterly 12: 309–320.
  • Cummiskey, D., 2008, “Dignity, Contractualism, and Consequentialism,” Utilitas 16:629–644.
  • –––,1990, “Kantian Consequentialism,” Ethics 100: 586–615.
  • Darby, D., 1999, “Are Worlds without Natural Rights Morally Impoverished?” Southern Journal of Philosophy , 37: 397–417.
  • Darwall, S., 2006, The Second Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 2004, “Respect and the Second Person Standpoint,” Presidential Address, Central Division of the American Philosophical Association, in Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 78 (2): 43–59.
  • –––, 2001, “Because I Want It,” Social Philosophy and Policy 18: 129–153.
  • –––, 1977, “Two Kinds of Respect,” Ethics 88: 36–49; reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect , R.S. Dillon (ed.), New York: Routledge, 1995.
  • Deigh, J., 1982, “Respect and the Right to be Punished,” Tulane Studies in Philosophy 31: 169–182.
  • Delue, S., 2006, “Martin Buber and Immanuel Kant on Mutual Respect and the Liberal State,” Janus Head 9: 117–137.
  • DeMarco, J.P., 1974, “Respect for Persons: Some Prerequisites,” Philosophy in Context 3: 33–37.
  • Deveaux, M., 1998, “Toleration and Respect,” Public Affairs Quarterly 12: 407–427.
  • Diggs, B.J., 1981, “A Contractarian View of Respect for Persons,” American Philosophical Quarterly 18: 273–283.
  • Dillon, R.S., 2009, “Respect for Persons, Identity, and Information Technology,” Ethics and Information Technology 11 (2).
  • –––, 1992a, “Respect and Care: Toward Moral Integration,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22: 105–132.
  • –––, 1991, “Care and Respect,” in Explorations in Feminist Ethics: Theory and Practice , E.B. Cole and S. Coultrap-McQuin (eds.), Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
  • Donagan, A., 1977, The Theory of Morality . Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Downie, R.S., and Telfer, E., 1969, Respect for Persons , London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • Drummond, J., 2006, “Respect as a Moral Emotion: A Phenomenological Approach,” Husserl Studies 22: 1–27.
  • Dworkin, R., 1985, “Liberalism,” in A Matter of Principle . Cambridge, U.K.: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1977, Taking Rights Seriously , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Edel, A., 1974, “The Place of Respect for Persons in Moral Philosophy,” Philosophy in Context 3: 23–32.
  • Falls, M., 1987, “Retribution, Reciprocity, and Respect for Persons,” Law and Philosophy 6: 25–51.
  • Farley, M.A., 1993, “A Feminist Version of Respect for Persons,” Journal of Feminist Studies in Religion 9: 183–198.
  • Feinberg, J., 1975, “Some Conjectures on the Concept of Respect,” Journal of Social Philosophy 4: 1–3.
  • –––, 1970, “The Nature and Value of Rights,” Journal of Value Inquiry 4: 243–260.
  • Fotion, N. and Elfstrom, G., 1992, “Honor,” in Encyclopedia of Ethics , L.C. Becker and C.B. Becker (eds.), New York: Garland Publishing, Inc.
  • Frankena, W.K., 1986, “The Ethics of Respect for Persons,” Philosophical Topics 14: 149–167.
  • Frankfurt, H.G., 1999, “Equality and Respect,” in Necessity, Volition, and Love , Frankfurt, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Fried, C., 1978, Right and Wrong , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Garry, A., 1978, “Pornography and Respect for Women,” Social Theory and Practice 4: 395–421.
  • Gaus, G.F., 1998, “Respect for Persons and Environmental Values,” in Autonomy and Community: Readings in Contemporary Kantian Social Philosophy , J. Kneller and S. Axinn (eds.), Albany: State University of New York Press.
  • Gauthier, D., 1963, Practical Reasoning , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Gaylin, W., 1984, “In Defense of the Dignity of Being Human,” The Hastings Center Report 14: 18–22.
  • Ghosh-Dastidar, K., 1987, “Respect for Persons and Self-Respect: Western and Indian,” Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research 5: 83–93.
  • Gibbard, A., 1990, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Giordano, S., 2005, “Respect for Equality and the Treatment of the Elderly,” Cambridge Quarterly of Heathcare Ethics 14: 83–92.
  • Goodin, R., 1981, “The Political Theories of Choice and Dignity,” American Philosophical Quarterly 8: 91–100.
  • Green, O.H., ed., 1982, Respect for Persons , Tulane Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 31, New Orleans: Tulane University Press.
  • Grenberg, J., 1999, “Anthropology from a Metaphysical Point of View,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 37: 91–115.
  • Griffin, J., 1986, Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Importance , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Gruzalski, B., 1982, “Two Accounts of Our Obligations to Respect Persons,” in Respect for Persons , O.H. Green (ed.), Tulane Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 31, New Orleans: Tulane University Press.
  • Hare, S., 1996, “The Paradox of Moral Humility,” American Philosophical Quarterly 33: 235–241.
  • Harris, E.E., 1966, “Respect for Persons,” in Ethics and Society: Original Essays on Contemporary Moral Problems , R. DeGeorge (ed.), Garden City, NJ: Anchor.
  • Hepburn, R.W., 1998, “Nature Humanized: Nature Respected,” Environmental Values 7: 267–279.
  • Herman, B., 1984, “Mutual Aid and Respect for Persons,” Ethics 94: 577–602.
  • Hicks, D.C., 1971, “Respect for Persons and Respect for Living Things,” Philosophy 46: 346–348.
  • Hill, T.E., Jr., 2000, Respect, Pluralism, and Justice: Kantian Perspectives , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 1998, “Respect for Persons,” Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy , E. Craig (ed.), London: Routledge.
  • –––, 1997, “Respect for Humanity,” in The Tanner Lectures on Human Values xviii, G. B. Peterson (ed.), Salt-Lake City: University of Utah Press; reprinted in Hill, Respect, Pluralism, and Justice.
  • –––, 1993, “Donagan's Kant,” Ethics 104: 22–52; reprinted in Hill, Respect, Pluralism, and Justice.
  • –––, 1992, Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant's Moral Theory , Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • Hinton, T., 2001, “Must Egalitarians Choose Between Fairness and Respect?” Philosophy and Public Affairs 30: 72–87.
  • Hobbes, T., 1958 (1651), Leviathan , Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, The Library of Liberal Arts.
  • Holmgren, M., 1993, “Forgiveness and the Intrinsic Value of Persons,” American Philosophical Quarterly 30: 341–352.
  • Honneth, A., 1992, “Integrity and Disrespect: Principles of a Conception of Morality Based on the Theory of Recognition,” Political Theory 20: 187–201.
  • Hudson, S.D., 1980, “The Nature of Respect,” Social Theory and Practice 6: 69–90.
  • Hume, D., 1875, “On the Dignity of Human Nature,” in Essays: Moral, Political and Literary , vol 1, T.H. Green and T.H. Grose (eds.), London: Longmans, Green, and Co.
  • Jacobs, J., 1995, Practical Realism and Moral Psychology , Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.
  • Johnson, E., 1982, “Ignoring Persons,” in Respect for Persons , O.H. Green (ed.), Tulane Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 31, New Orleans: Tulane University Press.
  • Johnson, R., 1997, “Love in Vain,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy 36 (Supplement): 45–50.
  • Kant, I., 1785, Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten , translated as Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals , by H.J. Paton, New York: Harper and Row, 1964.
  • –––, 1788, Critik der practischen Vernuft , translated as Critique of Practical Reason , by L. W. Beck, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1956.
  • –––, 1793, Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der bloßen Vernunft , translated as Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason , by A. Wood and G. di Giovanni, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
  • –––, 1797, Die Metaphysik der Sitten , translated as The Metaphysics of Morals , by M. Gregor, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
  • –––, 1779, Lectures on Ethics , P. Heath and J.B. Schneewind (eds.), P. Heath (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
  • Katz, M.S., 1992, “Respect for Persons and Students: Charting Some Ethical Territory,” Philosophy of Education Proceedings 19, Normal, IL: Illinois State University, Philosophy of Education Society.
  • Kent, E., 1976, “Respect for Persons and Social Protest,” in Social Ends and Political Means , T. Honderich (ed.), London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
  • Kershnar, S., 2004, “Respect for Persons and the Harsh Punishment of Criminals,” International Journal of Applied Philosophy 18: 103–121.
  • Klimchuk, D., 2004,“Three Accounts of Respect for Persons in Kant's Ethics,” Kantian Review 8: 38–61.
  • Kleinig, J., 1991, Valuing Life , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Kofman, S., 1997, “The Economy of Respect: Kant and Respect for Women,” N. Fisher (trans.), in Feminist Interpretations of Immanuel Kant , Robin May Schott (ed.), University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.
  • Kolnai, A., 1976, “Dignity,” Philosophy 5: 251–271; reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect , R.S. Dillon (ed.), New York: Routledge, 1995.
  • Korsgaard, C.M., 1996, Creating the Kingdom of Ends , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Kymlika, W., 1989, Liberalism, Community and Culture , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • LaCaze, M., 2005, “Love, That Indispensable Supplement: Irigaray and Kant on Love and Respect,” Hypatia 20: 92–114.
  • Landesman, C., 1982, “Against Respect for Persons,” in Respect for Persons , O.H. Green (ed.), Tulane Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 31, New Orleans: Tulane University Press.
  • Larmore, C.E., 1987, Patterns of Moral Complexity , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • LeMoncheck, L., 1997, Loose Women, Lecherous Men: A Feminist Philosophy of Sex , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Lippke, R.L., 1998, “Arguing Against Inhumane and Degrading Punishing,” Criminal Justice Ethics 17: 29–41.
  • Lombardi, L., 1983, “Inherent Worth, Respect, and Rights,” Environmental Ethics 5: 257–270.
  • Lueck, B., 2008, “Toward a Serresian Reconceptualization of Kantian Respect,” Philosophy Today 52: 52–59.
  • Lysaught, M., 2004, “Respect: Or, How Respect for Persons Became Respect for Autonomy,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 29: 665–680.
  • Maclagan, W.G., 1960, “Respect for Persons as a Moral Principle,” Philosophy 35: 199–305.
  • Markie, P. J., 2004, “Respect for People and Animals,” Journal of Value Inquiry 38: 33–47.
  • McBride, W.L., 2000, “Sexual Harassment, Seduction, and Mutual Respect: An Attempt at Sorting it Out,” in Feminist Phenomenology , L. Fisher (ed.), Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher.
  • McCarty, R., 1994, “Motivation and Moral Choice in Kant's Theory of Rational Agency,” Kant-Studien 85 : 15–31.
  • –––, 1993, “Kantian Moral Motivation and the Feeling of Respect,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 31: 421–435.
  • Meehan, J., 1994, “Autonomy, Recognition and Respect: Habermas, Benjamin, Honneth,” Constellations 1: 270-285.
  • Melden, A.I., 1992, “Dignity, Worth, and Rights,” in The Constitution of Rights: Human Dignity and American Values , M. J. Meyer and W.A. Parent (eds.), Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 1977, Rights and Persons , Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • Meyer, M.J. and L.J. Nelson, 2001, “Respecting What We Destroy: Reflections on Human Embryo Research,” Hastings Center Report 31: 16–23.
  • Metz, T., 2001, “Respect for Persons and Perfectionist Politics,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 30: 417–442.
  • Miller, R.W., 1998, “Cosmopolitan Respect and Patriotic Concern,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 27: 202–224.
  • Moland, L., 2002, “Fight, Flight, or Respect? First Encounters of the Other in Kant and Hegel,” History of Philosophy Quarterly 19: 381–400.
  • Morrison, I., 2004, “Respect in Kant: How the Moral Feeling of Respect Acts as an Incentive to Moral Action,” Southwest Philosophy Review 20(2): 1–26.
  • Munson, R., 2000, Intervention and Reflection: Basic Issues in Medical Ethics , 6 th edition, Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
  • Narveson, J., 2002a, Respecting Persons in Theory and Practice: Essays on Moral and Political Philosophy , Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
  • –––, 2002b, “Race, Social Identity, Human Dignity: Respect for Individuals,” in Social Philosophy Today: Race, Social Identity, and Human Dignity , vol. 16, C. L. Hughes (ed.), Bowling Green: Philosophy Documentation Center.
  • Neumann, M., 2005, “Can't We All Just Respect One Another a Little Less?” Canadian Journal of Philosophy , 34: 463–484.
  • –––, 2000, “Did Kant Respect Persons?” Res Publica 6: 285–299.
  • Noggle, R., 1999, “Kantian Respect and Particular Persons,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29: 449–477.
  • Norman, R., 1989, “Respect for Persons, Autonomy, and Equality,” Revue International de Philosophie 43: 323–341.
  • Nussbaum, M., 2003, “Political Liberalism and Respect,” SATS: Nordic Journal of Philosophy 4: 25–44.
  • –––, 1999, Sex and Social Justice , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Nyberg, D., 1991, “The Basis of Respect is Empathy,” Philosophy of Education 47: 197–201.
  • Paetzold, H., 2008, “Respect and Toleration Reconsidered,” Philosophy and Social Criticism 941–954.
  • Palmer, C., 2004, “'Respect for Nature' in the Earth Charter: The Value of Species and the Value of Individuals,” Ethics, Place, and Environment 7: 97–107.
  • Panichas, G.E., 2000, “Rights, Respect, and the Decent Society,” Journal of Social Philosophy 31: 51–67.
  • Partridge, E., 1981, “Posthumous Interests and Posthumous Respect,” Ethics 91: 243–264.
  • Pettit, P., 1989, “Consequentialism and Respect for Persons,” Ethics 100: 116–126.
  • Preus, A., 1991, “Aristotle and Respect for Persons,” in Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy IV, J. P. Anton (ed.), Albany: State University Of New York Press.
  • Raz, J., 2002, “On Frankfurt's Explanation of Respect for People,” in Contours of Agency: Essays on Themes from Harry Frankfurt , S. Buss (ed), Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.
  • –––, 2001, Value, Respect, and Attachment , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Reath, A., 2006, “Kant's Theory of Moral Sensibility: Respect for the Moral Law and the Influence of Inclination”, in Reath, Agency and Autonomy in Kant's Moral Theory , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Richardson, H.S., 1998, “Nussbaum: Love and Respect,” Metaphilosophy 29: 254–262.
  • Rolston III, H., 2004, “Caring for Nature: From Fact to Value, From Respect to Reverence,” Zygon 39: 277–302.
  • Schmidt, L.K., 2000, “Respecting Others: The Hermeneutic Virtue,” Continental Philosophy Review 33: 359–379.
  • Schmidtz, D., 2002, “Equal Respect and Equal Shares,” Social Philosophy and Policy 19: 244–274.
  • –––, 1998, “Are All Species Equal?” Journal of Applied Philosophy 15: 57–67.
  • Shafer, C.M. and Frye, M., 1977, “Rape and Respect,” in Feminism and Philosophy , M. Vetterling-Braggin, F.A. Elliston, and J. English (eds.), Totowa, N.J.: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Sherman, N., 1998a, “Concrete Kantian Respect,” Social Philosophy and Policy 15: 119–148.
  • –––, 1998b, “Empathy, Respect, and Humanitarian Intervention,” Ethics and International Affairs 12: 103–119.
  • Shields, P.R., 1998, “Some Reflections on Respecting Childhood,” Journal of Value Inquiry 32: 369–380.
  • Shockley, K., 2009, “Practice dependent Respect,”, Journal of Value Inquiry 43: 41–54.
  • Simpson, E., 1979, “Objective Reasons and Respect for Persons,” Monist 62: 457–469.
  • Singleton, J., 2007, “Kant's Account of Respect: A Bridge Between Rationality and Anthropology,” Kantian Review , 12: 40-60.
  • Skorupski, J., 2005, “Blame, Respect, and Recognition: A Reply to Theo Van Willigenberg,” Utilitas 17(3): 333–347.
  • Smith, D.H., ed., 1984, Respect and Care in Medical Ethics , Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
  • Spelman, E.V., 1977, “On Treating Persons as Persons,” Ethics 88: 150-161.
  • Stith, R., 2004, “The Priority of Respect: How Our Common Humanity Can Ground Our Individual Dignity,” International Philosophical Quarterly 44(2): 165–184.
  • Stratton-Lake, P., 2000, Kant, Duty, and Moral Worth , London: Routledge.
  • Strauss, M., 2003, “The Role of Recognition in the Formation of Self-Understanding,” in Recognition, Responsibility, and Rights , R. N. Fiore and H. L. Nelson (eds.), Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Taylor, C., 1992, “The Politics of Recognition,” in Multiculturalism and “The Politics of Recognition ,” A. Gutmann (ed.), Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Taylor, P.W., 1986, Respect for Nature , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 1981, “The Ethics of Respect for Nature,” Environmental Ethics 3: 197–218.
  • Thomas, L., 2001a, “Morality, Consistency, and the Self: A Lesson in Rectification,” Journal of Social Philosophy , 32: 374–381.
  • –––, 1992–93, “Moral Deference,” The Philosophical Forum 24: 233–250.
  • Tomasi, J., 1995, “Kymlika, Liberalism, and Respect for Cultural Minorities,” Ethics 105: 580-603.
  • Velleman, J.D., 1999, “Love as a Moral Emotion,” Ethics 109: 338–374.
  • Wawrytko, S.A., 1982, “Confucius and Kant: The Ethics of Respect,” Philosophy East and West 32: 237–257.
  • Westra, L., 1989, “'Respect,' 'Dignity,' and 'Integrity:' An Environmental Proposal for Ethics,” Epistemologia 12: 91–123.
  • Wiggens, D., 2000, “Nature, Respect for Nature, and the Human Scale of Values,” Presidential Address, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100: 1–32.
  • Williams, B.A.O., 1962, “The Idea of Equality,” in Politics, Philosophy, and Society , vol. 2, P. Laslett and W. G. Runciman (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Wolff, J., 1998, “Fairness, Respect, and Egalitarian Ethics,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 27: 97–122.
  • Woodruff, P., 2003, “Reverence, Respect, and Dependence,” in Virtues of Independence and Dependence on Virtues ,, L. Beckman (ed.), New Brunswick: Transactional Press.
  • Wong, D., 1984, “Taoism and the Problem of Equal Respect,” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 11: 165–183.
  • Wood, A.W., 1999, Kant's Ethical Thought , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 1998, “Kantian Duties Regarding Nonrational Nature,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , Supp. 72: 189–210.
  • Young, I.M., 1997, “Asymmetrical Reciprocity: On Moral Respect, Wonder, and Enlarged Thought,” Constellations , 3: 340-363.
  • Zinkin, M., 2006, “Respect for the Law and the Use of Dynamic Terms in Kant's Theory of Moral Motivation,” Archiv fur Geschichte der Philosophie 88: 31–53.
  • Adler, M.J., et al., 1952, “Honor,” in The Great Ideas: A Syntopicon of Great Books of the Western World , Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc.
  • Aristotle, 1941, Nichomachean Ethics , W.D. Ross (trans.), in Basic Works of Aristotle , R. McKeon (ed.), New York: Random House.
  • Babbitt, S., 2000, Artless Integrity: Moral Imagination, Agency, and Stories , Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • –––, 1993, “Feminism and Objective Interests: The Role of Transformation Experiences in Rational Deliberation,” in Feminist Epistemologies , L. Alcoff and E. Potter (eds.), New York: Routledge.
  • Balaief, L., 1975, “Self-Esteem and Human Equality,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 36: 25–43.
  • Bartky, S.L., 1990a, “Feminine Masochism and the Politics of Personal Transformation,” in Bartky, Femininity and Domination: Studies in the Phenomenology of Oppression , New York: Routledge.
  • –––, 1990b, “On Psychological Oppression,” Bartky, Femininity and Domination.
  • –––, 1990c, “Shame and Gender,” in Bartky, Femininity and Domination .
  • Becker, L.C., 1992, “Pride,” in Encyclopedia of Ethics , L. C. Becker and C. B. Becker (eds.), New York: Garland Publishing, Inc.
  • Bernick, M., 1978, “A Note on Promoting Self-Esteem,” Political Theory 6: 109–118.
  • Bloomfield, P., 2008, “The Harm of Immorality” Ratio 21: 241–259.
  • Boxill, B.R., 1992, Blacks and Social Justice , Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • –––, 1976, “Self-Respect and Protest,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 6: 58–69; reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect , R.S. Dillon (ed.), New York: Routledge, 1995.
  • Braybrooke, D., 1983, Ethics in the World of Business , Totowa, N.J.: Rowman & Allenheld.
  • Campbell, R., 1979, Self-Love and Self-Respect: A Philosophical Study of Egoism , Ottowa: Canadian Library of Philosophy.
  • Care, N., 2000, Decent People , Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Champlin, T.S., 1995, “Hanfling on Self-Love,” Philosophy 70: 107–110.
  • Chazan, P., 1998, “Self-Esteem, Self-Respect, and Love of Self: Ways of Valuing the Self,” Philosophia 26: 41–63.
  • Christensen, D., 2007, “Epistemic Self-Respect,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , 107: 319–337.
  • Collins, P.H., 1990, Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of Empowerment , New York: Routledge.
  • Daniels, N., 1975, “Equal Liberty and Unequal Worth of Liberty,” in Reading Rawls: Critical Studies of “A Theory of Justice ,” N. Daniels (ed.), New York: Basic Books, Inc.
  • Darwall, S.L., 1988, “Self-Deception, Autonomy, and Moral Constitution,” in Perspectives on Self-Deception , B.P. McLaughlin and A.O. Rorty (eds.), Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • DeGrazia, D., 1991, “Grounding a Right to Health Care in Self-Respect and Self-Esteem,” Public Affairs Quarterly , 5: 301–318.
  • Deigh, J., 1983, “Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique,” Ethics 93: 225–245; reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect , R.S. Dillon (ed.), New York: Routledge, 1995.
  • Diller, A., 2001, “Pride and Self-Respect in Unjust Social Orders,” Philosophy of Education 2001 : 308–310.
  • Dillon, R.S., 2007, “Arrogance, Self-Respect, and Personhood,” Journal of Consciousness Studies 14: 101–126.
  • –––, 2004, “‘What's a Woman Worth? What's Life Worth? Without Self-Respect?’: On the Value of Evaluative Self-Respect,” in Moral Psychology: Feminist Ethics and Social Theory , P. DesAutels and M. Walker (eds.), Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • –––, 2003, “Kant on Arrogance and Self-Respect,” in Setting the Moral Compass: Essays by Women Philosophers , C.Calhoun (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2001, “Self-Forgiveness and Self-Respect,” Ethics 112: 53–83.
  • –––, 1997, “Self-Respect: Moral, Emotional, Political,” Ethics 107: 226–249.
  • –––, ed., 1995, Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect , New York: Routledge.
  • –––, 1992b, “How To Lose Your Self-Respect,” American Philosophical Quarterly 29: 125–139.
  • –––, 1992c, “Toward a Feminist Conception of Self-Respect,” Hypatia 7: 52–69; reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect , R.S. Dillon (ed.), New York: Routledge, 1995.
  • Doppelt, G., 2009, “The Place of Self-respect in a Theory of Justice,” Inquiry 52: 127–154.
  • –––, 1981, “Rawls's System of Justice: A Critique from the Left,” Noûs 15: 259–307.
  • Elster, J., 1985–86, “Self-Realization in Work and Politics: The Marxist Conception of the Good Life,” Social Philosophy and Policy 3: 97–126.
  • Eyal, N., 2005, “Perhaps the Most Important Primary Good: Self-Respect and Rawls' Principles of Justice,” Politics, Philosophy, and Economics 4: 195–215.
  • Ezorsky, G., 1991, Racism & Justice: The Case for Affirmative Action , Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • Falk, W.D., 1986, “Morality, Form, and Content,” in Ought, Reasons, and Morality: The Collected Papers of W. D. Falk , Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • Feinberg, J., 1970, “The Nature and Value of Rights,” Journal of Value Inquiry 4: 243–257.
  • Ferguson, A., 1987, “A Feminist Aspect Theory of the Self,” in Science, Morality, and Feminist Theory , M. Hanen and K. Nielsen (eds.), Calgary: University of Calgary Press.
  • Flanagan, O., 1991, Varieties of Moral Personality: Ethics and Psychological Realism , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Friedman, M., 1985, “Moral Integrity and the Deferential Wife,” Philosophical Studies 47: 141–150.
  • Gewirth, A., 1992, “Human Dignity as the Basis of Rights,” in The Constitution of Rights: Human Dignity and American Values , M.J. Meyer and W.A. Parent (eds.), Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 1978, Reason and Morality , Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Govier, T., 1993, “Self-Trust, Autonomy, and Self-Esteem” Hypatia 8: 99–120.
  • Grace, H.A., 1953, “The Self and Self-Acceptance,” Educational Theory 3: 220-235.
  • Gutman, A., 1980, Liberal Equality , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Haber, J.G., 1991, Forgiveness , Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Hampton, J., 1997, “The Wisdom of the Egoist: The Moral and Political Implications of Valuing the Self,” Social Philosophy and Policy 14: 21–51.
  • –––, 1993, “Selflessness and the Loss of Self,” Social Philosophy and Policy 10: 135–165.
  • Hansberg, O.E., 2000, “The Role of Emotions in Moral Psychology: Shame and Indignation,” Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, vol 9: Philosophy of Mind , B. Elevitch (ed.), Bowling Green: Philosophy Documentation Center.
  • Harris, G.W., 2001, “Self-Esteem,” in Encyclopedia of Ethics , 2 nd edition, L.C. Becker and C.B. Becker (eds.), New York: Garland Publishing, Inc.
  • Heins, V., 2008, “Realizing Honneth: Redistribution, Recognition, and Global Justice,” Journal of Global Ethics 4: 141–153.
  • Held, V., 1973, “Reasonable Progress and Self-Respect,” The Monist 57: 12–27.
  • Hill, T.E., Jr., 1992, “Self-Respect,” in Encyclopedia of Ethics , L.C. Becker and C.B. Becker (eds.), New York: Garland Publishing, Inc.
  • –––, 1991, Autonomy and Self-Respect , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 1986, “Darwall on Practical Reason.” Ethic s 96: 604–619.
  • –––, 1982, “Self-Respect Reconsidered,” in Respect for Persons , O. H. Green (ed.), Tulane Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 31, New Orleans: Tulane University Press; reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect , R.S. Dillon (ed.), New York: Routledge, 1995.
  • –––, 1973, “Servility and Self-Respect,” Monist 57: 12–27; reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect , R.S. Dillon (ed.).
  • Holmgren, M., 1998, “Self-Forgiveness and Responsible Moral Agency,” Journal of Value Inquiry 32: 75–91.
  • Honneth, A., 1995, The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts , Cambridge: Polity Press.
  • Horsburgh, H.J.N., 1954, “The Plurality of Moral Standards,” Philosophy 24: 332–346.
  • Hudson, S.D., 1986, Human Character and Morality: Reflections from the History of Ideas , Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
  • Hume, D., 1751 (1983), Enquiries Concerning the Principle of Morals , J.B. Schneewind (ed.), Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
  • –––, 1739 (1971), A Treatise of Human Nature , L.A. Selby-Bigge (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Ikuenobe, P., 2004, “Culture of Racism, Self-Respect, and Blameworthiness,” Public Affairs Quarterly 18: 27–55.
  • Isenberg, A., 1949, “Natural Pride and Natural Shame,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 10: 1–24.
  • Kekes, J., 1988, “Shame and Moral Progress,” in Ethical Theory: Character and Virtue , Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 13, P.A. French, T.E. Uehling, and H.K. Wettstein (eds.), Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
  • Kristjansson, K., 2007, “Measuring Self-Respect,” Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior 37: 225–242.
  • –––, 2002, Justifying Emotions: Pride and Jealousy , New York: Routledge.
  • –––, 1998, “Self-Respect, Megalopsychia , and Moral Education,” Journal of Moral Education 27: 5–17.
  • Kupfer, J., 1997, “What's Wrong with Prostitution?” in Explorations in Value , T. Magnal (ed.), Amsterdam: Rodopi.
  • –––, 1995, “Prostitutes, Musicians, and Self-Respect,” Journal of Social Philosophy 26: 75–88.
  • LaCaze, M., 2008, “Seeing Oneself Through the Eyes of the Other: Asymmetrical Reciprocity and Self-Respect,” Hypatia 23: 118–135.
  • Lane, R.E., 1982, “Government and Self-Esteem,” Political Theory 10: 5–31.
  • Lomasky, L., 1987, Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Maclaren, E., 1974, “Dignity,” Journal of Medical Ethics 3: 40-41.
  • Margalit, A., 1996, The Decent Society , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Martin, M.W., 1996, Love's Virtues , Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas.
  • –––, 1989, Everyday Morality: An Introduction to Applied Ethics , Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth.
  • –––, 1986, Self-Deception and Morality , Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas.
  • Massey, S. J., 1983a, “Is Self-Respect a Moral or a Psychological Concept?” Ethics 93: 246–261; reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect , R.S. Dillon (ed.), New York: Routledge, 1995.
  • –––, 1983b, “Kant on Self-Respect,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 21: 57–73.
  • McGary, H., 1988, “Reparations, Self-Respect, and Public Policy,” in Ethical Theory and Society , D. Goldberg (ed.), New York: Holt, Rinehart, & Winston.
  • McKinnon, C., 2000, “Exclusion Rules and Self-Respect,” Journal of Value Inquiry 34: 491–505.
  • –––, 1997, “Self-Respect and the Stepford Wives,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 97: 325–330.
  • Meyer, M.J., 1992, “Dignity,” in Encyclopedia of Ethics , L.C. Becker and C.B. Becker (eds.), New York: Garland Publishing, Inc.
  • –––, 1989, “Dignity, Rights, and Self-Control,” Ethics 99: 520-534.
  • –––, 1987, “Kant's Conception of Dignity and Modern Political Thought,” History of European Ideas 8: 319–332.
  • Meyer, M.J., and W.A. Parent, eds., 1992, The Constitution of Rights: Human Dignity and American Values , Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • Meyers, D.T., 1989, Self, Society, and Personal Choice , New York: Columbia University Press; excerpts reprinted in Dignity, Character, Self-Respect , R.S. Dillon (ed.), New York: Routledge, 1995.
  • –––, 1987a, “The Socialized Individual and Individual Autonomy,” in Women and Moral Theory , E.F. Kittay and D.T. Meyers (eds.), Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.
  • –––, 1987b, “Work and Self-Respect,” in Moral Rights in the Workplace , G. Ezorsky (ed.), Albany: State University of New York Press.
  • –––, 1986, “The Politics of Self-Respect,” Hypatia 1: 83–100.
  • Michelman, F., 1975, “Constitutional Welfare Rights and A Theory of Justice,” in Reading Rawls: Critical Studies of A Theory of Justice, N. Daniels (ed.), New York: Basic Books, Inc.
  • Middleton, D., 2006, “Three Types of Self-Respect,” Res Publica 12: 59–76.
  • Mohr, R.D., 1992, Gay Ideas: Outings and Other Controversies , Boston: Beacon Press.
  • –––, 1988, Gays/Justice: A Study of Ethics, Society, and Law , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Montefiore, A., 1980, “Self-Reality, Self-Respect, and Respect for Others,” in Studies in Ethical Theory , Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 3, P.A. French, T.E. Uehling, and H.K. Wettstein (eds.), Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
  • Moody-Adams, M.M., 1992–93, “Race, Class, and the Social Construction of Self-Respect,” The Philosophical Forum , 24: 251–266; reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect , R.S. Dillon (ed.), New York: Routledge, 1995.
  • Morgan, K.P., 1986, “Romantic Love, Altruism, and Self-Respect: An Analysis of Simone de Beauvoir,” Hypatia 1: 117–148.
  • Morris, B., 1946, “The Dignity of Man,” Ethics 57: 57–64.
  • Murphy, J.G., 1982, “Forgiveness and Resentment,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 7: 503–516.
  • –––, 1972, “Moral Death: A Kantian Essay on Psychopathy,” Ethics 82: 284–298.
  • ––– and Hampton, J., 1988, Forgiveness and Mercy , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Nielsen, K., 1980, “Capitalism, Socialism, and Justice: Reflections on Rawls's Theory of Justice,” Social Praxis 7: 253–277.
  • Novitz, D., 1998, “Forgiveness and Self-Respect,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58: 299–315.
  • Nozick, R., 1981, Philosophical Explanations , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1974, Anarchy, State, and Utopia , New York: Basis Books.
  • Owen, D., 2002, “Equality, Democracy, and Self-Respect: Reflections of Nietzsche's Agonal Perfectionism,” Journal of Nietzsche Studies 24: 113–131.
  • Parent, W.A., 1992, “Constitutional Values and Human Dignity,” in The Constitution of Rights: Human Dignity and American Values , M.J. Meyer and W.A. Parent (eds.), Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • Peters, R.S., 1974, Psychology and Ethical Development , London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • Phillips, M., 1987, “Reason, Dignity, and the Formal Conception of Practical Reason,” American Philosophical Quarterly 24: 191–198.
  • Postow, B.C., 1978–79, “Economic Dependence and Self-Respect,” The Philosophical Forum 10: 181–205.
  • Pritchard, M.S., 1991, On Becoming Responsible , Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas.
  • –––, 1982, “Self-Regard and the Supererogatory,” in Respect for Persons , O.H. Green (ed.), Tulane Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 31, New Orleans: Tulane University Press.
  • –––, 1977, “Rawls's Moral Psychology,” Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 8: 59–72.
  • –––, 1972, “Human Dignity and Justice,” Ethics 82: 299–313.
  • Proudfoot, W., 1978, “Rawls on Self-Respect and Social Union,” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 5: 255–269.
  • Pullman, D., 1990, “Self-Respect, Morality, and Justice,” in Terrorism, Justice, and Social Values , C. Peden (ed.), Lewiston: Mellen Press.
  • Rawls, J., 2000, Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy , Barbara Herman (ed.), Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1982, “The Basic Liberties and Their Priority,” in The Tanner Lectures on Human Values , vol. 3, Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.
  • –––, 1980, “Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory”, The Journal of Philosophy 77: 515–572.
  • –––, 1971, A Theory of Justice , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; excerpt reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect , R.S. Dillon (ed.), New York: Routledge, 1995.
  • Raz, J., 1989, “Liberating Duties,” Law and Philosophy .
  • Sachs, D., 1982, “Self-Respect and Respect for Others: Are They Independent?” in Respect for Persons , O.H. Green (ed.), Tulane Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 31, New Orleans: Tulane University Press.
  • –––, 1981, “How To Distinguish Self-Respect from Self-Esteem,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 10: 346–360.
  • Scarre, G., 2001, “Upton on Evil Pleasures,” Utilitas 13: 106–111.
  • –––, 1992, “Utilitarianism and Self-Respect,” Utilitas 4: 27–42.
  • Seidler, V. J., 1991, The Moral Limits of Modernity: Love, Inequality, and Oppression . New York: St. Martins Press.
  • –––, 1986, Kant, Respect, and Injustice: The Limits of Liberal Moral Theory , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Shue, H., 1975, “Liberty and Self-Respect,” Ethics 85: 195–203.
  • Solomon, R., 1977, The Passions , New York: Basic Books.
  • Speigelberg, H., 1971, “Human Dignity: A Challenge to Contemporary Philosophy,” Philosophy Forum 9: 39–64.
  • Stark, C. A., 1998, “Self-Respect,” Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy , E. Craig (ed.), London: Routledge.
  • –––, 1997, “The Rationality of Valuing Oneself: A Critique of Kant on Self-Respect,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 35: 65–82.
  • Statman, D., 2002, “Humiliation, Dignity, and Self-Respect,” Philosophical Psychology 13: 523–540.
  • Strike, K., 1980, “Education, Justice, and Self-Respect: A School for Rodney Dangerfield,” Philosophy of Education , 35: 41–49.
  • Szabados, B., 1989–90, “Embarrassment and Self-Esteem,” Journal of Philosophical Research 15: 341–349.
  • Taylor, C., 1989, Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Taylor, G., 1985, Pride, Shame, and Guilt: Emotions of Self-Assessment , Oxford: Oxford University Press; excerpts reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect , R.S. Dillon (ed.), New York: Routledge, 1995.
  • Telfer, E., 1968, “Self-Respect,” The Philosophical Quarterly 18: 114–121; reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect , R.S. Dillon (ed.).
  • Thomas, L., 2003, “Self-Respect, Fairness, and Living Morally,” in A Companion to African American Philosophy , T. Lott (ed.), Malden, MA: Blackwell.
  • –––, 2001b, “The Moral Self in the Face of Injustice,” in Social and Political Philosophy: Contemporary Perspectives , J.P. Sterba (ed.), London: Routledge.
  • –––, 2000, “Moral Psychology,” in The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory , H. LaFollete (ed.), Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers.
  • –––, 1989, Living Morally: A Psychology of Moral Character , Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
  • –––, 1983a, “Self-Respect: Theory and Practice,” in Philosophy Born of Struggle: Anthology of Afro-American Philosophy from 1917 , L. Harris (ed.), Kendall/Hunt Publishing Company; reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect , R.S. Dillon (ed.), New York: Routledge, 1995.
  • –––, 1983b, “Morality, the Self, and Our Natural Sentiments,” in Emotion: Philosophical Studies , K.D. Irani and G.E. Meyers (eds.), New York: Haven Publishing Corp.
  • –––, 1982, “Law, Morality, and Our Psychological Nature,” in Social Justice , M. Bradie and D. Braybrooke (eds.), Bowling Green, Ohio: Bowling Green Studies in Applied Philosophy.
  • –––, 1980, “Sexism and Racism: Some Conceptual Differences,” Ethics 90: 239–250.
  • –––, 1979, “Capitalism vs. Marx's Communism,” Studies in Soviet Thought 20: 57–79.
  • –––, 1978, “Morality and Our Self-Concept,” Journal of Value Inquiry 12: 258–268.
  • –––, 1978–79, “Rawlsian Self-Respect and the Black Consciousness Movement,” The Philosophical Forum 9: 303–314.
  • Van Leeuwen, B., 2007, “A Formal Recognition of Social Attachment: Expanding Axel Honneth's Theory of Recognition,” Inquiry 50: 180-205.
  • Vlastos, G., 1962, “Justice and Equality,” in Social Justice , R. Brandt (ed.), Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
  • Weil, S., 1972, The Need for Roots , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • –––, 1965, Seventy Letters , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Wong, D.B., 1984, Moral Relativity , Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • Worsfold, V.L., 1988, “Educating for Self-Respect,” Philosophy of Education 44: 258–269.
  • Yanal, R.J., 1987, “Self-Esteem,” Noûs 21: 363–379.

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

autonomy: in moral and political philosophy | egalitarianism | -->ethics-biomedical --> | ethics: environmental | ethics: virtue | Kant, Immanuel: moral philosophy | love | moral particularism | moral psychology: empirical approaches | -->Rawls --> | -->recognition --> | rights | value: intrinsic vs. extrinsic

Logo

Essay on Respect

Students are often asked to write an essay on Respect in their schools and colleges. And if you’re also looking for the same, we have created 100-word, 250-word, and 500-word essays on the topic.

Let’s take a look…

100 Words Essay on Respect

Understanding respect.

Respect is a feeling of deep admiration for someone due to their abilities, qualities, or achievements. It’s not just about being nice to others, but also about recognizing their worth and giving them space to express themselves.

Why is Respect Important?

Respect is important because it helps us understand each other better. It promotes peace and harmony in our society. When we respect others, we show that we value their opinions and feelings.

Ways to Show Respect

We can show respect by listening to others, not interrupting when they’re speaking, and treating them with kindness and fairness. It’s important to remember that respect should be mutual.

Also check:

  • 10 Lines on Respect
  • Speech on Respect

250 Words Essay on Respect

Introduction.

Respect is a fundamental virtue, a cornerstone of human interaction and social cohesion. It is an intangible concept, yet it holds immense power, shaping our relationships and our perception of the world.

The Essence of Respect

Respect transcends mere tolerance; it signifies a deep admiration for someone due to their abilities, qualities, or achievements. It is acknowledging the worth and dignity of all people, regardless of their status, race, religion, or ideology. Respect is also about understanding boundaries and acknowledging the autonomy of others, valuing their rights to their thoughts, feelings, and experiences.

Respect as a Two-Way Street

Respect is reciprocal. It is not merely an act of deference, but a mutual exchange. It is a two-way street, requiring both giving and receiving. It nurtures trust, promoting open dialogue and collaboration. Without respect, our interactions become a breeding ground for conflict, misunderstanding, and resentment.

Self-Respect: The Foundation

Self-respect, the recognition of one’s own worth, is the foundation of respect for others. It is about maintaining our dignity, adhering to our values, and not compromising our self-worth for external validation. Self-respect guides us in treating others with the same dignity and consideration we demand for ourselves.

In an increasingly polarized world, respect is more critical than ever. It bridges gaps, fosters understanding, and promotes peaceful coexistence. Respect is not just a virtue but a responsibility, a commitment to uphold the dignity and worth of all individuals. It is a testament to our shared humanity and our capacity for compassion and understanding.

500 Words Essay on Respect

Introduction: the concept of respect.

Respect, a term often associated with morality and ethics, is a fundamental aspect of human interaction and society. It is a multifaceted concept, encompassing attitudes, behaviors, and actions that recognize the inherent worth and dignity of all individuals. Respect is not merely an act of deference or politeness, but a profound recognition of shared humanity and individuality.

Respect as a Universal Value

Respect transcends cultural, religious, and social boundaries, making it a universal value. It is a cornerstone of many ethical systems and moral codes worldwide. From Confucianism’s emphasis on “li” (propriety) and “ren” (humaneness) to the Golden Rule’s “do unto others as you would have them do unto you,” respect is a common thread. It is a fundamental principle that guides interpersonal relationships, fostering harmony, and mutual understanding.

The Dimensions of Respect

Respect has several dimensions, each contributing to its overall significance. Firstly, there is self-respect, which involves recognizing one’s own worth and maintaining personal dignity. It is a prerequisite for respecting others, as it is challenging to acknowledge the value of others without first appreciating one’s own.

Secondly, respect for others, which is often the most emphasized aspect, involves recognizing and appreciating the inherent worth of other individuals. This respect is not contingent on their actions, achievements, or status but is accorded simply because they are human beings.

Finally, there is respect for the environment and the world at large. This dimension extends the concept of respect beyond human interactions, emphasizing our responsibility towards the world we inhabit.

Respect in the Modern World

In today’s interconnected world, respect is more critical than ever. As we encounter diverse cultures, perspectives, and ways of life, respect serves as a bridge, fostering understanding and cooperation. It promotes tolerance, encourages dialogue, and helps to mitigate conflicts.

However, respect is not always easy. It requires us to challenge our prejudices, to listen even when we disagree, and to value people for who they are, not what they can do for us. It is a commitment to the fundamental principle that every individual matters.

Conclusion: The Power of Respect

Respect is more than a moral obligation; it is a powerful force for positive change. It fosters empathy, promotes social cohesion, and lays the groundwork for a more just and equitable society. By cultivating respect, we not only enrich our own lives but also contribute to a better, more harmonious world.

In conclusion, respect is a fundamental value that underpins our interactions and relationships. It is a universal principle that transcends boundaries, a multifaceted concept that encompasses self, others, and the world, and a critical tool for navigating our diverse, interconnected world. Through respect, we affirm the inherent worth and dignity of all individuals, fostering a society that is more understanding, compassionate, and just.

That’s it! I hope the essay helped you.

If you’re looking for more, here are essays on other interesting topics:

  • Essay on Saina Nehwal
  • Essay on Impact of Cinema on Youth
  • Essay on Cinema as an Art Form

Apart from these, you can look at all the essays by clicking here .

Happy studying!

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

respect begets respect meaning essay

Marilyn Price-Mitchell Ph.D.

Adolescence

The language of respect, walking our talk with teenagers..

Posted February 10, 2014 | Reviewed by Ekua Hagan

  • When children and teens are respected, they learn to believe in themselves and adults.
  • Respect is assimilated through language and modeling, not through the act of traditional “teaching.”
  • Separating adolescents from their behavior through forgiveness gives them a chance to "get it right," and increases respect.

Maurus/123RF

What does it mean to build respect between adults and teenagers? Respect means we have high regard or admiration for another’s views and feelings. We value their abilities and inner qualities.

Sadly, many of today’s teens feel undervalued and misjudged by adults. Could our language be part of the problem?

A teenager recently wrote to me, saying, “I understand teens have issues… I am a teen. I get these things… I hate it when people generalize that teens love experimenting with drugs and sex and other risks and that we are ‘little sponges’ soaking up social norms that we must counteract. How are happy teenagers supposed to feel? Should they feel strange because they don’t take part in what other teenagers do?”

I’m always grateful to hear what teens are thinking. And this young woman made a great point. When we generalize about teenagers, we run the risk of losing their respect.

You’ll find lots of popular articles on “how to teach respect to children,” but respect is assimilated through language and modeling, not through the act of traditional “teaching.” Even young children understand when adults are not walking their talk. By adolescence , those mixed messages can cause deeper and deeper divides between teens and adults.

Respect Is a Two-Way Street

Researchers Hal Holloman and Peggy Yates have studied the topic of respect and how it gets translated through the words we use. Their research, outlined in the Journal of Positive Behavior Interventions, focused on teachers and students, but it is also applicable to parents and families.

What they learned is not surprising. When we give respect, we get it back in return. When we respect children and teens, they learn to believe in themselves and us. They feel valued and loved. We feel valued and loved.

Respect is a two-way street where adults are the pace-setter cars.

How does language change the course of our relationships with teens and build a culture of mutual respect? Holloman and Yates discovered eleven categories of words that foster respect. They found that rephrasing words from a negative to a positive context helps develop a culture of respect. The 11 categories are listed below, with word samples for each.

11 Ways to Build a Culture of Respect in Families and Classrooms

  • Words of Encouragement : Instead of complaining when teens feel discouraged, let them know how much you admire their ability to overcome tough challenges and recover from apathy or failure. “I know things can be difficult, but I really admire how you reach deeply into yourself to find the right answers. I want you to know I’m always here for you.”
  • Words of Grace: Instead of blaming, always separate an adolescent from his or her behavior. Forgive them for mistakes or misjudgments. Give them a chance to get it right. “You are not the same as your mistake. I know you to be a kind, caring human being. I forgive you and I’m here to help you learn from this setback.”
  • Words of Guidance : Don’t just hope teens will find their ways. Encourage them to ask questions and give them words of guidance. “Your questions help me know and understand you better. Please never think you have a dumb question. I want to help whenever I’m able.”
  • Words of Respect : Rather than a narrow focus on academic successes, build a climate of respect in your classroom and family. “While I care about your grades and other external measures of success, it’s also important to have a climate of mutual respect here. I plan to work hard to see that each of our opinions, thoughts, and feelings are respected.”
  • Words of High Expectations : Rather than being discouraged when teens don’t show their best abilities, encourage them to envision and pursue goals that fuel their passion. “I want you to achieve your potential, in whatever way you choose. What goals do you most want to achieve?”
  • Words of Hope: Instead of helping teens get through another difficult day, help them envision a better tomorrow. “You have such a kind heart and helpful way with people. Those abilities will see you through many of life’s challenges.”
  • Words of Love: Don’t just speak to the minds of teenagers. Speak to their hearts. Demonstrate how much you love and care for them every day. (Check out " 50 Everyday Ways to Love Your Teen.")
  • Words of Relationship: Use words that build connection through the sharing of feelings. Help teens “feel felt” by you. “I want to know and understand how you feel. Can you tell me?”
  • Words of Understanding : Instead of making assumptions, discover a young person’s perspective through empathy. “I want to understand your perspective. Please tell me what you think and what led you to that conclusion.”
  • Words of Unity: Shed the attitude of “it’s my way or the highway,” and foster a culture of collaboration and cooperation. “I’m your parent (or teacher), but that doesn’t mean I have all the answers. I respect your role as part of this family (or classroom).”
  • Words of Accountability : Being respectful means holding everyone accountable. Instead of allowing disrespectful behavior, help young people stay on track. “How you just behaved was unkind and disrespectful. How could you have handled that differently?”

Walking Our Talk

While language is critical to building a culture of respect in families and classrooms, it can’t stop there. It is only when we practice these eleven categories of words with everyone in our lives that we truly learn to “walk our talk.” Children and teens know the difference.

©2014 Marilyn Price-Mitchell. All rights reserved. Please see the reprint guidelines for Marilyn's articles.

Holloman, H., & Yates, P. H. (2013). Cloudy With a Chance of Sarcasm or Sunny With High Expectations Using Best Practice Language to Strengthen Positive Behavior Intervention and Support Efforts. Journal of Positive Behavior Interventions , 15 (2), 124-127.

Marilyn Price-Mitchell Ph.D.

Marilyn Price-Mitchell, Ph.D., is an Institute for Social Innovation Fellow at Fielding Graduate University and author of Tomorrow’s Change Makers.

  • Find a Therapist
  • Find a Treatment Center
  • Find a Psychiatrist
  • Find a Support Group
  • Find Online Therapy
  • United States
  • Brooklyn, NY
  • Chicago, IL
  • Houston, TX
  • Los Angeles, CA
  • New York, NY
  • Portland, OR
  • San Diego, CA
  • San Francisco, CA
  • Seattle, WA
  • Washington, DC
  • Asperger's
  • Bipolar Disorder
  • Chronic Pain
  • Eating Disorders
  • Passive Aggression
  • Personality
  • Goal Setting
  • Positive Psychology
  • Stopping Smoking
  • Low Sexual Desire
  • Relationships
  • Child Development
  • Therapy Center NEW
  • Diagnosis Dictionary
  • Types of Therapy

March 2024 magazine cover

Understanding what emotional intelligence looks like and the steps needed to improve it could light a path to a more emotionally adept world.

  • Emotional Intelligence
  • Gaslighting
  • Affective Forecasting
  • Neuroscience
  • (877) 237-8540
  • Open Daily | 7am to 9pm

Impact Family Christian Counseling

  • Share Feedback

Counseling Services

Other services.

  • Anger Assessment

respect begets respect meaning essay

  • Google Reviews
  • Yelp Reviews
  • Facebook Reviews
  • Knowledge Base
  • Counseling Team
  • Volunteer Team
  • Terms and Policies
  • Schedule Session
  • Scholarship Request
  • Special Sessions
  • Addiction Counseling
  • Career Counseling
  • Clergy Counseling
  • Couples Counseling
  • Deliverance Counseling
  • Financial Counseling
  • Grief Counseling
  • Inner Healing Counseling
  • Marriage Counseling
  • Men’s Counseling
  • Parenting Counseling
  • Phone & Text Counseling
  • Virtual Counseling
  • Spiritual Growth Counseling
  • Sports Counseling
  • Women’s Counseling
  • Youth Counseling
  • Event Speakers
  • Matchmaker Ministry
  • Online Studies
  • Private Couples Retreat
  • Private Inner Healing Retreat
  • Small Groups
  • Wedding Official
  • All Services
  • Video Studies
  • Book Studies
  • Meditation Tools
  • Four Temperaments Test
  • Addiction Recovery Program
  • Couples Survey Questions
  • Love Language Quiz
  • Apology Language Quiz

Respect Begets Respect

  •   / Blog
  •   / Respect Begets Respect

Respect begets respect

Respect is often described as a two-way street, meaning it should be given to receive it. This proverb suggests that respect  must be earned; it cannot be demanded or expected.

People who show respect for others are more likely to receive respect. Conversely, those who do not treat others with respect are unlikely to earn the respect of others. To create a polite environment, it is important to model respectful behavior. We can encourage them to do the same by treating others with courtesy and consideration.

Respect begets respect; disrespect begets disrespect. We can create a more civil and compassionate world by showing respect for others.

Importance of Respect

Respect is a fundamental human need. We all crave respect and hopefully extend that same courtesy to others. But what exactly is respect?  Webster  defines respect as “a positive feeling or action shown towards someone or something considered important, worthy, or possessed of certain qualities.” In other words, respect is acknowledging someone or something as valuable.

There are many  different types of respect . The kind of politeness we show our elders differs from the kind we show our peers. And how we treat a movie star differs from how we might treat our next-door neighbor. But all forms share one common element: they involve recognition of the worthiness of another person or thing.

Importance of respect with other

Respect is important to who we are and how we interact with the world around us. It shapes our relationships and influences the way we communicate. Showing respect for others can be as simple as being polite and considerate. It can also mean giving people the benefit of the doubt or offering them a listening ear. Whatever form it takes, respect is always about taking someone else’s feelings and needs into account – not just our own.

Respect is an essential ingredient in any  healthy relationship . Whether it’s a romantic partnership, a parent-child bond, or a friendship, mutual respect is key to maintaining a positive connection. When we offer others our respect, we acknowledge their value and affirm their worthiness as individuals. This increases the likelihood that they’ll reciprocate by showing us the same level of consideration and thoughtfulness. Over time, this mutual exchange helps to build trust and intimacy between two people.

How to Show Respect for Others

1. be present in the conversation, aka pay attention.

In today’s world, it’s easy to get distracted. With constant notifications and a never-ending supply of entertainment, it’s no wonder that we often find ourselves buried in our phones or zoning out when someone is talking to us. However, this behavior can be rude and make the other person feel unimportant.

If you want to show someone you respect them, it’s important to be present in the conversation. This means putting away your phone, making eye contact, and actively listening to what the other person is saying. It may seem like a small gesture, but it can make a big difference in showing that you value the other person and what they have to say.

2. Understand others (even if their beliefs are different)

It’s important to remember that everyone comes from different backgrounds and experiences. Just because someone’s beliefs may differ from your own, it doesn’t mean they’re wrong. It’s important to understand where others are coming from, even if you don’t agree with them. Doing so can show respect for their beliefs and help create a more respectful and tolerant world.

Furthermore, when you take the time to understand others, they are more likely to reciprocate and try to understand you. So, the next time you meet someone with different beliefs, take a moment to try and see things from their perspective. It makes all the difference.

3. Show empathy for unique differences

Importance of respect and showing sympathy as a form of respect

We are all different, and that’s what makes us special. When we show empathy for the unique differences in others, we respect them as individuals. This doesn’t mean that we have to agree with everything they do or say, but it does mean that we should try to see things from their perspective. Doing this can build bridges and create a more united world.

4. Say sorry when you’re wrong

We all make mistakes. It’s part of being human. What’s important is how we handle those mistakes. One way to show respect for others is to apologize when we’ve wronged them. A sincere apology can go a long way toward repairing relationships and restoring trust. It shows that we value the people we’ve hurt and are willing to take responsibility for our actions.

Furthermore, an apology shows that we’re willing to change our behavior in the future. So next time you make a mistake, don’t be afraid to say sorry. It just might be the most respectful thing you can do.

5. Show gratitude

Respect is a fundamental building block of any successful relationship, whether it be between peers, colleagues, or family members. One simplest and most effective ways to show respect for others is to express gratitude. Whether a sincere “thank you” for a job well done or a handwritten note expressing appreciation, taking the time to express gratitude sends a powerful message that you value the other person and their contributions.

Nowadays, it’s easy to take the people in our lives for granted. But by consciously showing gratitude, we can cultivate more respectful and satisfying relationships with the people who matter most to us.

Start Your First Intake Session Today

Impact Family Christian Counseling Network  is a safe place where you can come and start your first intake session. With the help of our  professional counselors , you will be able to work through your feelings and thoughts in a confidential and comfortable setting.

At Impact Family Christian Counseling Network, we understand that taking the first step toward counseling can be difficult. Our goal is to make the process as easy and stress-free as possible. We offer a variety of counseling services that are designed to meet your unique needs.  Schedule your first intake session today.

You don’t have to go through this alone. We’re here to help.

© 2023 Impact Family Inc. Powered by Global Presence Marketing

10031 Pines Boulevard, Suite 234 Pembroke Pines FL 33024 | (877) 237-8540

  • New account

Forgot your password?

Mobile Number

Lost your password? Please enter your email address. You will receive mail with link to set new password.

Back to login

Why Respect Is Important

By: Author Valerie Forgeard

Posted on August 2, 2022

Categories Business , Leadership , Self Improvement

Whether you respect yourself or others, the concept is the same: it’s a way of showing that you value someone.

Respect is important in your life because it helps you feel good about yourself and your place in the world. It also helps you get along with other people because when you respect them, they feel respected and are more likely to respect you too!

Respect Is Part of Who We’re as People

Every person respects at least one person. It may be one of your family members or your mentor. You may respect the CEO of your company, the person who always helps you when you’re in trouble, or your favorite sports team.

Showing Respect Is an Essential Part of Building and Maintaining Relationships

Without it, you can’t have healthy relationships with others.

Showing respect means giving other people the space and freedom to be who they’re, to think what they think, and to do what they do.

It means accepting their values and beliefs as valid, even if you don’t share them yourself. Showing respect doesn’t mean always agreeing but understanding that your friend or partner is entitled to their own opinions, feelings, and actions.

This kind of respect isn’t only crucial for romantic relationships and applies to all relationships in our lives, from family members to work colleagues to friends. Relationships aren’t always easy – they take work! But when we learn to respect each other, we can make these relationships stronger and healthier for all of us.

Respect Starts With You

Respect isn’t something you can force on someone but something you can give to yourself. When you respect yourself, you lay the foundation for feeling worthy of other people’s respect.

When you respect yourself, you tell yourself and the world that you matter. You take time to acknowledge your accomplishments and appreciate your strengths. When you respect yourself, you choose to treat your body well and not put it through harmful situations or substances.

When we respect ourselves, we’re more confident and less afraid of failure or rejection. We gain more confidence in our abilities, which leads us to try new things and grow as people. As we grow as individuals and feel increasingly confident, we also feel more comfortable interacting with others – and because we feel comfortable interacting with people who care about us and value our opinions, they respond with kindness in return.

Respect Creates a Work Environment Where People Feel Comfortable and Can Be Themselves

Employees who feel respected are more likely to take risks and innovate. They’re also more likely to be satisfied with their work and stay with their company longer. Employees who feel treated with respect are twice as likely to stay with their company for at least three years.

In Other Words, Respect Is Good for Business and Employee Engagement!

If companies want their employees to innovate and take on new challenges, they need to show them that they trust them by giving them the freedom to make decisions and solve problems themselves.

They can do this, for example, by acknowledging what their employees do well – whether it’s something small, like remembering a sending an email, or something big, like helping in a crisis. Another way is to ensure the human resources management has an open-door policy so anyone can approach them if they experience disrespectful behavior from coworkers or leadership.

Disrespect in workplaces can have a devastating effect on employee satisfaction, their leadership, and even the business as a whole.

Workplaces must ensure that employees are treated with dignity and work in a respectful environment.

This Contributes to Employee Well-Being and Prevents Burnout

Employees who feel respected are more productive, engaged, and satisfied. Employee satisfaction makes people more likely to stay with their company for longer, making them an asset to the company.

Human resources management at these companies is also more likely to have a closer relationship with their respected employees, leading to better communication, enabling a common ground, mutual understanding, and better decision-making.

Respectful workplace interactions can prevent employees from feeling taken advantage of or having little say, which can lead to stress in their daily life, and sometimes mental health issues.

Treating employees with appreciation is essential because it increases productivity by allowing you to focus on something other than completing their daily tasks.

For example, if employees don’t respect each other because they’ve different ways of working, not only will the working relationship be affected, but conflict and an uncomfortable environment will arise instead of deep admiration for each other where they could complement each other and accomplish amazing things together.

Respect Is an Essential Aspect of a Healthy Workplace Culture

A healthy relationship between employees is the best way to get the best results and helps keep the business running smoothly.

Leaders tell them they value their opinions when there’s a positive relationship between employees and leadership. They show that leaders care about what they have to say and how they feel about their work. Companies will find that when their employees feel respected, they’re more motivated to do their best for their leaders – and when they’re happy with their work, they’re likely to want to stay with the company as long as possible.

Respect also means giving employees enough freedom in their work environment. If a company gives its employees some leeway in setting up their workspace or choosing their projects, they can expect them to be more engaged in their work and more likely to produce excellent results.

It’s important to remember that respect doesn’t just mean treating employees well but also giving them good tools to succeed and plenty of opportunities to grow within the company.

Respect Is Just as Important at Home as It’s at Work

When you’re at home, you’re not just a boss or a coworker but also a parent, a sibling, a roommate, a neighbor, or a partner. You must be as considerate of each other’s needs and feelings as you’re at work. It’s easy to get caught up in the daily grind and forget there’s more to life than work.

Respect is a matter of balance. Respecting your loved ones doesn’t mean giving up your career or never talking about work again; it means making sure everyone gets what they need in their relationships with others. It means making time for each other and finding ways to bring more balance into your lives, so everyone feels heard and valued.

Respect means listening and speaking up when you’ve something important to say. Whether you’re asking for help or offering your support, it helps things run smoothly at home – and lets everyone know they matter.

The Golden Rule: Treat Others the Way You Want to Be Treated

It’s easy to forget.

We’re all so busy and always on the move. We’ve so many projects, tasks, and people to talk to that in the hustle and bustle of everyday life, it’s easy to forget one of life’s most essential principles: treat others the way you want to be treated.

When you’re rushing to work, meeting up with your friends, or going out to dinner with your family, it’s easy to forget that there’s a human being on the other end of your actions. It’s easy to forget that she might be having a bad day or worrying about something else entirely.

  • But what happens when we take a moment before interacting with someone?
  • What if, instead of imagining ourselves as the person receiving the message we send out into the world, we imagined ourselves as another person who’s just as busy as we’re?
  • What if we thought about how we’d feel if someone treated us like an object – or worse?

That’s why we all must remember to treat others the way we want to be treated.

Respecting Others Doesn’t Mean Not Respecting Yourself

Not everyone is respectful, and that’s where it gets complicated.

We know respect is important, but how do we practice it when faced with people who don’t seem to care? How do we stay true to our values and still find our way in the world?

It can be hard to feel like you’re doing the right thing when you’re surrounded by people who don’t share your values – but there are a few small things you can do to center yourself when you feel like everything is going south.

Remember that your actions have consequences – meaning that even if someone doesn’t respect you, there’s a chance that because of something you did or said, they’ll respect someone else. So keep going!

Second, realize that while your actions may not make an immediate change in the behavior of others, over time, as more and more people see how respectful you’re, they’ll make a change. That’s right: respect begets respect.

Respect for others means respecting ourselves and then taking that respect out into the world to make it a better place for everyone.

To Get Respect, You’ve to Know Yourself and Your Boundaries

If you want people to respect you, then you must respect others. If you don’t respect yourself, no one else will either. Don’t let other people push you around or make you feel like you’re worth less than you’re because that’s what they think of you – that’s their problem, not yours!

Here are some ways you can show respect to yourself:

  • Be honest with yourself and others about what you want in life . Don’t settle for less than what makes your heart sing.
  • Don’t be afraid to ask for help when needed ; don’t try to do everything yourself, even if it means missing out on opportunities!
  • Stay true to yourself (and not what someone else wants). The more confident and self-assured people see you, the more willing they’ll be to open their hearts and minds.

Learning to Respect Yourself and Others Is a Lifelong Journey

It’s not something you can learn in your freshman year or at the end of your senior year.

It takes time, effort, and practice – and it’s different for everyone.

There are so many versions of ourselves that we can try on! Maybe we start as a free spirit who thinks we know it all, but then we learn humility through mistakes or setbacks.

Maybe we become introverts who want to spend time alone because we need space to think. Or maybe you’re an extrovert who needs lots of human contact to feel comfortable. Maybe you crave solitude after spending time with people who drain your energy, or vice versa!

The point is that there are many ways to live our lives, and no one way is better than another – just different. The most important thing is to find what works best for you and stick with it until it becomes second nature.

As a Society, We Must Respect Others

Respect is a basic social value that most of us learned at home as children. But many of us were never taught how to apply it in our daily lives. Instead, we take our cues from our surroundings – the people around us, our friends and family, television and movies, and even some of our favorite celebrities.

It’s easy to understand why: we want to belong, and it can be hard to be different from everyone else. But when we ignore what society tells us to do and treat others disrespectfully, we expose ourselves to failure and disappointment.

Mutual respect is so simple yet so hard to achieve. There are many different reasons to respect someone, but the most important thing is that it’s the right thing to do.

Respecting others is important because it shows that you care about their feelings and thoughts. It shows them you’re willing to learn from their experiences and perspectives.

Related Topics

Can You Respect a Person Without Respecting Their Opinions

Can Money Buy Respect

respect begets respect meaning essay

‘Respect Begets Respect’: The New Way Of Teaching Kids

  • by Kevyn Gohu
  • June 7, 2022

Teaching kids about respect shouldn’t involve power play anymore.

Respect is a big thing among Filipino families , especially when it’s demanded from the kids. But there is an unspoken hierarchy that is strongly influenced by age. Where the elders can never be wrong and children know nothing because they are younger. Unfortunately, the existing premise adds unnecessary pressure to both the elder generation and the younger one. And it twists the definition of respect into something more toxic and pervasive.

‘Respect’: How Do Filipino Families Define It To Their Kids

Respect or in Filipino, respeto , is a heavily weighted word in Filipino families which has several implications. Some of these implications include “staying silent” to preserve harmony instead of being problem-oriented in communication and solution. Rooted deeply in the virtue of “ hiya “ , this also involves not correcting older people even if it’s blatantly obvious that they are wrong.

The Unspoken Hierarchy in Filipino Families

respect begets respect meaning essay

Strongly influenced by age, the power distributed in Filipino families is usually based on wisdom, which we often define as “knowledge gained through experience and time”. Unfortunately, that same rule becomes problematic, especially with how fast things evolve and how easy it is to fact-check nowadays . Knowledge decays so quickly that many people get confused about what to believe.

It’s also this premise that gives unnecessary pressure on elders and children. Elders, bearing the responsibility to lead the family, are more unforgiving with themselves . Thus, they’re more prone to gaslighting people because there’s that ceiling where they must be perfect . This also extends to parents. While children, on the other hand, end up continuing the toxic cycle because they are taught that their thoughts hold no weight at their age. Statements such as “ Tahimik ka lang, bata ka lang !” or “Shut up!” or “What do you know?” consistently shut down our children’s attempts to establish boundaries and independence.

How To Teach Respect To Kids

Perhaps, we’re better off showing respect to our kids rather than just teaching it. Teaching involves a lecture that usually goes in one ear and out the other. Here’s what we can do to show and teach our kids respect:

1. Respect them the same way you want to be respected

“Do unto others what you want others to do to you” applies even with kids. By giving your kids the space to talk, they too will respect that and give you space to talk. Talking back will be a lot less especially when they realize that the space you’re giving is “safe” for them to express their feelings.

respect begets respect meaning essay

2. Remind yourself that they’re not mad at you but more at the idea

In the heat of the moment and rage, it’s easy to think that kids disrespect their parents because they hate their parents. But in reality, it’s not. Their distaste and disgust are more toward the idea. Our kids explaining to us how they want us to talk to them isn’t undermining our ability as parents. In fact, it should be a bonus because now we don’t have to read their minds!

respect begets respect meaning essay

3. Mantra: “Respect is respect. Not an exercise of power.”

Having a mantra and repeating it in front of the mirror can subconsciously influence how we behave. A lot of times, people perceive defiance and disrespect as “stealing one’s power”. But it’s high time we define respect as “refining one’s boundaries without stepping on others”. Reminding ourselves that in the mirror can help keep our emotions calm when someone or our kids are asserting themselves.

respect begets respect meaning essay

4. When someone makes a mistake, don’t shame

The majority of the reason why we gaslight or prefer sweeping things under the rug is that we’re quick to shame others. Although it’s easy for us to rationalize that we’re just “telling the truth”, we have to take a step back and check if the truth is what our kids or whoever needs to hear at that moment in time. In the heat of the moment, the truth can be seen as a weapon instead of a learning experience.

respect begets respect meaning essay

5. Restrain our biases

We all have our biases and when confronted with something that doesn’t fit, we’re quick to shut it down. That phenomenon is known as confirmation bias wherein we only listen and absorb information that fits our worldview. However, these biases do not control us. Rather, we control it. So when there’s a thought that contradicts our existing information, it’s okay to ask our kids about it. What may be common sense to them may not be the same for you and vice versa.

respect begets respect meaning essay

Respect is a Two-Way Street For Parents and Kids

If we want our kids to respect us and others, we need to do the same for them. From making sure our tone is controlled and neutral to the choice of words being more inquisitive, these are things our kids learn from us when it comes to respecting others. While there are a lot of things we can talk to them about, respect is just one of those few virtues that are best done by showing rather than telling.

More about kids? Check these stories out:

Do Your Kids Have A Sweet Tooth? Here’s How To Manage It How Utang ng Loob Made Filipino Families Toxic Gaslighting: What It is and How Parents Can Avoid It

Shop for Modern Parenting's print issues through these platforms.

Sari Sari Shopping

Download this month's Modern Parenting magazine digital copy from:

Magzter

Subscribe via [email protected]

  • Latest News
  • The Economy
  • Vantage Points

respect begets respect meaning essay

RESPECT BEGETS RESPECT

respect begets respect meaning essay

“Respect for ourselves guides our morals; respect for others guides our manners.” – Laurence Sterne

In these days of stress, information highway, and cellular phones, respect seems to be completely ignored.

If you have a scheduled meeting at 9 in the morning, you arrive early but others come late. Today’s youngsters never pay attention to their parents anymore. In a bus, nobody offers a seat for the old folks.

There are two types of respect. The first one is a “due regard for the feelings, wishes, rights, or traditions of others.” If a person’s belief prohibits him from eating pork or drinking alcohol, that someone offering it should not insist.

The second is about “a feeling of admiration for someone or something elicited by their abilities, qualities, or achievements.” This happens when someone is being bestowed a coveted award and everyone stand and clap their hands for ovation.

As someone puts it: “Respect is a way of treating or thinking about something or someone. If you respect your teacher, you admire her and treat her well. People respect others who are impressive for any reason, such as being in authority – like a teacher or cop – or being older – like a grandparent.”

Even if someone is not superior to you or someone who is lesser than you in life, you still have to show some respect to that person. Listen to what the famed Albert Einstein said: “I speak to everyone in the same way, whether he is the garbage man or the president of the university.”

There are people who show respect only if you respect him in the first place. In a graduation speech, Dr. Robert Michaels pointed this out, “I don’t care if you’re black, white, straight, bisexual, gay, lesbian, short, tall, fat, skinny, rich or poor. If you’re nice to me, I’ll be nice to you. Simple as that.”

If you want others to respect you, you have to respect yourself first. “Respect yourself and others will respect you,” Confucius reminded. Or as Fyodor Dostoyevsky elucidated in The Insulted and Humiliated: “If you want to be respected by others, the great thing is to respect yourself. Only by that, only by self-respect will you compel others to respect you.”

“You will never gain anyone’s approval by begging for it,” writes Mandy Hale in The Single Woman: Life, Love and a Dash of Sass. “When you stand confident in your own worth, respect follows.”

Here’s a story from freestoriesforkids.com which gives a lesson why respect is a necessity:

Once upon a time, the King’s two princes were playing in a forest and – meeting one at a time – they came across four dwarves who asked to be more careful.

The first dwarf had a headache and he asked them not to shout. The second dwarf was painting a landscape, and he asked the children to move away because they were blocking out the light. The third dwarf was doing a giant jigsaw puzzle in the middle of the road, and he asked the children not to tread on it. The fourth dwarf was watching a butterfly and he asked them not to frighten it away.

The first prince who respected others did as what the dwarves asked, but the second prince who disrespect anyone ignored the dwarves’ pleas, and kept bothering them. In the evening, both boys had become separated and lost. They needed to get back to the palace quickly.

Each of them separately came across the four dwarves again, and asked for their help. They refused to help the disrespectful prince, but with the respectful prince they did whatever they could to help, and took him along some secret tracks which led right to the palace.

The second prince arrived much later, and was punished for it. He now understood that it’s much better to respect everyone if you want to have friends.

The Holy Bible has presented several passages on respect. In Ephesians 6:5-9, Paul was talking about respect between masters and slaves: “Slaves, obey your earthly masters with respect and fear, and with sincerity of heart, just as you would obey Christ. Serve wholeheartedly, as if you were serving the Lord, not men.

“And masters, treat your slaves in the same way. Do not threaten them, since you know that he who is both their master and yours is in heaven, and there is no favouritism with him.”

Romans 13:1 highlights the importance of respecting people in authority: “Everyone must submit himself to the governing authorities, for there is no authority except that which God has established. The authorities that exist has been established by God.”

Wm. Paul Young in The Shack explains: “Submission is not about authority and it is not obedience; it is all about relationships of love and respect.”

Respect begets respect. Once it is lost, it is lost forever. In Fools, Martyrs, Traitors: The Story of Martyrdom in the Western World, Mahatma Gandhi was quoted: “I cannot conceive of a greater loss than the loss of one’s self-respect.”

Respect is for people who show it and for people who receive it.

Oftentimes, both have to show it in order for the other person to receive it. “When we treat people merely as they are, they will remain as they are,” says Thomas S. Monson, an American religious leader and author. “When we treat them as if they were what they should be, they will become what they should be.”

RELATED ARTICLES MORE FROM AUTHOR

Think on these: 99-percent perspiration, think on these: when failure is no failure, my scene: finding the magic within the generation gap, think on these: conquering short-lived madness, my scene finding the magic within the generation gap, think on these | aquaculture: boon and bane, leave a reply cancel reply.

Examples

Essay on Respect

Respect is a fundamental value that forms the cornerstone of harmonious and empathetic societies. It is a concept deeply ingrained in human interactions and has far-reaching implications for relationships, communities, and the world at large. In this essay, we will explore the significance of respect, its various dimensions, and the profound impact it has on individuals and society. Understanding respect is crucial for fostering unity, empathy, and a more compassionate world.

Respect can be defined as a positive regard for the inherent worth, dignity, and rights of all individuals, regardless of their background, beliefs, or differences. It involves treating others with consideration, courtesy, and empathy, acknowledging their humanity, and valuing their perspectives and boundaries.

The Dimensions of Respect

  • Respect for Individual Rights: This dimension emphasizes recognizing and upholding the rights and freedoms of every person. It encompasses freedom of expression, religion, and personal choices, as well as the right to live free from discrimination and harm.
  • Respect for Diversity: Respect goes beyond mere tolerance; it celebrates the rich tapestry of human diversity. Embracing differences in culture, ethnicity, gender, and beliefs enriches our collective experience.
  • Respect for Personal Boundaries: Respecting personal boundaries means honoring the physical and emotional space of others. It involves seeking consent, refraining from invasive actions, and allowing individuals to express their feelings without judgment.
  • Respect for Nature: Showing respect extends to the environment and all living beings. It entails responsible stewardship of the planet, recognizing the interconnectedness of all life forms.

The Significance of Respect

  • Fostering Empathy: Respect fosters empathy by encouraging individuals to put themselves in others’ shoes, understand their perspectives, and relate to their experiences. Empathy is the foundation of compassion and cooperation.
  • Building Trust: Respect is the cornerstone of trust in any relationship, whether personal or professional. When people feel respected, they are more likely to trust one another, communicate openly, and collaborate effectively.
  • Conflict Resolution: Respect plays a pivotal role in resolving conflicts peacefully. It enables individuals to engage in constructive dialogue, find common ground, and reach compromises without resorting to aggression or hostility.
  • Promoting Inclusivity: Respect creates an inclusive environment where all voices are heard and valued. In such spaces, individuals from diverse backgrounds feel safe to express themselves and contribute to society’s growth.
  • Enhancing Personal Well-being: Experiencing respect has a positive impact on one’s mental and emotional well-being. It fosters a sense of self-worth, belonging, and overall life satisfaction.
  • Global Harmony: On a global scale, respect is a powerful tool for promoting peace and international cooperation. Mutual respect among nations can lead to diplomacy, conflict resolution, and the pursuit of common goals, ultimately contributing to a more peaceful world.

Importance of Respect

  • Cultural Understanding: Respect for cultural diversity is essential in today’s interconnected world. By respecting and learning about different cultures, we can break down stereotypes, reduce prejudice, and build bridges between communities. This promotes a global perspective and encourages tolerance.
  • Respect for Authority: Respecting authority figures, such as teachers, parents, and leaders, is crucial for maintaining order and fostering a sense of responsibility. It sets a positive example for others and creates a culture of obedience to rules and regulations.
  • Role in Education: In educational settings, respect is the foundation for effective teaching and learning. When teachers and students respect each other, the classroom becomes an environment where ideas can be freely shared, questions are encouraged, and intellectual growth flourishes.
  • Respect for Self: Self-respect is equally important. It involves valuing your own worth, setting healthy boundaries, and making choices that align with your values and goals. When you respect yourself, you are better equipped to demand respect from others.
  • Respect in Leadership: Leaders who lead with respect rather than fear tend to inspire loyalty and commitment among their followers. They encourage teamwork, inclusivity, and innovation by valuing the contributions of each team member.
  • Resolving Conflicts: Respect is a powerful tool in resolving conflicts peacefully. It involves active listening, empathy, and a willingness to compromise. When individuals approach conflicts with respect, they are more likely to find mutually beneficial solutions.
  • Impact on Mental Health: A lack of respect can lead to feelings of isolation, low self-esteem, and anxiety. On the other hand, experiencing respect can improve mental health by creating a supportive and nurturing environment.
  • Respect for Future Generations: Practicing respect today has a lasting impact on future generations. By teaching children and young people about respect, we pass on the values and behaviors that can create a better world for them to inherit.
  • Respect for Animals: Respect extends to the treatment of animals. Treating animals with kindness and ensuring their well-being is not only an ethical responsibility but also reflects our commitment to a compassionate society.

In conclusion, understanding and practicing respect is not just a moral duty but a vital element in building harmonious societies. Respect transcends boundaries, fosters empathy, and fuels positive interactions. By valuing the dignity and rights of individuals, we create an atmosphere where cooperation, tolerance, and personal growth can thrive. As we embark on our journey of learning and growth, let respect be our guiding principle, shaping a better world for all

Twitter

Essay Generator

Text prompt

  • Instructive
  • Professional

Generate an essay on the importance of extracurricular activities for student development

Write an essay discussing the role of technology in modern education.

Home — Essay Samples — Life — Respect — The Significance of Respect in a Relationship

test_template

The Significance of Respect in a Relationship

  • Categories: Being a Good Person Respect

About this sample

close

Words: 639 |

Published: Sep 1, 2023

Words: 639 | Page: 1 | 4 min read

Image of Dr. Oliver Johnson

Cite this Essay

Let us write you an essay from scratch

  • 450+ experts on 30 subjects ready to help
  • Custom essay delivered in as few as 3 hours

Get high-quality help

author

Verified writer

  • Expert in: Life

writer

+ 120 experts online

By clicking “Check Writers’ Offers”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy . We’ll occasionally send you promo and account related email

No need to pay just yet!

Related Essays

1 pages / 316 words

1 pages / 629 words

3 pages / 1204 words

4 pages / 1894 words

Remember! This is just a sample.

You can get your custom paper by one of our expert writers.

121 writers online

Still can’t find what you need?

Browse our vast selection of original essay samples, each expertly formatted and styled

Related Essays on Respect

Respect is a fundamental value that underpins our interactions with others and our engagement with society as a whole. It serves as a cornerstone for positive relationships and plays a pivotal role in promoting social justice [...]

Respect is a fundamental value that should be upheld in all aspects of life. It is essential to treat others with respect, regardless of their background, beliefs, or opinions. In this essay, we will explore the importance of [...]

Respect plays a role in everyone’s everyday life. When we go to school we should show respect to all people. When we go home we should show respect to our parents and siblings. We should show respect to all of our family members [...]

Respect is a fundamental value in the military, forming the bedrock upon which discipline, cohesion, and honor are built. This essay delves into the concept of military respect, exploring its significance, manifestations, and [...]

Nearly anything will earn you respect in the eyes of someone. But only certain things will earn you respect in the eyes of those who are respected. It’s that simple. So, true respect is not earned of injuring oneself or breaking [...]

Creating a desire to respect the law is a vital step to building a civilised community. In order for the laws created by the government to be respectable, they must be aligned with our natural laws. St. Thomas Aquinas’ theory of [...]

Related Topics

By clicking “Send”, you agree to our Terms of service and Privacy statement . We will occasionally send you account related emails.

Where do you want us to send this sample?

By clicking “Continue”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy.

Be careful. This essay is not unique

This essay was donated by a student and is likely to have been used and submitted before

Download this Sample

Free samples may contain mistakes and not unique parts

Sorry, we could not paraphrase this essay. Our professional writers can rewrite it and get you a unique paper.

Please check your inbox.

We can write you a custom essay that will follow your exact instructions and meet the deadlines. Let's fix your grades together!

Get Your Personalized Essay in 3 Hours or Less!

We use cookies to personalyze your web-site experience. By continuing we’ll assume you board with our cookie policy .

  • Instructions Followed To The Letter
  • Deadlines Met At Every Stage
  • Unique And Plagiarism Free

respect begets respect meaning essay

By providing an email address. I agree to the Terms of Use and acknowledge that I have read the Privacy Policy .

Respect begets respect

Dear President Duterte,

It is a basic Filipino right to have freedom of expression, and also that everyone’s rights must be respected. As you are looked up to as a role model in our country, we believe that respecting these rights should go both ways.

We respect that you have these views and opinions about our faith. But, although we all have the right to freedom of expression, it is still important to remember that we must uphold respect for others and be more vigilant about what we say.

We understand that you have your own opinion on our religion because you see us from an outsider’s point of view. In the same way, we too, are outsiders to your beliefs, yet we continue to uphold our respect toward you. Your generalizations and comments regarding the leaders of our religion make your position as President questionable.

We acknowledge that your duty as our President comes with a lot of pressure and stress. However, we believe that having an open mind toward the different cultures and beliefs of Filipinos would help unite our country amid our diversity. President Duterte, please don’t take this matter lightly as it deals with the beliefs of the people who look up to you.

ISABELLE MARTINNE I. CRISOLOGO, MARIA ELENA TRINIDAD S. DACO, LIANDRA ELISE C. ESPINOSA, ARIANNA SOFIA D.C. ROSAS, DIANE ANDRE M. VELASCO, Grade 12, Paref Woodrose School

Subscribe to our daily newsletter

pdi

Subscribe to our opinion columns

Disclaimer: Comments do not represent the views of INQUIRER.net. We reserve the right to exclude comments which are inconsistent with our editorial standards. FULL DISCLAIMER

© copyright 1997-2024 inquirer.net | all rights reserved.

We use cookies to ensure you get the best experience on our website. By continuing, you are agreeing to our use of cookies. To find out more, please click this link.

Home / Essay Samples / Life / Respect / The Meaning And Importance Of Respect

The Meaning And Importance Of Respect

  • Category: Education , Life
  • Topic: College Students , Respect

Pages: 1 (527 words)

Views: 1937

  • Downloads: -->

--> ⚠️ Remember: This essay was written and uploaded by an--> click here.

Found a great essay sample but want a unique one?

are ready to help you with your essay

You won’t be charged yet!

Adversity Essays

Kindness Essays

Empathy Essays

Inspiration Essays

Hope Essays

Related Essays

We are glad that you like it, but you cannot copy from our website. Just insert your email and this sample will be sent to you.

By clicking “Send”, you agree to our Terms of service  and  Privacy statement . We will occasionally send you account related emails.

Your essay sample has been sent.

In fact, there is a way to get an original essay! Turn to our writers and order a plagiarism-free paper.

samplius.com uses cookies to offer you the best service possible.By continuing we’ll assume you board with our cookie policy .--> -->